Skip to main content

Full text of "The Act of Creation, Arthur Koestler.pdf (PDFy mirror)"

See other formats


I 



THE ACT OF CREATION 

In this major and long-awaited study Arthur Koestler advances the theory that 
all creative activities — the conscious and unconscious processes underlying 
artistic originality, scientific discovery, and comic inspiration—have a basic 
pattern in common, which he attempts to define. He calls it 'bisodative* thinking 
—a word he coined to distinguish the various routines of associative thinking 
£coni die creative leap which connects previously unconnected frames of reference 
and nukes us experience reality on several planes at once. He also suggests that 
phenomena analogous to creativity are manifested in various ways on various 
level* of the animal kingdom, from flatworms to chimpanzees, if the experi- 
menter know* how to look for them. The dog trained by Pavlovian methods is 
given a* link dunce to display originality as the human robots of Brave New 
iVM. But under appropriate conditions, man and animal are shown to possess 
umuspected creative resources. 

"Hie problem of creativity is fundamental to the assessment of man's condition. 
The duiiuiunt trend in the last fifty years of academic psychology was to take a 
view oi mm wliich reduced him to the status of a conditioned automaton. *I 
believe', Koestler writes, 'that view to be depressingly true— but only up to a 
point. The argument of this book starts at the point where it ceases to be true. 
TWre are two ways of escaping our more or less automatized routines of thinking 
md behaving. The first is the plunge into dreaming or dream-like states, where 
tik" rule* of rational thinking arc suspended. The other way is also an escape — 
dotn boredom, ^agnation, intellectual predicaments and emotional frustrations 

but an escape in the opposite direction; it is signalled by the spontaneous flash 
of iinijtht wliich show* a familiar situation or event in a new light' 

Most of the time man is a slave of Ms habits. Habit and originality are opposite 
jwlci of his nature; Koestler attempts to show that they also reflect basic principles 
whkh can be traced in different guises on all levels of the organic hierarchy. In 
Book One of this volume, The art of Discovery and the Discoveries of Art', 
he analyses the 'bisociativc* process— the way the mind of genius works in the 
fcicucc* and art?. This part is written for the general reader without scientific 
background In Book Two, 'Habit and Originality', he supplies the wider, 
icientific frame-work on which the theory rests; this part presupposes a closer 
Acquaintance with the biological sciences and current trenCs in experimental 
p>>vhology. Even here, however, he writes with such lucidity that the reader will 
be irresistibly led on to follow through his arguments. 

To quote from the Foreword of Professor Sir Cyril Burt: It is not merely a 
lugitly original contribution to present-day psychology. It is also a richly 
documented study in the history of scientific discovery and an essay in the 
analysis of literary and artistic creation. . . . Mr. Koesder's book will at once 
take its place as a classic among recent contributions to the science of the human 
mind,* 



Also by Arthur Koestler 



Novels 

THE GLADIATORS 
DARKNESS AT NOON 
ARRIVAL. AND DEPARTURE 
THIEVES IN THE NIGHT 
THE AGE OF LONGING 

Autobiography 

DIALOGUE WITH DEATH 

SCUM OF THE EARTH 

ARROW IN THE BLUE 

THE INVISIBLE WRITING 

THE GOD THAT FAILED (with Others) 

Essays 

THE YOGI AND THE COMMISSAR 
INSIGHT AND OUTLOOK 
PROMISE AND FULFILMENT 
THE TRAIL OF THE DINOSAUR 
REFLECTIONS ON HANGING 
THE SLEEPWALKERS 
THE LOTUS AND THE ROBOT 
SUICIDE OF A NATION? (edit.) 

Theatre 

TWILIGHT BAR 



ARTHUR KOESTLER 



Hutchinson of london 



PiUXCtHISrSON Sc CO. (Publishers) LTD 
17&—202 Great Portland Street, London, W.i 



London. jMLelbourxie Sydney 
Auckland Bombay Toroiato 
Johannesburg ISTew York 

-A- 

First published IQ64 



<g> Arthur ICoestler 1964 

This book has been set in ttembo type face. It has 
been printed tit Great Uritair* by TTie Anchor JPress, 
JLtd. 9 in Tip tree* JBssex, on Antique Wove paper- 



CONTENTS 



★ 

Foreword by Professor Sir Cyril Burt 
Author's Preface 

BOOK ONE 

THE ART OF DISCOVERY 
AND THE DISCOVERIES OF ART 

★ 

PART ONE 

THE JESTER 

I THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 

The Triptych— The Laughter Reflex— The Paradox o. 
Laughter — The Logic of Laughter: A First Approach — 
Matrices and Codes — Hidden Persuaders — Habit and 
Originality — Man and Machine 

II LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 

Aggression and Identification — The Inertia of Emotion — 
The Mechanism of Laughter — The Importance of not being 
Earnest 

III VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 

Pun and Witticism — Man and Animal — Impersonation — 
The Child-Adult— The Trivial and the Exalted— Carica- 
ture and Satire — The Misfit — The Paradox of the Centipede 
— Displacement — Coincidence — Nonsense — Tickling — The 
Clown — Originality, Emphasis, Economy 



IV FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY ^ ( 87 
Explosion and Catharsis — 'Seeing the Joke* and 'Solving 
the Problem* — The Creation of Humour— Paradox and 
Synthesis — Summary 



PART TWO 

THE SAGE 

V MOMENTS OF TRUTH 101 
The Chimpanzee and the Stick — Archimedes — Chance and 
Ripeness — Logic and Intuition — Summary 

VI THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 121 
1. The Printing Press — 2. Gravity and the Holy Ghost — 
3. Evolution through Natural Selection 

VII THINKING ASIDE 145 
Limits of Logic — The Unconscious before Freud — The 
Mechanization of Habits — Exploring the Shallows — The * 
'Hooked Atoms of Thought' — Exploring the Deeps — The 
Word and the Vision — The Snares of Language 

VHI UNDERGROUND GAMES 178 
The Importance of Dreaming — Concretization and Sym~ 
bolization — Punning for Profit — The Benefits of Impersona- 
tion — Displacement — Standing on One's Head — Analogy 
and Intuition — Summary 

DC THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 212 
False Inspirations — Premature Linkages — Snowblindness — 
Gradual Integrations — The Dawn of Language — Summary 

X THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 224 
Separations and Reintegrations — Twenty-six Centuries of 
Science — Creative Anarchy — 'Connect, Always Connect' 
—Tfie Thinking Cap— The Pathology of Thought- 
Limits of Confirmation — Fashions in Science — Boundaries 
of Science — Summary 

XI SCIENCE AND EMOTION 255 
Three Character-Types— Magic and Sublimation — The 
Boredom of Science — Summary 



CONTENTS 



9 



PART THREE 

THE ARTIST 
A. THE PARTICIPATORY EMOTIONS 

XII THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 271 
Laughter and Weeping — Why do we Weep? — Raptness 
— Mourning — Relief— Pity — Self-Pity — Summary 

XIII PARTNESS AND WHOLENESS 285 
Stepchildren of Psychology — The Concept of Hierarchy 

XIV ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 292 



B. VERBAL CREATION 

XV ILLUSION 301 
The Power of Illusion — The Value of Illusion — The 
Dynamics of Illusion — Escape and Catharsis — Identification 

and Magic — The Dawn of Literature 

XVI RHYTHM AND RHYME 311 
Pubation — Measure and Meaning — Repetition and Affinity 

— Compulsive Punning — Coaxing the Unconscious 

XVII IMAGE 

The Hidden Analogy — Emotive Potentials — The Picture- 320 
strip — On Law and Order — On Truth and Beauty 

XVIII INFOLDING 333 
Originality and Emphasis — Economy — The Last Veil — 
Summary 

XIX CHARACTER AND PLOT 345 
Identification — Phantoms and Images — Conflict — Integra- 
tions and Confrontations — Archetypes — Cataloguing Plots — 
Puppets and Strings 

XX THE BELLY OF THE WHALE 358 
The Night Journey— The Guilt of Jonah— The Root and 

the Flower — The Tightrope 



10 



CONTENTS 



C. VISUAL CREATION 

XXI MOTIF AND MEDIUM 3<56 
Looking at Nature — Pigment and Meaning — The Two En- 
vironments — Visual Inferences — Codes of Perception — Con- 
vention and Creation 

XXII IMAGE AND EMOTION 383 
Virtues of the Picture Postcard — Taste and Distaste — Motion 

and Rest— Ascending Gradients — Summary 

XXIII ART AND PROGRESS 393 
Cumulative Periods — Stagnation and Cross-Fertilization — 
Statement and Implication 

XXIV CONFUSION AND STERILITY 400 
The Aesthetics of Snobbery — The Personal Emanation — 

The Antiquarian Fallacy — The Comforts of Sterility 



BOOK TWO 

HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 
* 

Introduction 413 

I PRENATAL SKILLS 415 
Structure and Function — The Cell-Matrix— Nucleus and 
Cytoplasm — Regulative and Mosaic Development — 
Organizers ana Inducers — Summary 

II THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 430 
Development of the Nervous System — Locomotor Hier- 
archies — The Goldfish and the Crab — Shuffling the Sala- 
manders Limbs — Limits of Control 

EI DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERA- 
TIVE POTENTIAL 447 
Acting and Reacting — What is Equilibrium? — Super- 
Elasticity and Regenerative Span — Physiological Isolation 

IV RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 454 
Structural Regenerations — Reversed Gradients — The Dangers 
of Regression — 'Routine Regenerations* — Reorganizations of 



CONTENTS 



Function — Reculer sans Sauter — Regeneration and Psycho- 
therapy — The Routine of Dreaming — Regeneration and 
Creativity — Regeneration and Evolution 

V PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION 

VI CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 

The Genetics of Behaviour — Instinct and Learning — Tin- 
bergens Hierarchy — Appetitive Behaviour and Consum- 
mately Act — Leerlauf and Displacement — Instinct and 
Originality 

VII IMPRINTING AND IMITATION 

The 'Following-response' — Bird-song and Parrot-talk — 
Untapped Resources 

VIII MOTIVATION 

Retrospect — Decline of the Reflex — Hunger, Fear, and 
Curiosity — The Exploratory Drive 

IX PLAYING AND PRETENDING 

Diffiadties of Definition — The Ludic and the Ludicrous 

X PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 

Screening the Input — Stripping the Input — Dismantling 
and Reassembling — 'Coloured Filters 1 — A Digression on 
Engrams — Tracing a Melody — Conditioning and Insight in 
Perception — Abstract and Picture-strip — Learning to See 
— Knowing and Seeing — Levels of Memory — Image and 
Meaning — Klangbild and Wortschatz — Perceptual and 
Conceptual Abstraction — Generalization, Discrimination, 
and Association — Recognition and Recall — Summary 

XI MOTOR SKILLS 

Learning Hierarchies — Summary: Rigidity and Freedom 

XII THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 

A Glance in Retrospect — The Denial of Creativity — The 
Advent of Gestalt — Conditioning and Empirical Induction 
— Do Insects have Insight? — The Controversial Rat — The 
Cat in the Box 

XIII THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 

More about Chimpanzees — Uniform Factors in Learning — 
Criteria of Insight Learning — Preconditions of Insight — 
The Ambiguities of Gestalt — Putting Two and Two To- 
gether 



CONTENTS 



XIV LEARNING TO SPEAK 592 
Intending and Saying — The Dawn of Symbol Consciousness 

— Concepts and Labels — Ideation and Verbalization 

XV LEARNING TO THINK 606 
Abstraction, Discrimination, and Transfer — The Magic of 
Names — The Rise of Casuality — Explaining and Under-* 
standing — Tlie Dawn of Mathematics — The Dawn of 
Logics 

XVI SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 630 
Multi-dimensionality — The Experience of Free Choice — 
Degrees of Self-Awareness — Master-Switches and Releasers 

— Explicit Rules and Implicit Codes — Matrix Categories 

XVH ASSOCIATION 642 
Multiple Attunements — Types of Association 

XVIH HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 649 
Bridging the Gap — Searching for a Code — Degrees of 
Originality — Association and Bisodation 

APPENDIX I 
ON LOADSTONES AND AMBER 661 

APPENDIX II 
SOME FEATURES OF GENIUS 674 

I. THE SENSE OP WONDEB 674 

Aristotle on Motivation — The Leaders of the Revolution — 
— Newton, Monster and Saint — The Mysticism of Franklin 
— The Fundamentalism of Faraday — The Metaphysics of 
Maxwell — The Atheism of Darwin — The Faith of Pasteur 

2- INNOCENCE AND EXPERIENCE 703 

Precociousness — Scepticism and Credulity—Abstraction 
and Practicality — Multiple Potentials 

References 709 
Works Mentioned in this Book 717 

Acknowledgements 729 

Index 731 



1 



FOREWORD 
BY PROFESSOR SIR CYRIL BURT 

From time immemorial the gift of creativity has been venerated 
almost as if it were divine. There is more than a grain of truth in 
the romance of old Euhemerus, which relates how the gods and 
demigods of the ancient myths were really 'men of pre-eminent 
accomplishments deified out of flattery or gratitude'. Prometheus, the 
discoverer of fire, Vulcan, the first of the smiths, Hermes, the inventor 
of writing, Aesculapius, the founder of the most ancient school of 
medicine — each was welcomed into the classical Pantheon, much as 
today an outstanding scientist is elected to the Royal Society. In the 
Middle Ages the scientific pioneers — the leading alchemists, anatomists, 
and physicists — were almost as frequendy suspected of owing dieir 
miraculous knowledge and skill to the devil rather than to the deity. 
Even as late as the nineteenth century relics of the old superstitious awe 
still lingered on, translated into the biological jargon of the day. These 
intellectual prodigies, it was argued, were plainly endowed, not with 
supernatural, but certainly with superhuman powers: they must there- 
fore be either congenital sports or members of a rare anthropological 
species. Cynics, like Nordau and Lombroso, retorted that the much- 
vaunted superman was nothing but an unbalanced pathological freak, 
suffering from a hypertrophied cerebrum, or else the victim of some 
mental degeneracy, akin no doubt to the 'sacred disease* of epilepsy. 
'After all,* it was said, 'who could be more original than a lunatic, 
and what is more imaginative than a dream?' Perhaps the so-called 
genius is just a 'sleepwalker' whose dreams have hit upon the truth. 

As Mr, Koestler has so clearly indicated in his earlier volumes, in 
Insight and Outlook, and again in The Sleepwalkers, each of these views 
— once we have allowed for naivetes resulting from the system of 
thought in which it appeared — brings out an important aspect of the 
problem. It is therefore curious, as he goes on to observe, that not until 
the close of the nineteenth century were any systematic attempts made 

13 



FOREWORD 



to investigate the matter scientifically. By collecting pedigrees, 
measuring abilities, and applying statistical techniques, Sir Francis 
Galton proved, or thought he could prove, that the most important 
element in genius was simply an exceptionally high degree of the all- 
round mental capacity which every human being inherits — 'general 
intelligence'. And, reviving a proposal that originated with Plato, he 
contended that the surest way to manufacture geniuses would be to 
breed them, much as we breed prize puppies, Derby winners, and 
pedigree bulls. 

Galton, however, in his later years came to lay almost equal stress 
on certain supplementary qualitites, which he believed were likewise 
very largely the outcome of innate disposition. Of these 'special 
aptitudes' the most important was what he called 'fluency* — that is, 
'an unusual and spontaneous flow of images and ideas': the creative 
mind seemed 'always pullulating with new notions'. He added two 
further characteristics^-'receptivity' and 'intuition or insight', i.e. 
what James has called 'sagacity' and T. S. Eliot 'sense of fact' — 
characteristics that are said to distinguish the 'useful inventiveness' of 
the genius from the 'useless fancies of the eccentric and the crank'. 
McDougall, Galton' s most enthusiastic follower, discerned a fourth 
and still more elusive characteristic which he described as 'productive* 
or 'deviant association'. (What all these terms really cover is still a 
problem for intensive inquiry.) And then finally, as they all insist, 
there is also a motivational ingredient which Galton described by the 
somewhat ambiguous label — 'zeal': the enthusiasm of the genius over 
his problems keeps him working late into the night long after the 
clerks and the factory-workers have gone home to their evening 
relaxations. 

Galton's view, or rather the oversimplified version of it which 
appears in the popular textbooks, has of late been vigorously challenged 
by psychologists and educationists in America. To begin with, as 
might be expected in a democracy founded on the thesis that 'all men 
are created equal', many of them insist that genius is 'not born but 
made'. 'Give me', said Professor Watson* the aposde of behaviourism, 
'half a dozen healthy infants and my own world to bring them up in, 
and I will guarantee to turn each one of them into any kind of man you 
please — artist, scientist, captain of industry, soldier, sailor, beggar-man, 
or thief.' We may willingly grant that without the necessary environ- 
ment and the appropriate training even those who are most richly 
endowed by nature will fail to bring their gifts to full fruition. Heredity 



FOREWORD 



15 



at best can provide only the seed; the seed must be planted in suitable 
soil, tended, watered, and cultivated before it can mature and blossom. 
But the question then arises — what kind of soil is needed? What sort 
of a world would Watson have provided? What type of training or 
what special brand of education can we ourselves supply to develop 
these latent potentialities to the utmost? 

On all these points there is a conflict of doctrine which Mr. Koesder's 
arguments should do much to resolve. And there is a further point of 
disagreement. According to what has been called the British view, and 
contrary to the traditional notion, the difference between the creative 
genius and the plain man is not qualitative but merely quantitative: 
the so-called genius owes his outstanding achievements merely to the 
fortunate concurrence of a variety of factors, partly innate and partly 
environmental, all quite ordinary in themselves, but in his case develo- 
ped to an exceptional degree. During the past few years, however, an 
alternative view has been put forward in America, which maintains 
that there are two distinct types of intellectual ability, differing not in 
degree but in kind. The commoner intelligence tests, it is argued — 
those, for example, which are in regular use in our 11-plus examina- 
tion — measure only one rather superficial type of ability. There is a 
second, which Professor Guilford, as a result of his researches on 'high- 
level personnel', has suggested should be christened 'creativity'; and 
this in his opinion is 'far more fundamental'. As to what exactly is the 
nature of this second capacity we are still left rather in the dark. If you 
look up this useful word in the earlier editions of the Oxford English 
Dictionary you will fail to find it; and yet during the last two or three 
years it has attained something of the status of a glamour term among 
both English and American educationists. 

At the moment, therefore, the views of professional psychologists 
regarding 'the act of creation seem mainly to be in a state of bewildered 
confusion; and there is a crying need for an entirely fresh examination 
of the subject from top to bottom. However, psychologists are by no 
means the only people to maintain that 'creativity' (or whatever we 
like to term it) is in some sense or other an 'individual property'. In 
most civilized countries the importance attached to its results has been 
recognized by the laws of patent and of copyright. Both in war and in 
peace rewards have been offered and bestowed for what are known as 
'original inventions'. And the various legal arguments to which these 
proprietary rights have led may furnish some preHminary notion of 
what such phrases are intended to convey. First, there must be the 



16 FOREWORD 

basic idea or conception; secondly, the idea must be embodied in 
concrete and articulate form — a literary, musical, or dramatic work, 
the specifications for a machine, a manufacturing process, or a material 
product; thirdly, the outcome as thus embodied must be new; and 
finally — a point which, curiously enough, is often forgotten in psycho- 
logical and educational discussions — it must have value; the novelty 
must be a useful novelty. 

If there is such a thing as creativity as thus defined, then it is clear that 
dvilization must owe much, if not everything, to the individuals so 
gifted. The greater the number and variety of genuinely creative minds 
a nation can produce and cultivate, the faster will be its rate of progress. 
However, the pastime of debunking the 'cult of great men', which 
became so popular when Spencer and Buckle were laying the founda- 
tions of social and political theory, has once again become fashionable; 
and in these egalitarian days it requires some courage to pick up a pen 
and defend the concept of 'creative genius' against the onslaughts of 
the scientific sceptic. It is, so the critics assure us, not the gifted indi- 
vidual, but the spirit of the age and the contemporary trends of 
society — what Goethe called the Zeitgeist — that deserve the credit for 
these cumulative achievements; had Julius Caesar's grand-nephew 
succumbed to the illness which dogged his early youth, another 
son of Rome would have reorganized the State, borne the proud title 
of Augustus, and been duly deified. Had Copernicus, Kepler, and 
Newton fallen victims to the plague, one of their contemporaries would 
sooner or later have hit upon the scientific laws now coupled with their 
names. Certainly, Aut Caesar aut nullus is not an axiom to which the 
modern historian would subscribe either in these or any other in- 
stances. Yet to build up an empire on the ruins of a republic, to devise 
the theories which govern modern astronomy, would still have needed 
the vigour and the brain of an individual genius. And can anyone 
believe that, if William Shakespeare, like his elder sisters, had died in the 
cradle, some other mother in Stratford-upon-Avon or Stratford-atte- 
Bow would have engendered his duplicate before the Elizabethan 
era ended? 

However, it is scarcely profitable to discuss the relative importance 
of genetic constitution and social environment until we have first 
determined in what precisely the 'act of creation really consists. Here, 
as it seems to me, is one of the greatest gaps in the psychology of today. 
It is not an issue that can be satisfactorily solved by the tools and 
techniques which present-day psychologists commonly employ — 



FOREWORD 



17 



mental testing, experimental research, planned observations on men 
and animals. What is really needed is a systematic study carried out by 
one of those rare individuals who himself happens to possess this 
peculiar gift of creativity. And here, I venture to suggest, Mr. Koestler 
enjoys an advantage which few, if any, of the professional psycholo- 
gists who have touched upon the subject can genuinely claim. This 
does not mean that the book is just based on the author's 'introspec- 
tive reflections' about his methods of working as an essayist or novelist; 
on the contrary, he has been at pains to keep personal introspection, 
as the phrase is commonly understood, out of his chapters. The ground 
which he has covered and the evidence which he offers for his main 
conclusions are very much wider and more varied. He has in fact 
undertaken a new and comprehensive analysis of the whole problem; 
and is, so I believe, the first to make such an attempt. 

The impartial reader will scarcely need any independent witness to 
testify in advance that Mr. Koestler is admirably equipped for the 
task. Although most widely known as a creative artist in the field of 
general literature, he received his early training as a scientist at the 
University of Vienna. In the course of travels in both hemispheres he 
has visited most of the more progressive places of learning where 
psychological research is being carried out. His knowledge of the 
relevant literature, both psychological and non-psychological, is 
unusually extensive and fully up to date. Moreover, he has enjoyed 
the intimate friendship of some of the most original investigators in 
contemporary branches of science, from nuclear physics to experi- 
mental neurology; and he has thus been able to watch the daily 
workings of their minds. 

He begins with human creativity as exemplified in art, science, and 
literature; and to these fascinating topics the first half of his book is 
devoted. But he holds that creativity is by no means a peculiarly human 
gift; it is merely the highest manifestation of a phenomenon which is 
discernible at each successive level of the evolutionary hierarchy, from 
die simplest one-celled organism and the fertilized egg to the adult 
man and the highest human genius. It is, to adopt his phraseology, an 
Actualization of surplus potentials' — of capacities, that is to say, which 
are untapped or dormant under ordinary conditions, but which, when 
the conditions are abnormal or exceptional, reveal themselves in 
original forms of behaviour. This 'actualization he seeks to trace 
through morphogenesis, neurogenesis, and regeneration, and the 
various departures from simple instirictive behaviour in lowlier 



18 



FOREWORD 



creatures, up to the more 'insightful* forms of learning and of problem- 
solving exhibited by animals and man. At every stage, so he maintains, 
much the same 'homologue principles', derived from the hierarchical 
nature of the basic part-whole relation, can be seen to operate. This 
is of necessity the most technical and the most controversial part of his 
work, but it is also the most original and iUuminating. The outcome 
is a wide and an entirely novel synthesis; and Mr. Koestlers book will 
at once take its place as a classic among recent contributions to the 
science of the human mind. 

Technicalities are unavoidable, particularly when we pass from 
first-hand observation to explanatory interpretations couched in pre- 
cise biological, neurological, or psychological terms. Mr, Koestler 
has overcome the problem by relegating the more erudite and specu- 
lative parts of his exposition to the second half of his book; and in his 
prefatory remarks he suggests that those who feel more at home in the 
Arts and Humanities than in the Sciences can skip the more technical 
chapters. I hope, however, that all such readers will disregard this 
advice as merely a symptom of the authors own modesty. Psychology, 
more than any other branch of study, requires us to break down the 
barriers between the two cultures. In my youth psychology was 
regarded as a department of philosophy; and in my own university 
the only way of studying it was by registering as an Arts student and 
taking a degree in what were traditionally styled the Humaner 
Letters. But the true student of humanity must study, not the Humani- 
ties only, but the relevant branches of science as well. However, I 
suspect that my advice will turn out to be superfluous: most readers 
on reaching the end of Book One will find themselves so intrigued 
that they will be unable to resist pushing on to the next. 

On the other hand, the specialist may perhaps feel tempted to turn 
to the second half first of all: for, now that the pendulum has swung in 
the opposite direction, the royal road to psychology usually starts 
from elementary science. And, since the science taught in the pre- 
Imiinary stages is not only elementary but too often out of date, the 
intending psychologist is still more severely penalized. A scientific 
training may suffice for studying the behaviour of rats and robots. 
The student of human nature is nowadays too apt to forget that most 
of what we know about the mind of man is to be learnt from the 
writings not of scientists but of men of letters— the poets and the 
philosophers, the biographers and the historians, the novelists and the 
literary critics. I teH my own students to read Pope's Essay on Man as 



FOREWORD 



19 



well as Skinner's textbook on Science and Human Behaviour. But 
indeed the modern psychologist, like the youthful Bacon, needs to 
'take all knowledge for his province'. 

Many of those who find Mr. Koestler's arguments completely 
convincing on all essential points may nevertheless be inclined, as I 
myself, to query minor details here and there. My own hesitations 
arise, not so much from definable objections, but rather from doubts 
requiring further information or factual evidence which is at present 
unobtainable. Indeed, the most valuable feature of Mr. Koestler's book 
is that it suggests so many problems and provisional hypotheses for 
direct scientific inquiry in a deplorably neglected field. In particular it 
would be highly instructive to note how far the views he has indepen- 
dently reached resemble those already outlined, in their own cum- 
bersome language, by earlier British writers such as Bain, Ward, 
Stout, and McDougall, and, more important still, where precisely they 
differ. 

Meanwhile, his theory of the creative process carries with it a 
number of practical corollaries of first importance to the teacher and 
the social and educational reformer. Most of the earlier discussions of 
creativity were based on accounts of the intellectual processes of 
creative adults. It is, however, with the work of children in our 
schools that we ought really to begin. Viewed in the light of Mr. 
Koesders analysis, three salient questions call urgently for special 
investigation. How can we best detect the individuals who are en- 
dowed by nature with creative ability of this or that specific type? 
How are they to be trained and educated? And what are the existing 
social and scholastic barriers which hide or hinder the emergence of 
creative talent? Educational psychologists have of late woken up to 
the fact that the kind of examinations and intelligence tests which they 
still habitually employ tend to select the efficient learner and the 
verbal reasoner rather than inaiitive observers or constructive and 
critical thinkers. "With most of the mechanically scored tests handed 
out year by year, the child who gives an original answer, or hits on an 
alternative solution which the psychologist has missed (by no means 
a rare occurrence), is automatically marked wrong. Even when by 
some happy chance our methods of selection have picked out a 
potential inventor or a budding genius, we still have no notion how he 
should be encouraged and instructed so as to develop to the utmost 
his unusual latent powers. The problem has at last been recognized; 
but the remedy is still to seek. During the past year or two there have 



20 



FOREWORD 



been an increasing number of conferences and papers, especially in 
the United States, devoted to 'the identification of creative individuals' 
and 'the cultivation of creative talents'. There has, too, been a small but 
growing amount of experimental research. Nevertheless, apart from 
a few unconvincing speculations, varying with the prepossessions of 
each writer, there is as yet no sound psychological basis either for the 
theorise or the practitioner. Mr. Koestler's eclectic survey is thus as 
timely in its appearance as it is far-reaching in its implications. It 
supplies a fertile set of premisses from which the practical teacher 
as well as the psychological research-worker can reap a rich harvest of 
fruitful ideas. 

But his book is not merely a highly original contribution to present- 
day psychology. It is also a richly documented study in the history of 
scientific discovery and an essay in the analysis of literary and artistic 
creation. It will, therefore, present an irresistible challenge, and should 
appeal, not only to psychological or educational specialists, but also to 
every cultivated reader who is interested in 'the proper study of 
mankind'. 




AUTHOR'S PREFACE 

The first part of this book proposes a theory of the act of creation 
— of the conscious and unconscious processes underlying 
scientific discovery, artistic originality, and comic inspiration. 
It endeavours to show that all creative activities have a basic pattern in 
common, and to outline that pattern. 

The aim of Book Two is to show that certain basic principles operate 
throughout the whole organic hierarchy — from the fertilized egg to 
the fertile brain of the creative individual; and that phenomena analo- 
gous to creative originality can be found on all levels. 

Anyone who writes on a complex subject must learn that he cannot 
aim one arrow at two targets. Book One is aimed at the general reader; 
some of the chapters in Book Two presuppose a closer acquaintance 
with current trends in biology and experimental psychology, and are 
rather technical. There is an unavoidable difference in style between the 
two parts: in the first I avoided pedantry at the cost of occasional lapses 
into a loose terminology; in the second this was not possible. Readers 
who find certain passages in the second part too technical can safely skip 
them and pick up the thread later on without losing sight of the general 
idea. Its leitmotifs are restated on various levels throughout the book. 

It may seem a presumptuous undertaking to inquire into the bio- 
logical origins of mental creativity when we are still unable to define 
the chemistry of a simple muscle twitch. But often in the history of 
ideas we find two opposite methods at work: the 'downward* approach 
from the complex to the elementary, from the whole to its component 
parts, and the 'upward' approach from part to whole. The emphasis on 
cither of these methods may alternate according to philosophical 
fashion, until they meet and merge in a new synthesis. It would have 
been as impossible to build theoretical physics on a foundation of its 
elementary particles (which turn out to be more and more bafBing) 
as it has proved impossible to build a theory of psychology on 'ele- 
mentary reflexes' and 'atoms of behaviour'. Vice versa, without the 

21 



22 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



assumption that complex matter consisted of atomic parts, whatever 
they are, physics and chemistry could not have evolved. 

I have tried to combine both methods by choosing as my starting 
point a phenomenon which is at the same time complex and simple, 
in which a subde intellectual process is signalled by a gross physiological 
reflex: the phenomenon of laughter. Humour is an elusive thing, so is 
the rainbow; yet the study of coloured spectra provided clues to the 
elementary structure of matter. 

A preliminary outline of this theory was published in 1949 under the 
title Insight and Otttlook, It was intended as the first of two volumes, and 
its preface contained the optimistic sentence: * Volume Two is in 
preparation and will, it is hoped, appear twelve months after the first/ 

The twelve months have grown into fifteen years. Partly because I 
became involved with other subjects; but mainly because I felt dis- 
satisfied with that first attempt, and felt the need to base the theory on 
a broader foundation. I kept returning to it in between other books, 
but each time the broadening process necessitated an excursion into some 
related field and, as often happens, these excursions acquired a momen- 
tum of their own. One chapter on 'man's changing vision of the 
universe* grew into a separate book of more than six hundred pages; 1 
so did another chapter, on Eastern mysticism. 2 And when at last I 
felt ready to write that long-postponed second volume I found that I 
had to scrap the first and begin again at the beginning. The whole 
theoretical framework had to be revised and even the terminology 
changed. Readers acquainted with Insight and Outlook will notice, 
however, that I have taken over, or paraphrased, passages from it 
which seem to have weathered the time; to avoid tedium I have omitted 
quotation marks. I have also incorporated into the text extracts from 
lectures given at English and American universities, with the kind 
permission of the authorities concerned* 

Summaries appear at irregular intervals at the ends of chapters or 
sections where I felt that they might be helpful* Asterisks refer to text 
notes, index numbers to source references. 

I have no illusions about the prospects of the theory I am proposing: 
it will suffer the inevitable fate of being proven wrong in many, or 
most, details, by new advances in psychology and neurology. What I 
am hoping for is that it will be found to contain a shadowy pattern of 
truth, and that it may stimulate those who search for unity in the 
diverse manifestations of human thought and emotion. 



author's preface 



23 



I am deeply indebted to Professor Sir Cyril Burt, and to Professor 
Holger Hyden, University of Gothenburg, for reading the manuscript, 
for their corrections, criticisms and encouragement; to Professor 
Dennis Gabor, Imperial College, London, Dr. Alan McGlashan, St. 
George's Hospital, and Professor Michael Polanyi, Oxford, for many 
stimulating discussions on the subject of this book. My grateful thanks 
are further due to Dr. J. D. Cowan, Imperial College, for his criticism 
from the standpoint of Communication Theory; to Dr. Rodney 
Maliphant for surveying the literature on the psycho-physiology of 
weeping; to Dr. Christopher Wallis for compiling a bibliography on 
the same subject; and to Miss Edith Horsley for her patient and careful 
editorial work. 

London, December 1963 



BOOK ONE 
THE ART OF DISCOVERY 
AND THE DISCOVERIES OF ART 



PART ONE 

THE JESTER 



I 

THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 
The Triptych 

The three panels of the rounded triptych shown on the frontis- 
piece indicate three domains of creativity which shade into 
each other without sharp boundaries: Humour, Discovery, and 
Art. The reason for this seemingly perverse order of arrangement— the 
Sage flanked by the Jester and the Artist on opposite sides — will become 
apparent as the argument unfolds. 

Each horizontal line across the triptych stands for a pattern of 
creatiye^ac!iyity_which. is represented on all three panels; for instance: 
comic comparison — objective analogy — poetic image. The first is 
intended to make us laugh; the second to make us understand; the 
third to make us marvel. The logical pattern of the creative process is 
the same in all three cases; it consists in the discovery of hidden similari- 
ties. But the emotional climate is different in the three panels: the comic 
simile has a touch of aggressiveness; the scientist's reasoning by 
analogy is emotionally detached, i.e. neutral; the poetic image is sym- 
pathetic or admiring, inspired by a positive kind of emotion. I shall 
try to show that all patterns of creative activity are tri-valent: they can 
enter the service of humour, discovery, or art; and also, that as we 
travel across the triptych from left to right, the emotional climate 
changes by gradual transitions from aggressive to neutral to sym- 
pathetic and ldentdficatory^-or, to put it another way, from *ah 
absurd through an abstract to a tragic or lyric ykw of existence. This 
may look like a basketful of wild generalizations but is meant only as a 
first indication of the direction in which the inquiry will move. 

The panels on the diagram meet in curves to indicate that there are 
no clear dividing lines between them. The fluidity of the boundaries 
between Science and Art is evident, whether we consider Architec- 
ture, Cooking, Psychotherapy, or the writing of History. The mathe- 
matician talks of 'elegant' solutions, the surgeon of a 'beautiful' 

27 



28 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



operation, the literary critic of 'two-dimensional' characters. Science 
is said to aim at Truth, Art at Beauty; but the criteria of Truth (such 
as verifiability and refutability) are not as clean and hard as we tend to 
believe, and the criteria of Beauty are, of course, even less so. A glance 
at the chart on p. 332 will indicate that we can arrange neighbouring 
provinces of science and art in series which show a continuous gradient 
from 'objective' to 'subjective', from 'verifiable truth' to 'aesthetic 
experience'. One gradient, for instance, leads from the so-called exact 
sciences like chemistry through biochemistry to biology, then through 
medicine — which is, alas, a much less exact science — to psychology, 
through anthropology to history, through biography to the biographi- 
cal novel, and so on into the abyss of pure fiction. As we move along 
the sloping curve, the dimension of 'objective verifiability' is seen to 
cUminish steadily, and the intuitive or aesthetic dimension to increase. 
Similar graded series lead from construction engineering through 
architecture and interior design to the hybrid 'arts and crafts' and 
finally to the representative arts; here one variable of the curve could 
be called 'utility', the second 'beauty'. The point of this game is to 
show that regardless of what scale of values you choose to apply, you 
will move across a continuum without sharp breaks; there are no 
frontiers where the realm of science ends and that of art begins, and 
the uomo universale of the Renaissance was a citizen of both. 

On the other side of the triptych the boundaries between discovery 
and comic invention are equally fluid—as the present chapter will show 
— although at first sight this is less obvious to see. That the Jester 
should be brother to the Sage may sound like blasphemy, yet our 
language reflects the close relationship: the word 'witticism' is derived 
from *wit' in its original sense of ingenuity, inventiveness.* Jester and 
savant must both 'live on their wits'; and we shall see that the Jester's 
riddles provide a useful back-door entry, as it were, into the inner 
workshop of creative originality. 

The Laughter Reflex 

Laughter is a reflex. The word reflex, as Sir Charles Sherrington said, 
is a useful fiction. However much its definitions and connotations 
,, differ according to various schools — it has in fact been the central 
fead^pund of psychology for the last fifty years— no one is likely 
io; 4u#|^ w|th the statement that we are the more justified to call an 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



29 



organism's behaviour 'reflex* the more it resembles the action of a 
mechanical slot-machine; that is to say, the more instantaneous, 
predictable, and stereotyped it is. We may also use the synonyms 
'automatic', 'involuntary', etc., which some psychologists dislike; 
they are in fact implied in the previous sentence. 

Spontaneous laughter is produced by the co-ordinated contraction 
of fifteen facial muscles in a stereotyped pattern and accompanied by 
altered breathing. The following is a description abridged from Sully's 
classic essay on the subject. 

Smiling involves a complex group of facial movements. It may 
suffice to remind the reader of such characteristic changes as the 
drawing back and slight lifting of the corners of the mouth, the 
raising of the upper lip, which partially uncovers the teeth, 
and the curving of the furrows betwixt the corners of the 
mouth and the nostrils (the naso-labial furrows). To these must be 
added the formation of wrinkles under the eye, which is a further 
result of the first movement . . . and the increased brightness of the 
eyes. 

These facial changes are common to the smile and the laugh, 
though in the more violent forms of laughter the eyes are apt to lose 
under their lachrymal suffusion the sparkle which the smile brings. 

We may now pass to the larger experience of the audible laugh. 
That this action is physiologically continuous with the smile has 

already been suggested How closely connected are smiling and 

moderate laughing may be seen by the tendency we experience 
when we reach the broad smile and the fully open mouth to start the 
respiratory movements of laughter. As Darwin and others have 
pointed out, there is a series of gradations from the faintest and most 
decorous smile up to the full explosion of the laugh, 

. . . The series of gradations here indicated is gone through, more 
or less rapidly, in an ordinary laugh. . . . The recognition of this 
identity of the two actions is evidenced by the usages of speech. We 
see in the classical languages a tendency to employ the same word for 
the two. . . . This is particularly clear in the case of the Latin ridere, 
which means to smile as well as to laugh, the form subridere being rare 
(Italian, ridere and sorridere; French rire and sourire; German lachen 
and lacheln). 

We may now turn to the distmguishing characteristics oflaughing; 
that is, the production of the familiar series of sounds .* 



30 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



But these do not concern us yet. The point to retain is the con- 
tinuity of the scale leading from the faint smile to Homeric laughter, 
confirmed by laboratory experiments. Electrical stimulation of the 
zygomatic major, the main lifting muscle of the upper lip, with currents 
of varying intensity, produces expressions ranging from smile to 
broad grin to the facial contortions typical of loud laughter. 2 Other 
researchers made films of tickled babies and of hysterics to whom 
tickling was conveyed by suggestion. They again showed the reflex 
swifdy increasing from the first faint facial contraction to paroxysms 
of shaking and choking — as the quicksilver in a thermometer, dipped 
into hot water, rapidly mounts to the red mark. 

These gradations of intensity not only demonstrate the reflex 
character of laughter but at the same time provide an explanation for 
the rich variety of its forms — from Rabelaisian laughter at a spicy joke 
to the rarefied smile of courtesy. But there are additional reasons to 
account for this confusing variety. Reflexes do not operate in a vacuum; 
they are to a greater or lesser extent interfered with by higher nervous 
centres; thus civilized laughter is rarely quite spontaneous. Amusement 
can be feigned or suppressed; to a faint involuntary response we may 
add at will a discreet chuckle or a leonine roar; and habit-formation 
soon crystallizes these reflex-plus-pretence amalgams into characteris- 
tic properties of a person. 

Furthermore, the same muscle contractions produce different 
effects according to whether they expose a set of pearly teeth or a 
toothless gap — producing a smile, a simper, or smirk. Mood also super- 
imposes its own facial pattern—hence gay laughter, melancholy smile, 
lascivious grin. Lastly, contrived laughter and smiling can be used as a 
conventional signal-language to convey pleasure or embarrassment, 
friendliness or derision. We are concerned, however, only with 
spontaneous laughter as a specific response to the comic; regarding 
which we can conclude with Dr. Johnson that 'men have been wise 
in very different modes; but they have always laughed in the same 
way*. 

The Paradox of Laughter 

I have taken pains to show that laughter is, in the sense indicated above, 
a true reflex, because here a paradox arises which is the starting point 
of our inquiry , Motor reflexes, usually exemplified in textbooks by 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



31 



knee-jerk or pupillary contraction, are relatively simple, direct res- 
ponses to equally simple stimuli which, under normal circumstances, 
function autonomously, without requiring the intervention of higher 
mental processes; by enabling the organism to counter disturbances of 
a frequently met type with standardized reactions, they represent 
eminently practical arrangements in the service of survival. But what 
is the survival value of the involuntary, simultaneous contraction of 
fifteen facial muscles associated with certain noises which are often 
irrepressible? Laughter is a reflex, but unique in that it serves no 
apparent biological purpose; one might call it a luxury reflex. Its only 
utilitarian function, as far as one can see, is to provide temporary 
relief from utilitarian pressures. On the evolutionary level where 
laughter arises, an element of frivolity seems to creep into a humour- 
less universe governed by the laws of thermodynamics and the survival 
of the fittest. 

The paradox can be put in a different way. It strikes us as a reasonable 
arrangement that a sharp light shone into the eye makes the pupil 
contract, or that a pin stuck into one's foot causes its instant with- 
drawal — because both the 'stimulus' and the response' are on the same 
physiological level. But that a complicated mental activity like the 
reading of a page by Thurber should cause a specific motor response 
on the reflex level is a lopsided phenomenon which has puzzled philoso- 
phers since antiquity. 

There are, of course, other complex intellectual and emotional activi- 
ties which also provoke bodily reactions — frowning, yawning, sweat- 
ing, shivering, what have you. But the effects on the nervous system 
of reading a Shakespeare sonnet, working on a mathematical problem, 
or listening to Mozart are diffuse and indefinable. There is no clear- 
cut predictable response to tell me whether a picture in the art gallery 
strikes another visitor as 'beautiful'; but there is a predictable facial 
contraction which tells me whether a caricature strikes him as 'comic*. 

Humour is the only domain of creative activity where a stimulus on a high 
level of complexity produces a massive and sharply defined response on the 
level of physiological reflexes. This paradox enables us to use the res- 
ponse as an indicator for the presence of that elusive quality, the 
comic, which we are seeking to define — as the tell-tale clicking of the 
geiger-counter indicates the presence of radioactivity. And since the 
comic is related to other, more exalted, forms of creativity, the back- 
door approach promises to yield some positive results. We all know 
that there is only one step from the sublime to the ridiculous; the more 



32 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



surprising that Psychology has not considered the possible gains which 
could result from the reversal of that step. 

The bibliography of Greig's Psychology of Laughter and Comedy, 
published in 1923, mentioned three hundred and sixty-three tides of 
works bearing partly or entirely on the subject — from Plato and 
Aristode to Kant, Bergson, and Freud. At the turn of the century 
T. A. Ribot summed up these attempts at formulating a theory of the 
comic: 'Laughter manifests itself in such varied and heterogeneous 
conditions . . . that the reduction of all these causes to a single one 
remains a very problematical undertaking. After so much work spent 
on such a trivial phenomenon, the problem is still far from being 
completely explained/ 3 This was written in 1896; since then only two 
new theories of importance have been added to the list: Bergson s 
Le Rire and Freud's Wit and its Relations to the Unconscious, I shall have 
occasion to refer to them.* 

The dimculty lies evidendy in the enormous range of laughter- 
producing situations — from physical tickling to mental titillation of 
the most varied kinds. I shall try to show that there is unity in this 
variety; that the common denominator is of a specific and specifiable 
pattern which is of central importance not only in humour but in all 
domains of creative activity. The bacillus of laughter is a bug difHcult to 
isolate; once brought under the microscope, it will turn out to be a 
yeast-like, universal ferment, equally useful in making wine or vinegar, 
and raising bread. 

The Logic of Laughter: A First Approach 

Some of the stories that follow, including the first, I owe to my late 
friend John von Neumann, who had all the makings of a humorist: 
he was a mathematical genius and he came from Budapest. 

Two women meet while shopping at the supermarket in the 
Bronx, One looks cheerful, the other depressed. The cheerful one 
inquires: 

"What's eating you?' 

'Nothing's eating me.* 

'Death in the family?' - 

*No, God forbid!* 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



33 



'Worried about money?' 

'No . . . nothing like that.' 

'Trouble with the kids?' 

'Well, if you must know, it's my little Jimmy.' 

'What's wrong with him, then?' 

'Nothing is wrong. His teacher said he must see a psychiatrist/ 
Pause. 'Well, well, what's wrong with seeing a psychiatrist?' 
'Nothing is wrong. The psychiatrist said he's got an Oedipus 
complex.' 

Pause. 'Well, well, Oedipus or Shmoedipus, I wouldn't worry so 
long as he's a good boy and loves his mamma.' 

The next one is quoted in Freud's essay on the comic. 

Chamfort tells a story of a Marquis at the court of Louis XIV who, 
on entering his wife's boudoir and finding her in the arms of a 
Bishop, walked calmly to the window and went through the motions 
of blessing the people in the street. 

'What are you doing?' cried the anguished wife. 

'Monseigneur is performing my % functions,' replied the Marquis, 
'so I am performing his.' 

Both stories, though apparently quite different and in their origin 
more than a century apart, follow in fact the same pattern. The 
Chamfort anecdote concerns adultery; let us compare it with a tragic 
treatment of that subject — say, in the Moor of Venice. In the tragedy 
the tension increases until the climax is reached: Othello smothers 
Desdemona; then it ebbs away in a gradual catharsis, as (to quote 
Aristotle) 'horror and pity accomplish the purgation of the emotions* 
(see Fig. i, a, on next page). 

In the Chamfort anecdote, too, the tension mounts as the story pro- 
gresses, but it never reaches its expected climax. The ascending curve 
is brought to an abrupt end by the Marquis* unexpected reaction, 
which debunks our dramatic expectations; it comes like a bolt out of 
the blue, which, so to speak, decapitates the logical development of the 
situation. The narrative acted as a channel directing the flow of emo- 
tion; when the channel is punctured the emotion gushes out like a 
liquid through a burst pipe; the tension is suddenly relieved and 
exploded in laughter (Fig. i, b): 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



35 



I said that this effect was brought about by the Marquis' unexpected 
reaction. However, unexpectedness alone is not enough to produce a 
comic effect. The crucial point about the Marquis* behaviour is that 
it is both unexpected and perfectly logical — but of a logic not usually 
applied to this type of situation. It is the logic of the division of labour, 
the quid pro quo, the give and take; but our expectation was that the 
Marquis' actions would be governed by a different logic or code of 
behaviour. It is the clash of the two mutually incompatible codes, or 
associative contexts, which explodes the tension. 

In the Oedipus story we find a similar clash. The cheerful woman's 
statement is ruled by the logic of common sense: if Jimmy is a good 
boy and loves his mamma there can't be much wrong. But in the 
context of Freudian psychiatry the relationship to the mother carries 
entirely different associations. 

The pattern underlying both stories is the perceiving of a situation or 
idea, L, in two self-consistent but habitually incompatible frames of reference, 
M 1 and M 2 (Fig. 2). The event L, in which the two intersect, is made 
to vibrate simultaneously on two different wavelengths, as it were. 
While this unusual situation lasts, L is not merely linked to one 
associative context, but bisociated with two. 

I have coined the term 'bisociation* in order to make a distinction 
between the routine skills of thinking on a single 'plane*, as it were, 
and the creative act, which, as I shall try to show, always operates on 




Figure 2 



3<S 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



more than one plane. The former may be called smgle-minded, the 
latter a double-minded, transitory state of unstable equilibrium where 
the balance of both emotion and thought is disturbed. The forms which 
this creative instability takes in science and art will be discussed later; 
first we must test the validity of these generalizations in other fields of 
the comic. 

At the time when John "Wilkes was the hero of the poor and 
lonely, an ill-wisher informed him gleefully: 'It seems that some of 
your faithful supporters have turned their coats.' 'Impossible,' 
Wilkes answered. 'Not one of them has a coat to turn.' 

In the happy days of La Ronde, a dashing but penniless young 
Austrian officer tried to obtain the favours of a fashionable courtesan. 
To shake off this unwanted suitor, she explained to him that her 
heart was, alas, no longer free. He replied politely: 'Mademoiselle, I 
never aimed as high as that.' 

'High' is bisociated with a metaphorical and with a topographical 
context. The coat is turned first metaphorically, then literally. In 
both stories the literal context evokes visual images which sharpen the 
clash. 

A convict was playing cards with his gaolers. On discovering that 
he cheated they kicked him out of gaol. 

This venerable chestnut was first quoted by Schopenhauer and has 
since been roasted over and again in the literature of the comic. It can 
be analysed in a single sentence: two conventional rules ('offenders 
are punished by being locked up' and 'cheats are punished by being 
kicked out'), each of them self-consistent, collide in a given situation 
— as the ethics of the quid pro quo and of matrimony collide in the 
Chamfort story. But let us note that the conflicting rules were merely 
implied in the text; by making them explicit I have destroyed the story's 
comic effect. 

Shortly after the end of the war a memorable statement appeared 
in a fashion article in the magazine Vogue: 

Belsen and Buchenwald have put a stop to the too-thin woman 
age, to the cult of undernourishment.* 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



37 



It makes one shudder, yet it is funny in a ghastly way, foreshadow- 
ing the 'sick jokes' of a later decade. The idea of starvation is bi- 
sociated with one tragic, and another, utterly trivial context. The 
following quotation from Time magazine 5 strikes a related chord: 

REVISED VERSION 

Across the first page of the Christmas issue of the Catholic Universe 
Bulletin, Cleveland's official Catholic diocesan newspaper, ran this 
eight-column banner head: 

It's a boy in Bethlehem. 

Congratulations God — congratulations Mary — congratulations 
Joseph/ 

Here the frames of reference are the sacred and the vulgarly pro- 
fane. A technically neater version — if we have to dwell on blasphemy 
— is the riposte which appeared, if I remember rightly, in the New 
Yorker: 

'We wanted a girV 

The samples discussed so far all belong to the class of jokes and 
anecdotes with a single point of culmination. The higher forms of 
sustained humour, such as the satire or comic poem, do not rely on 
a single effect but on a series of minor explosions or a continuous state 
of mild amusement. Fig. 3 is meant to indicate what happens when a 




Figure 3 



38 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



humorous narrative oscillates between two frames of reference — say, 
the romantic fantasy world of Don Quixote, and Sancho's cunning 
horse-sense. 

Matrices and Codes 

I must now try the reader's patience with a few pages (seven, to be 
exact) of psychological speculation in order to introduce a pair of 
related concepts which play a central role in this book and are indis- 
pensable to all that follows. I have variously referred to the two planes 
in Figs. 2 and 3 as 'frames of reference', 'associative contexts', 'types of 
logic', 'codes of behaviour', and 'universes of discourse'. Henceforth I 
shall use the expression 'matrices of thought' (and 'matrices of be- 
haviour') as a unifying formula. I shall use the word 'matrix' to denote 
any ability, habit, or skill, any pattern of ordered behaviour governed 
by a ' code of fixed rules. Let me illustrate this by a few examples on 
different levels. 

The common spider will suspend its web on three, four, and up to 
twelve handy points of attachment, depending on the lie of the land, 
but the radial threads will always intersect the laterals at equal angles, 
according to a fixed code of rules built into the spider's nervous system; 
and the centre of the web will always be at its centre of gravity. The 
matrix — the web-building skill — is flexible: it can be adapted to en- 
vironmental conditions; but the rules of the code must be observed 
and set a limit to flexibility. The spider's choice of suitable points of 
attachment for the web are a matter of strategy, depending on the en- 
vironment, but the form of the completed web will always be poly- 
gonal, determined by the code. The exercise of a skill is always under 
the dual control (a) of a fixed code of rules (which may be innate or ac- 
quired by learning) and (b) of a flexible strategy, guided by environ- 
mental pointers — the 'lie of the land'. 

As the next example let me take, for the sake of contrast, a matrix 
on the lofty level of verbal thought. There is a parlour game where 
each contestant must write down on a piece of paper the names of all 
towns he can think of starting with a given letter — say, the letter *L\ 
Here the code of the matrix is defined by the rule of the game; and the 
members of the matrix are the names of all towns beginning with 'U 
which the participant in question has ever learned, regardless whether 
at the moment he remembers them or not. The task before him is to 
fish these names out of his memory. There are various strategies for 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



39 



doing this. One person will imagine a geographical map, and then scan 
this imaginary map for towns with *L\ proceeding in a given direction 
— say west to east. Another person will repeat sub-vocally the syllables 
Li, La, Lo, as if striking a tuning fork, hoping that his memory circuits 
(Lincoln, Lisbon, etc.) will start to vibrate' in response. His strategy 
determines which member of the matrix will be called on to perform, 
and in which order. In the spider's case the 'members' of the matrix 
were the various sub-skills which enter into the web-building skill: 
the operations of secreting the thread, attaching its ends, judging the 
angles. Again, the order and manner in which these enter into action 
is determined by strategy, subject to the 'rules of the game' laid down 
by the web-building code. 

All coherent thinking is equivalent to playing a game according to a 
set of rules. It may, of course, happen that in the course of the parlour 
game I have arrived via Lagos in Lisbon, and feel suddenly tempted to 
dwell on the pleasant memories of an evening spent at the night-club 
La Cucaracha in that town. But that would be not playing the game', 
and I must regretfully proceed to Leeds. Drifting from one matrix to 
another characterizes the dream and related states; in the routines of 
disciplined thinking only one matrixes active at a time. 

In word-association tests the code consists of a single command, for 
instance 'name opposites'. The subject is then given a stimulus word — 
say, 'large' — and out pops the answer: 'small'. If the code had been 
'synonyms', the response would have been 'big' or 'tall', etc. Associa- 
tion tests are artificial simplifications of the thinking process; in actual 
reasoning the codes consist of more or less complex sets of rules and 
sub-rules. In mathematical thinking, for instance, there is a great array 
of special codes, which govern different types of operations; some of 
these are hierarchically ordered, e.g. addition — multiplication — ex- 
ponential function. Yet the rules of these very complex games can 
be represented in 'coded' symbols: x + y, or x.y or x y or x^/y, the 
sight of which will 'trigger off' the appropriate operation — as 
reading a line in a piano score will trigger off a whole series of very 
complicated finger-movements. Mental skills such as arithmetical 
operations, motor skills such as piano-playing or touch-typing, tend 
to become with practice more or less automatized, pre-set routines, 
which are triggered off by 'coded signals' in the nervous system — 
as the trainer's whistle puts a performing animal through its paces. 

This is perhaps the place to explain why I have chosen the ambiguous 
word 'code' for a key-concept in the present theory. The reason is 



40 



THB ACT OF CREATION 



precisely its nice ambiguity. It signifies on the one hand a set of rules 
which must be obeyed — like the Highway Code or Penal Code; and 
it indicates at the same time that it operates in the nervous system 
through coded signals' — like the Morse alphabet— which transmit 
orders in a kind of compressed 'secret language'. "We know that not 
only the nervous system but all controls in the organism operate in 
this fashion (starting with the fertilized egg, whose 'genetic code' 
contains the blue-print of the future individual. But that blue-print in 
the cell nucleus does not show the microscopic image of a little man; 
it is 'coded' in a kind of four-letter alphabet, where each letter is 
represented by a different type of chemical molecule in a long chain; 
see Book Two, I).* 

Let us return to reasoning skills. Mathematical reasoning is governed 
by specific rules of the game — multiplication, differentiation, integra- 
tion, etc. Verbal reasoning, too, is subject to a variety of specific codes: 
we can discuss Napoleon's defeat at Waterloo 'in terms of (a) historic 
significance, (b) military strategy, (c) the condition of his liver, (d) the 
constellation of the planets. We can call these 'frames of reference* or 
'universes of discourse' or 'associative contexts' — expressions which I 
shall frequently use to avoid monotonous repetitions of the word 
'matrix'. The jokes in the previous section can all be described as 
universes of discourse colliding, frames getting entangled, or contexts 
getting confused. But we must remember that each of these ex- 
pressions refers to specific patterns of activity which, though flexible, 
are governed by sets of fixed rules. 

A chess player looking at an empty board with a single bishop on it 
does not see the board as a uniform mosaic of black and white squares, 
but as a kind of magnetic field with lines of force indicating the bishops' 
possible moves: the board has become patterned, as in Fig. 4 a; Fig. 4 b 
shows the pattern of the rook. 

When one thinks of 'matrices' and 'codes' it is sometimes helpful to 
bear these figures in mind. The matrix is the pattern before you, rep- 
resenting the ensemble of permissible moves. The code which governs 
the matrix can be put into simple mathematical equations which con- 
tain the essence of the pattern in a compressed, 'coded' form; or it can 
be expressed by the word 'diagonals'. The code is the fixed, invariable 
factor in a skill or habit; the matrix its variable aspect. The two words 
do not refer to different entities, they refer to different aspects of the 
same activity. When you sit in front of the chessboard your code is 
the rule of the game determining which moves are permitted, your 



42 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



matrix is the total of possible choices before you. Lastly, the choice of 
the actual move among the variety of permissible moves is a matter 
of strategy, guided by the He of the land — the 'environment* of other 
chessmen on the board. We have seen that comic effects are produced 
by the sudden clash of incompatible matrices: to the experienced chess 
player a rook moving bishop wise is decidedly 'funny'. 

Consider a pianist playing a set-piece which he has learned by heart. 
He has incomparably more scope for 'strategy* (tempo, rhythm, 
phrasing) than the spider spinning its web. A musician transposing a 
tune into a different key, or improvising variations of it, enjoys even 
greater freedom; but he too is still bound by the codes of the diatonic 
or chromatic scale. Matrices vary in flexibility from reflexes and more 
or less automatized routines which allow but a few strategic choices, 
to skills of almost unlimited variety; but all coherent thinking and 
behaviour is subject to some specifiable code of rules to which its 
character of coherence is due— even though the code functions partly 
or entirely on unconscious levels of the mind, as it generally does. A 
bar-pianist can perform in his sleep or while conversing with the 
barmaid; he has handed over control to the automatic pilot, as it were. 



Hidden Persuaders 

Everybody can ride a bicycle, but nobody knows how it is done. Not 
even engineers and bicycle manufacturers know the formula for the 
correct method of counteracting the tendency to fall by turning the 
handlebars so that 'for a given angle of unbalance the curvature of 
each winding is inversely proportional to the square of the speed at 
which the cyclist is proceeding'. 6 The cyclist obeys a code of rules 
which is specifiable, but which he cannot specify; he could write on 
his number-plate Pascal's motto: 'Le coeur a ses raisons que la raison ne 
connait point! Or, to put it in a more abstract way: 

The controls of a skilled activity generally function below the level 
of consciousness on which that activity takes place. The code is a 
hidden persuader. 

This applies not only to our visceral activities and muscular skills, 
but also to the skill of perceiving the world around us in a coherent 
and meaningful manner. Hold your left hand six inches, the other 
twelve inches, away from your eyes; they will look about the same 
size, although the retinal image of the left is twice the size of the right. 



THE LOGIC -OF LAUGHTER 



43 



Trace the contours of your face with a soapy finger on the bathroom 
mirror (it is easily done by closing one eye). There is a shock waiting: 
the image which looked life-size has shrunk to half-size, like a head- 
hunter's trophy. A person walking away does not seem to become a 
dwarf— as he should; a black glove looks just as black in the sunlight 
as in shadow — though it should not; when a coin is held before the eyes 
in a tilted position its retinal projection will be a more or less flattened 
ellipse; yet we see it as a circle, because we know it to be a circle; and it 
takes some effort to see it actually as a squashed oval shape. Seemg is 
believing, as the saying goes, but the reverse is also true: knowing is 
seeing. 'Even the most elementary perceptions', wrote Bartlett, 7 'have 
the character of inferential constructions.' But the inferential process, 
which controls perception, again works unconsciously. Seeing is a 
skill, part innate, part acquired in early infancy.* The selective codes 
in this case operate on the input, not on the output. The stimuli im- 
pinging on the senses provide only the raw material of our conscious 
experience — the dooming, buzzing confusion' of William James; 
before reaching awareness the input is filtered, processed, distorted, 
interpreted, and reorganized m a series of relay-stations at various levels 
of the nervous system; but the processing itself is not experienced by 
the person, and the rules of the game according to which the controls 
work are unknown to him. 

The examples I mentioned refer to the so-called Visual constancies 9 
which enable us to recognize that the size, brightness, shape of objects 
remain the same even though their retinal image changes all the time; 
and to 'make sense 1 out of our sensations. They are shared by all people 
with normal vision, and provide the basic structure on which more 
personal 4 frames of perception* can be built. An apple looks different to 
Picasso and to the greengrocer because their visual matrices are different- 
Let me re.turn once more to verbal thinking. When a person dis- 
,cusses, saj, the problem of capital punishment he may do so 'in terms 
. of 1 social utility or religious morality or psychopathology. Each of 
these universes of discourse is governed by a complex set of rules, some 
of which operate on conscious, others on unconscious levels. The latter 
are axiomatic beliefs and prejudices which are taken for granted and 
implied in the code. Further implied, hidden in the space between the 
words, are the rules of grammar and syntax. These have mostly been 
learned not from textbooks but 'by ear', as a young gypsy learns to 
fiddle without knowing musical notation. Thus when one is engaged 
in ordinary conversation, not only do the codes of grammar and 



44 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



syntax, of courtesy and common-or-garden logic function uncon- 
sciously, but even if consciously bent on doing so we would find it 
extremely difficult to define these rules which define our thinking. For 
doing that we need the services of specialists — the semanticists and 
logicians of language. In other words, there is less difference between 
the routines of thinking and bicycle-riding than our self-esteem would 
make us believe. Both are governed by implicit codes of which we are 
only dimly aware, and which we are unable to specify.* 

Habit and Originality 

Without these indispensable codes we would fall off the bicycle, and 
thought would lose its coherence — as it does when the codes of normal 
reasoning are suspended while we dream. On the other hand, thinking 
which remains confined to a single matrix has its obvious limitations. 
It is the exercise of a more or less flexible skill, which can perform 
tasks only of a kind already encountered in past experience; it is not 
capable of original, creative achievement. 

We learn by assimilating experiences and grouping them into 
ordered schemata, into stable patterns of unity in variety. They enable 
us to cope with events and situations by applying the rules of the 
game appropriate to them. The matrices which pattern our percep- 
tions, thoughts, and activities are condensations of learning into habit. 
The process starts in infancy and continues to senility; the hierarchy of 
flexible matrices with fixed codes — from those which govern the 
breathing of his cells, to those which determine the pattern of his 
signature, constitute that creature of many-layered habits whom we 
call John Brown. When the Duke of Wellington was asked whether 
he agreed that habit was man's second nature he exclaimed: 'Second 
nature? It's ten times nature!' 

Habits have varying degrees of flexibility; if often repeated under 
unchanging conditions, in a monotonous environment, they tend to 
become rigid and automatized. But even an elastic strait-jacket is still 
a strait-jacket if the patient has no possibility of getting out of it. 
Behaviourism, the dominant school in contemporary psychology, is 
inclined to take a view of man which reduces him to the station of that 
patient, and the human condition to that of a conditioned automaton. 
I believe that view to be depressingly true up to a point. The argument 
of this book starts at the point where, I believe, it ceases to be true. 



THE LOGIC OP LAUGHTER 



45 



There are two ways of escaping our more or less automatized 
routines of thinking and behaving. The first, of course, is the plunge 
into drearning or dream-like states, when the codes of rational thinking 
are suspended. The other way is also an escape — from boredom, 
stagnation, intellectual predicaments, and emotional frustration — but 
an escape in the opposite direction; it is signalled by the spontaneous 
Hash of insight which shows a familiar situation or event in a new 
light, and elicits a new response to it. The bisociative act connects 
previously unconnected matrices of experience; it makes us 'under- 
stand what it is to be awake, to be living on several planes at once* (to 
quote T. S. Eliot, somewhat out of context). 

The first way of escape is a regression to earlier, more primitive 
levels of ideation, exemplified in the language of the dream; the 
second an ascent to a new, more complex level of mental evolution. 
Though seemingly opposed, the two processes will turn out to be 
mtamately related. 

Man and Machine 

When two^ independent matrices of perception or reasoning interact 
with each other the result (as I hope to show) is either a collision ending 
in laughter, or their fusion in a new intellectual synthesis, or their con- 
frontation in an aesthetic experience. The bisociative patterns found in 
any domain of creative activity are tri-valent: that is to say, the same 
pair of matrices can produce comic, tragic, or intellectually challenging 
effects. 

Let me take as a first example 'man' and 'machine' . A favourite 
trick of the coarser type of humour is to exploit the contrast between 
these two frames of reference (or between the related pair 'mind' and 
'matter'). The dignified schoolmaster lowering himself into a rickety 
chair and crashing to the floor is perceived simultaneously in two in- 
compatible contexts: authority is debunked by gravity. The savage, 
wistfully addressing the carved totem figure — 'Don't be so proud, I 
know you from a plum-tree' — expresses the same idea: hubris of mind, 
earthy materiality of body. The variations on this theme are inex- 
haustible: the person slipping on a banana skin; the sergeant-major 
attacked by diarrhoea; Hamlet getting the hiccoughs; soldiers march- 
ing like automata; the pedant behaving like a mechanical robot; the 
absent-minded don boiling his watch while clutching the egg, like a 
machine obeying the wrong switch. Fate keeps playing practical jokes 



46 THE ACT OF CREATION 

to deflate the victim's dignity, intellect, or conceit by demonstrating 
his dependence on coarse bodily functions and physical laws — by 
degrading him to an automaton. The same purpose is served by the 
reverse technique of making artefacts behave like humans: Punch and 
Judy, Jack-in-the-Box, gadgets playing tricks on their masters, hats in 
a gust of wind escaping the pursuer as if with calculated malice. 

In Henri Bergson's book on the problem of laughter this dualism 
of subde mind and inert matter ('the mechanical encrusted on the 
living') is made to serve as an explanation of all forms of the comic; 
whereas in the present theory it applies to only one variant of it among 
many others. Surprisingly, Bergson failed to see that each of the 
examples just mentioned can be converted from a comic into a tragic 
or purely intellectual experience, based on the same logical pattern — 
i.e. on the same pair of bisociated matrices — by a simple change of 
emotional climate. The fat man slipping and crashing on the icy pave- 
ment will be either a comic or a tragic figure according to whether the 
spectator's attitude is dominated by malice or pity: a callous schoolboy 
will laugh at the spectacle, a sentimental old lady may be inclined to 
weep. But in between these two there is the emotionally balanced 
attitude of the physician who happens to pass the scene of the mishap, 
who may feel both amusement and compassion, but whose primary 
concern is to find out the nature of the injury. Thus the victim of the 
crash may be seated in any of the three panels of the triptych. Don 
Quixote gradually changes from a comic into a puzzling figure if, 
instead of rehshing his delusions with arrogant condescension, I become 
interested in their psychological causes; and he changes into a tragic 
figure as detached curiosity turns into sympathetic identification — as I 
recognize in the sad knight my brother-in-arms in the fight against 
windmills. The stock characters in the farce — the cuckold, the miser, 
the stutterer, the hunchback, the foreigner — appear as comic, intel- 
lectually challenging, or tragic figures according to the different 
emotional attitudes which they arouse in spectators of different mental 
age, culture, or mood. 

The 'mechanical encrusted on the living' symbolizes the contrast 
between man's spiritual aspirations and his all-too-solid flesh subject 
to the laws of physics and chemistry. The practical joker and the clown 
specialize in tricks which exploit the mechanical forces of gravity and 
inertia to deflate his humanity. But Icarus, too, like the dinner guest 
whose chair collapsed, is the victim of a practical joke — the gods, 
instead of breaking the legs of his chair, have melted away his wings. 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



47 



The second appeals to loftier emotions than the first, but the logical 
structure of the two situations and their message is the same: whatever 
you fancy yourself to be you are subject to the inverse square law like 
any other lump of clay. In one case it is a comic, in the other a tragic 
message. The difference is due to the different character of the emotions 
involved (malice in the first case, compassionate admiration in the 
second); but also to the fact that in the first case the two frames of 
reference collide, exploding the tension, while in the second they 
remain juxtaposed in a tragic confrontation, and the tension ebbs away 
in a slow catharsis. The third alternative is the reconciliation and syn- 
thesis of the two matrices; its effect is neither laughter, nor tears, but 
the arousal of curiosity: just how is the mechanical encrusted on the 
living? How much acceleration can the organism stand, and how does 
zero gravity affect it? 

According to Bergson, the main sources of the comic are the mecha- 
nical attributes of inertia, rigidity, and repetitiveness impinging on life; 
among his favourite examples are the man-automaton, the puppet on 
strings, Jack-in-the-Box, etc. However, if rigidity contrasted with 
organic suppleness were laughable in itself, Egyptian statues and Byzan- 
tine mosaics would be the best jokes ever invented. If automatic 
repetitiveness in human behaviour were a necessary and sufficient 
condition of the comic there would be no more amusing spectacle 
than an epileptic fit; and if we wanted a good laugh we would merely 
have to feel a person's pulse or listen to his heart-beat, with its mono- 
tonous tick-tack. If we laugh each time a person gives us the impres- 
sion of being a thing' 8 there would be nothing more funny than a 
corpse. 

In fact, every one of Bergson's examples of the comic can be trans- 
posed, along a horizontal line as it were, across the triptych, into the 
panels of science and art. His homme-automate, man and artefact at the 
same time, has its lyric counterpart in Galatea — the ivory statue which 
Pygmalion made, Aphrodite brought to life, and Shaw returned to 
the comic domain. It has its tragic counterpart in the legends of Faust's 
Homunculus, the Golem of Prague, the monsters of Frankenstein; its 
origins reach back to Jehovah manufacturing Adam out of adamah, 
the Hebrew word for earth. The reverse transformation — life into 
mechanism — has equally rich varieties: the pedant whom enslavement 
to habit has reduced to an automaton is- comic because we despise him; 
the compulsion-neurotic is not, because we are puzzled and try to 
understand him; the catatonic patient, frozen into a statue, is tragic 



48 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



because we pity him. And so again back to mythology: Lot's wife 
turned into a pillar of salt, Narcissus into a flower, the poor nymph 
Echo wasting away until nothing is left but her voice, and her bones 
changed into rocks. 

In the middle panel of the triptych the homme-automate is the focal, 
or rather bi-focal, concept of all sciences of life. From their inception 
they treated, as the practical joker does, man as both mind and machine. 
The Pythagoreans regarded the body as a musical instrument whose 
soul-strings must have the right tension, and we still unwittingly refer 
to our mortal frame as a kind of stringed guitar when we speak of 
'muscle tone \ or describe John as 'good tempered'. The same bifocal 
view is reflected in the four Hippocratic 'humours' — which were both 
liquids of the body and moods of the spirit; and spiritus itself is, like 
pnewna, ambiguous, meaning also breath. The concept of catharsis 
applied, and still does, to the purgation of either the mind or the bowels. 
Yet if I were to speak earnesdy of halitosis of the soul, or of laxatives 
to the mind, or call an outburst of temper a humourrhage, it would 
sound ludicrous, because I would make the implicit ambiguities 
explicit for the purpose of maliciously contrasting them; I would tear 
asunder two frames of reference that our Greek forbears had managed 
to integrate, however tentatively, into a unified, psychosomatic view 
which our language still reflects. 

In modern science it has become accepted usage to speak of the 
'mechanisms' of digestion, perception, learning, and cognition, etc., 
and to lay increasing or exclusive stress on the automaton aspect of the 
homme-automate. The mechanistic trend in physiology reached its 
symbolic culmination at the beginning of the century in the slogan 
'Man a machine* — the programmatic tide of a once famous book by 
Jacques Loeb; it was taken over by behaviouristic psychology, which 
has been prominent in the Anglo-Saxon countries for half a century. 
Even a genial naturalist like Konrad Lorenz, whose King Solomons 
Ring has delighted millions, felt impelled to proclaim that to regard 
Newton and Darwin as automata was the only permissible view for 
*the inductive research worker who does not believe in miracles'. 9 
It all depends, of course, on what one's definition of a miracle is: 
Galileo, the ideal of all 'inductive research workers', rejected Kepler's 
theory that the tides were due to the moon's attraction as an 'occult 
fancy'. 10 The intellectual climate created by these attitudes has been 
summed up by Cyril Burt, writing about 'The Concept of Con- 
sciousness' (which behaviourists have banned, as another 'occult 



THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 



49 



fancy', from the vocabulary of science): 'The result, as a cynical on- 
looker might be tempted to say, is that psychology, having first 
bargained away its soul and then gone out of its mind, seems now, as 
it faces an untimely end, to have lost all consciousness.' 11 

I have dwelt at some length on Bergsons favourite example of the 
comic, because of its relevance to one of the leitmotifs of this book. 
The man-machine duality has been epitomized in a laconic sentence — 
'man consists of ninety per cent water and ten per cent minerals' — 
which one can regard, according to taste, as comic, intellectually 
challenging, or tragic. In the first case one has only to think of a 
caricature showing a fat man under the African sun melting away into 
a puddle; in the second, of the 'inductive research worker' bent over 
his test-tube; in the third, of a handful of dust. 

Other examples of Bergsons man-automaton need be mentioned 
only briefly. The puppet play in its naive Punch and Judy version is 
comic; the sophisticated marionette theatre is a traditional form of 
art; life-imitating contraptions are used in various branches of science 
and technology: from the dummy figures of dressmakers to the 
anatomical models in medical schools; from the artificial limbs of the 
orthopaedist to robots imitating the working of the nervous system 
(such as Grey Walter's electronic tortoises). In the metaphorical sense 
the puppet on strings is a timeless symbol, either comic or tragic, of 
man as a plaything of destiny — whether he is jerked about by the 
gods or suspended on his own chromosomes and glands. In the neutral 
zone between comedy and tragedy philosophers have been tireless in 
their efforts to reconcile the two conflicting aspects of the human 
puppet: his experience of free will and moral responsibility on the one 
hand; the strings of determinism, religious or scientific, on the other. 

An extreme variant of the puppet motif is Jack-in-the-Box, symbol 
of the stubborn, mechanical repetitiveness, but also of the indestruc- 
tibility, of life. Its opposite number is the legendary monster who 
instantly grows a new tentacle or head when the hero has cut it off; 
or the old woman in Raskolnikof 's dream who, after each stroke of 
the axe on her skull, turns round and laughs in his face. In the bio- 
logical sciences Jack-in-the-Box is a familiar figure, represented in all 
processes of the trigger-release type — the muscle-twitch, the epileptic 
fit, the 'sign-releasers' of the animal kingdom, whose symbolic 
message activates the springs of hopping mad or tenderly amorous, 
innate behaviour patterns. 



NOTES 



To p. 28. 'Wit' stems from witan, understanding; whose roots go back 
(via videre and eeSco) to the Sanskrit veda, knowledge. The German Wltz means 
both joke and acumen; it comes from wissen, to know; Wissenschaft — science, is 
a close kin to Fiirwitz and Aberwitz — presumption, cheek, and jest. French teaches 
the same lesson. Spirituet may either mean witty or spiritually profound; to 
amuse comes from to muse \a-muser), and a witty remark is a jeu d* esprit — a 
playful, mischievous form of discovery. 

The word 'jester', too, has a respectable ancestry. The chansons degeste played a 
prominent part in medieval literature from the eleventh to the fifteenth centuries. 
They were epics centred on heroic events; their name is derived from the Latin 
gesta : deeds, exploits. With the coming of the Renaissance, satire tended to re- 
place the epics of chivalry, and in the sixteenth century the heroic 'geste' turned 
into *jest\ 

To p. 32. A critical discussion of both theories can be found in Appendix I 
of Insight and Outlook. 

To p. 40. The choice of the term 'matrix* is less easy to explain. In an 
earlier version I used 'field' and 'framework', but 'field' is too vague, and 'frame' 
too rigid. 'Matrix' is derived from the Latin for womb and is figuratively used 
for any pattern or mould in which things are shaped and developed, or type is 
cast. Thus the exercise of a habit or skill is 'moulded' by its matrix. In mathematics, 
matrices are rectangular arrays of numbers capable of all sorts of magic; they can 
be subjected to various transformations without losing their identity — i.e. they 
are both 'flexible' and 'stable'. Also, matrices have a constant attached to them, 
called their 'determinant', which remains unaffected by any of these trans- 
formations. But the analogy between 'determinant' and 'code' is extremely loose 
and in more than one respect misleading. 

To p. 43. Congenitally blind patients, who acquire vision after surgical 
operations at a mature age, have great difficulties in recognizing patterns and 
faces, and in orienting themselves in space. Cf. Senden (1932), quoted by Hebb 
(1949). 

To p. 44. The dual concepts of matrices and codes were designed with one 
eye on psychology, the other on physiology. Their theoretical implications in 
this wider context are discussed in Book Two. 

The reader versed in experimental psychology will have been reminded by 
now of such old fnends from the Wurzburg School as Aufgabe, Einstellung, 
Bewusstseinstage; and of their Anglo-Saxon relatives: 'determining tendency', 
'expectancy*, 'task', 'schema' and 'set*. He will probably also remember that 
J.J. Gibson in a famous article (quoted by Humphrey, 1951, p. 105) listed some 
forty different meanings in which the word 'set' was used. I hope to show that 
'matrices' and 'codes' are concepts at the same time more precise, and of more 
general validity, than Aufgaben or 'sets'. 



50 



II 

LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 

The sudden bisociation of an idea or event with two habitually 
incompatible matrices will produce a comic effect, provided 
that the narrative, the semantic pipeline, carries the right kind 
of emotional tension. When the pipe is punctured, and our expectations 
are fooled, the now redundant tension gushes out in laughter, or is 
spilled in the gentler form of the sou-rire. 

Aggression and Identification 

Laugher, as the cliche has it, is 'liberating*, i.e. tension-relieving. 
Relief from stress is always pleasurable, regardless whether it was 
caused by hunger, sex, anger, or anxiety. Under ordinary circum- 
stances such relief is obtained by some purposeful activity which is 
appropriate to the nature of the tension. When we laugh, however, the 
pleasurable relief does not derive from a consummatory act which 
satisfies some specific need. On the contrary: laughter prevents the 
satisfaction of biological drives, it makes a man equally incapable of 
killing or copulating; it deflates anger, apprehension, and pride* The 
tension is not consummated — it is frittered away in an apparently 
purposeless reflex, in facial grimaces, accompanied by over-exertion 
of the breathing mechanism and aimless gestures. To put it the other 
way round: the sole function of this luxury reflex seems to be the dis- 
posal of excitations which have become redundant, which cannot be 
consummated in any purposeful manner. 

But why has the excitation suddenly become 'redundant*; and why is 
it discharged in laughter and not, say, in weeping — which is an equally 
'purposeless* activity? The answer to the second half of the question 

51 



52 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



seems obvious: the kind of excitation exploded in laughter has a 
different quality or chemical composition, as it were, from the emo- 
tions which overflow in tears. But the very obviousness of this answer 
is deceptive, for the attempt to define this difference in 'quality and 
composition* necessitates a new approach to the theory of human 
emotions. 

At first sight there seems to be a bewildering variety of moods in- 
volved in different types of humour. The practical joke is frankly 
aggressive; the lavatory jokes of children are scatological; blue jokes 
are sexual; the Charles Addams type of cartoon and the 'sick* joke 
play on feelings of horror and disgust; the satirist on righteous in- 
dignation. Moreover, the same type of semantic pipeline can be made 
to carry different types of fluid under varying degrees of pressure: for 
instance, 'they haven't got a coat to turn' and 'I never aimed as high 
as that' are both bisociations of metaphorical and direct meaning — 
jokes of the same logical pattern but with different emotional colour- 
ing. The more sophisticated forms of humour evoke mixed, and some- 
times contradictory, feelings; but whatever the mixture, it must con- 
tain one ingredient whose presence is indispensable: an impulse, how- 
ever faint, of aggression or apprehension. It may be manifested in the 
guise of malice, derision, the veiled cruelty of condescension, or merely 
as an absence of sympathy with the victim of the joke — a 'momentary 
anaesthesia of the heart', as Bergson put it. I propose to call this 
common ingredient the aggressive-defensive or self-asserting tendency — 
the reasons for choosing this clumsy term will be seen later on. In 
the subtler types of humour this tendency is so faint and discreet that 
only careful analysis will detect it, like the presence of salt in a well- 
prepared dish-— which, however, would be tasteless without it. 

It is the aggressive element, the detached malice of the parodist, 
which turns pathos into bathos, tragedy into comedy. It may be com- 
bined with affection, as in friendly teasing; in civilized humour aggres- 
sion is sublimated and often unconscious. But in jokes which appeal to 
children and primitives cruelty and boastful self-assertion are much in 
evidence, and the same is true of the historically earlier forms and 
theories of the comic. 'As laughter emerges with man from the mists of 
antiquity it seems to hold a dagger in its hand. There is enough brutal 
triumph, enough contempt, enough striking down from superiority 
in the records of antiquity and its estimates of laughter to presume that 
original laughter may have been wholly animosity/ 1 In the Old 
Testament there are (according to Mitchell 2 ) twenty-nine references to 



LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 



53 



laughter, out of which thirteen are linked with scorn, derision, 
mocking, or contempt, and only two are 'born out of a joyful and 
merry heart'. A survey among American schoolchildren between the 
ages of eight and fifteen led to the conclusion (which could hardly have 
surprised anybody) that 'mortification or discomfort or hoaxing of 
others very readily caused laughter, while a witty or funny remark 
often passed unnoticed'. 3 

Among the theories of laughter that have been proposed since the 
days of Aristotle, the 'theory of degradation' appears as the most 
persistent. For Aristotle himself laughter was closely related to ugliness 
and debasement; for Cicero 'the province of the ridiculous ... lies in 
a certain baseness and deformity'; for Descartes laughter is a mani- 
festation of joy 'mixed with surprise or hate or sometimes with both'; 
in Francis Bacon's list of laughable objects, the first place is taken by 
'deformity'. The essence of the 'theory of degradation' is defined in 
Hobbes's Leviathan: 

The passion of laughter is nothing else but sudden glory arising 
from a sudden conception of some eminency in ourselves by com- 
parison with the infirmity of others, or with our own formerly. 

Bain, one of the founders of modern psychology, followed on the 
whole the same theory: 'Not in physical effects alone, but in everything 
where a man can achieve a stroke of superiority, in surpassing or 
discomforting a rival, is the disposition of laughter apparent.' 4 

For Bergson laughter is the corrective punishment inflicted by society 
upon the unsocial individual: 'In laughter we always find an unavowed 
intention to humiliate and consequently to correct our neighbour.' 5 
Max Beerbohm found 'two elements in the public's humour: delight 
in suffering, contempt for the unfamiliar'. McDougall believed that 
'laughter has been evolved in the human race as an antidote to sym- 
pathy, a protective reaction shielding us from the depressive influence 
of the shortcomings of our fellow men.' 6 

Thus on this one point there is agreement among the theorists, 
ancient and modern; and not only agreement but exaggeration. One 
has only to think of Aristophanes or Calderon; A Midsummer Night's 
Dream or Chateaubriand's Maximes et Pensies, to realize that the aggres- 
sive charge detonated in laughter need not be gunpowder; a grain of 
Attic salt is enough to act as a catalyst. Furthermore, we must remember 



54 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



that aggression and self-defence, rage and fear, hostility and appre- 
hension, are as pairs of twins in their psychology and physiology. One 
of the typical situations in which laughter occurs is the moment of the 
sudden cessation of danger, real or imaginary; and rarely is the character 
of laughter as a discharge-mechanism for redundant tensions more 
strikingly manifested than in the sudden change of expression on the 
small child's face from anxious apprehension to the happy laugh of 
relief. 

Whatever the composition of the emotional charge which a narra- 
tive carries, it will produce a comic effect only if an aggressive-defensive 
tendency, however sublimated, is present in it. You may be deeply 
moved by a persons predicament, and yet unable to suppress a smile 
at its ludicrous aspect; and the impression of the 'ludicrousness' of 
another persons behaviour always implies an assertion — conscious 
or unconscious — of your own superiority; you smile at his ex- 
pense. 

The emotions which dominate on the opposite side of the triptych 
do not concern us as yet; but I must briefly mention them for the sake 
of contrast. Listening to Mozart, watching a great actor's performance, 
being in love or some other state of grace, may cause a welling up of 
happy emotions which moisten the eye or overflow in tears. Com- 
passion and bereavement may have the same physical effect. The 
emotions of this class, whether joyous or sad, include sympathy, 
identification, pity, admiration, awe, and wonder. The common 
denominator of these heterogeneous emotions is a feeling of participa- 
tion, identification, or belonging; in other words, the self is experienced 
as being a part of a larger whole, a higher unity — which may be Nature, 
God, Mankind, Universal Order, or the Anitna Mundi; it may be an 
abstract idea, or a human bond with persons living, dead, or imagined. 
I propose to call the common element in these emotions the partici- 
patory or self-transcending tendencies. This is not meant in a mystical 
sense (though mysticism certainly belongs to this class of emotion); the 
term is merely intended to convey that in these emotional states the 
need is felt to behave as a part of some real or imaginary entity which 
transcends, as it were, the boundaries of the individual self; whereas 
when governed by the self-assertive class of emotions the ego is ex- 
perienced as a self-contained whole and the ultimate value. 

As a rule our emotions are complex mixtures in which both ten- 
dencies participate. Thus the emotion called 'love' — whether sexual 
or maternal — usually contains an aggressive or possessive, self-asserting 



LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 



55 



component, and an identificatory or self-transcending component. If 
emotions were represented by different colours, then the two opposite 
tendencies would appear as brightness values (black-white mixtures) 
superimposed on them. 

The subject will be discussed in more detail later (Chapters XI-XV); 
readers irritated by these repeated anticipatory excursions may find 
some excuse for them in the consideration that the painful vivisection 
of the comic, in which they are asked to participate, is not an end in 
itself, but a means to uncover the pattern which unites the apparently 
so heterogeneous creative activities in humour, art, and discovery. 

The Inertia of Emotion 

The first to make the suggestion that laughter is a discharge mechanism 
for 'nervous energy* seems to have been Herbert Spencer. His essay on 
the 'Physiology of Laughter* (i860) starts with the proposition: 
'Nervous energy always tends to beget muscular motion; and when it 
rises to a certain intensity always does beget it Emotions and sensa- 
tions tend to generate bodily movements, and . . . the movements are 
violent in proportion as the emotions or sensations are intense.' 
Hence, he concludes, 'when consciousness is unawares transferred 
from great things to small' the 'liberated nerve force' will expend itself 
along the channels of least resistance, which are the muscular move- 
ments of laughter. 

The details of Spencer's theory (parts of which Freud incorporated 
into his own) 7 have become obsolete; but its basic thesis that 'emotion 
tends to beget bodily motion' has not only been confirmed, but has 
become so much of a commonplace in contemporary neurophysiology 
that the need to qualify it is often forgotten. For there exist, of course, 
emotional states — looking at the sea, or engaging in religious contem- 
plation — which, on the contrary, tend to promote relaxation and 
bodily passivity. The title of Walter B. Cannon's pioneer work, which 
had a decisive influence on the modern approach to the problem of 
emotions — Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear, and Rage — ought to 
have acted as a warning that the emotions- which mobilize the body 
into action all belong to an important, but nevertheless limited, cate- 
gory — that which enters the service of the self-assertive tendencies. 
Cannon himself warned—with little success — against the lumping 
together of all emotions into a kind of red rag drenched with 



56 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



adrenalin.* However, for the moment we are concerned only with 
precisely this limited category—the aggressive-defensive type of 
emotion which enters into the comic. 

"When the Marquis in the Chamfort story rushes to the window, our 
intellect turns a somersault and enters with gusto into the new game; 
but the piquant expectations which the narrative carried, including 
perhaps an unconscious admixture of sadism, cannot be transferred to 
the other, the quid-pro-quo matrix; they are disposed of through 
channels of least resistance. When Othello, on the point of strangling 
Desdemona, breaks into hiccoughs and is transformed into a poor, 
sodden ham, our thoughts are again capable of performing the jump 
from one associative context into another, but our tension, now de- 
prived of its logical justification, must somehow be worked off. In a 
word, laughter is aggression (or apprehension) robbed of its logical 
raison d'etre; the puffing away of emotion discarded by thought. 

To give another example: one of the popular devices of sustained 
humour is impersonation. Children imitating adults, the comedian 
impersonating a public figure, men disguised as women and women as 
men— in all these cases the impersonator is perceived as himself and 
somebody else at the same time. While this situation lasts the two 
matrices are bisodated in the spectator's mind; and while his intellect 
is capable of swiftly oscillating from one matrix to the other and back, 
his emotions are incapable of following these acrobatic turns; they are 
spilled into the gutters of laughter as soup is spilled on a rocking ship. 

What these metaphors are meant to convey is that the aggressive- 
defensive class of emotions has a greater inertia, persistence, or mass momentum 
than reason. This assumption is tacidy shared by most psychological 
theories, but it needs to be explicidy stated in order to appreciate its 
consequences. The most important among these is that quite fre- 
quently our emotions are incapable of keeping step with our reason 
and become divorced from reason. In psychopathology this pheno- 
menon is taken for granted, but its significance in less extreme situa- 
tions is generally overlooked — although both common experience 
and neurophysiology ought to make it obvious. Emotions of the self- 
asserting type involve a wide range of bodily changes, such as in- 
creased secretion of the adrenal glands, increase of blood sugar, 
acceleration of heart rate, speedier clotting of the blood, altered 
breathing, inhibition of digestive activity, changes in electric skin 
resistance, sweating, 'goose-pimples' which make the hair of the skin 
stand on end, dilation of the pupils, muscle tension, and tremor. The 



LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 



57 



joint effect of these so-called emergency reactions is to put the whole 
organism into a state of readiness for come what may; sweating, for 
instance, disposes of the heat generated by fight or flight, and the 
abundance of blood sugar in the circulation provides the muscles with 
excess energy. Hence the remarkable feats of force of which people 
are capable in danger; but more important from our point of view is 
the lowering of the threshhold of motor responses — the increased 
excitability of the muscles by nervous impulses, and the resulting 
tendency to violent movement, to 'work off', or at least 'shake off', the 
physiological effects of emotion. The chief mediators of this general 
mobilization of the resources of the body are the so-called sympathetic 
division of the autonomous nervous system, and the hormones secreted 
by the medulla of the suprarenal glands: adrenalin and nor-adrenalin, 
the 'humours' of fear and anger. Since these nervous and glandular 
processes are interrelated, it is convenient to refer to them jointly as 
activities of the sympathico-adrenal system. (To avoid confusion, I 
must underline that the sympathetic nervous system has nothing to do 
with the friendly emotion of sympathy; rather, as I have just said, with 
its opposites: rage and fear. However, by a lucky coincidence the 
initials of Sympathico-adrenal system are the same as those of the 
Self-^issertive emotions which are aroused by it.) 

It follows from the above that these emotions involve incom- 
parably heavier machinery, acting on the whole body, than the pro- 
cess of thinking which, physiologically speaking, is confined to the 
roof of the brain. The chemical and visceral states induced by the 
action of the sympathico-adrenal system tend to persist; once this 
massive apparatus is set in motion it cannot be called off or 'change 
its direction at a moment's notice. Common observation provides 
daily, painful confirmation of this. We are literally 'poisoned* by our 
adrenal humours; reason has little power over irritability or anxiety; 
it takes time to talk a person out of a mood, however valid the argu- 
ments; passion is blind to better judgement; anger and fear show 
physical after-effects long after their causes have been removed. If we 
could change our moods as quickly as we jump from one thought to 
another we would be acrobats of emotion. 

Thinking, in its physiological aspect, is based on electro-chemical 
activities in the cerebral cortex and related regions of the brain, in- 
volving energy transactions which are minute compared to the massive 
glandular, visceral, and muscular changes that occur when emotions 
are aroused. These changes are governed by phylogenetically much 



58 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



older parts of the brain than the roof-structures which enable man to 
think in verbal symbols. Behaviour at any moment is the outcome 
of complex processes which operate simultaneously on several levels of 
the nervous system, from the spinal cord to our latest acquisition, the 
pre-frontal lobes. There is probably no formal thinking without some 
affective colouring; but it is nevertheless legitimate to distinguish 
between form and colour — in our case between the logical pattern of a 
comic narrative and the emotive charge which it carries. 

The sympathico-adrenal system might be compared to the body of 
a piano which gives resonance to the cortical strings of thought. When 
all is well the huge wooden box lends depth and colour and warmth 
to the vibrations of the strings. But if you play a humorous scherzo 
with full pedal on, the resonating body is unable to follow the swift 
modulations of the chords — thought and emotion have become dis- 
sociated. It bjmotion des erted by tho ughLsMd&is disc ha rged in laughter. 
For e motion, c jwjng^ to its greatgLmas&uiicunentum, is unable to 
follow th e sudden switch oj jdejts,to a HifFfTcat type of logic o r a new 
~ru!e of the game; less nimble than tho ught, it tends to persist in a straight 
line.^Ariel leads CaEGaiTbn tjy r lKe nose: she jumps on a branch, 
he crashes into the tree. 

It could be objected that the faint emotive charge of a joke, the slight 
malice or salaciousness which it arouses, would not be sufficient to 
bring the massive sympathico-adrenal machinery into action. The 
answer lies in the anachronistic character of our autonomous responses 
to stimuli which carry an echo, however faint, of situations that held 
a threat or promise in the remote past of the species; which once were 
biologically relevant, though they no longer are. These reactions lag 
by many rnillermia behind the conditions in which we live: we jump 
at a sudden sound; we develop gooseflesh in response to a screeching 
noise, to make our long-lost body hair bristle at the attack of some 
extinct beast; we sweat before an examination — to dispose of the 
excessive heat our bodies might develop in the impending struggle 
with the examiner. I like to call these innate, anachronistic responses 
the over-statements of the body. One of the remarkable things about them 
is that they can be triggered off by certain stimuli in minute, quasi- 
homeopathic doses. 

To sum up, the grain of salt which must be present in the narrative 
to make us laugh turns out to be a drop of adrenalin. 



The Mechanism of Laughter 



In the first chapter I discussed the logic of humour; in the previous 
section its emotional dynamics. Fitting the two together, we can now 
expand the formula on page 35 as follows: The sudden bisociation of a 
mental event with two habitually incompatible matrices results in an 
abrupt transfer of the train of thought from one associative context to 
another. The emotive charge which the narrative carried cannot be so 
transferred owing to its greater inertia and persistence; discarded by 
reason, the tension finds its outlet in laughter. 

But that still leaves the question open why the excess energy should 
be worked off in the particular form of laughter and not, say, by 
flapping one's arms or wiggling one's toes. The somewhat tentative 
answer is that the muscular contractions and breathing actions in 
laughter seem to offer natural channels of least resistance for the over- 
flow. To quote Freud: 

According to the best of my knowledge, the grimaces and 
contortions of the corners of the mouth that characterize laughter 
appear first in the satisfied and over-satiated nursling when he 
drowsily quits the breast. . . . They are physical expressions of the 
determination to take no more nourishment, an 'enough' so to 
speak, or rather a 'more than enough*. . . . This primal sense of 
pleasurable saturation may have provided the link between the smile 
— that basic phenomenon underlying laughter — and its subsequent 
connection with other pleasurable processes of de-tension. 8 

In other words, the muscle-contractions of the smile, as the earliest 
manifestations of relief from tension, would thereafter become 
channels of least resistance. 

The peculiar breathing in laughter, with its repeated, explosive ex- 
halations, seems designed to 'puff away' surplus tension in a kind of 
respiratory gymnastics; and the vigorous gestures and slapping of 
thighs obviously serve the same function. Often these massive reactions 
seem to be quite out of proportion to the feeble stimuli which provoke 
them — particularly when we do not like the type of joke which causes 
such- hilarity in others: 

A thousand Edinburgh schoolchildren burst into laughter when 
David Oistrakh, the Russian violinist, snapped a string while playing 

59 



<5o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Schubert's Fantasy in C Major during a recital of a city housing 
estate yesterday. Their studious attention broke when Mr. Oistrakh 
— guest of honour at the Edinburgh Festival — held up the violin and 
looked with consternation at his accompanist. 9 

Let us try to understand what those brats found so funny. Firstly, 
there is the familiar pattern of the practical joke which the laws of 
physics play on the artist, suddenly revealing that his magic strings 
are made of common cat-gut — 'I know you from a plum-tree'. The 
'consternation on Oistrakh' s face is the consternation of the man 
slipping on the banana skin; exaltation is debunked by the sudden 
impact of triviality. But all this does not account for that unexpected, 
barbaric outburst of hilarity which schoolmasters know only too well 
— unless one realizes that what I call, somewhat abstracdy, 'the 
emotional charge of the narrative' contains here a mass of resentment, 
mosdy perhaps unconscious, at having to sit still and listen 'with 
studious attention* to that Russian with the unpronouncable name; a 
repressed emotion, tending to beget fidgety motions, until the tension 
snaps with the string, releasing the outburst, instantly transforming the 
hushed class into a horde of savages. 

In other words, all discussions of the comic remain bloodless abstrac- 
tions unless we bear in mind that laughter is a phenomenon of the 
trigger-release type, where a minute cause can open the tap of sur- 
prisingly large stores of energy from various sources: repressed sadism; 
repressed sex; repressed fear; even repressed boredom. Here is a list 
of 'occasions for laughter' recorded by American undergraduates in 
reply to a questionnaire: 

A pillow fight in the dormitory 

A girl friend tore her dress 

I fell during skating 

A dog came in during a lecture 

A mispronounced word in rhetoric class 

Being teased about my corpulence 

Lizzie trying to do a fairy dance 

My opponents in a bridge game bidding four spades when I held 

two aces and the king, jack and five of spades 
An article by a priest on the sex life of H. G. Wells. 10 

This ought to be enough to make one realize that laughter may be 



LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 



61 



entirely mirthless and humourless;* it can be contrived as a means of 
social communication or in lieu of a rude noise. It can also serve to 
cover up sexual or sadistic gloating, as in the forced, tumescent laughter 
of the spectators at a strip-tease — or in the jolly manifestations of 
English popular humour at public hangings in the last century. 

Surprisingly, Bergson believed that one can only laugh in the 
presence of others — presumably because this fitted his theory of 
laughter as an act of social correction ('one has no taste for the comic 
when one feels isolated. It seems that laughter needs an echo. Our 
laughter is always the laughter of a group.'). 11 No doubt, collective 
giggling fits do occur in dormitories at girls' schools, and no doubt one 
laughs with more gusto in company than alone. But the infectiousness 
of emotive manifestations is a well-known phenomenon in group 
behaviour, which equally applies to hysteria, panic, even to infectious 
coughing of theatre audiences; it is not a specific characteristic of 
laughter, and contributes nothing to its explanation. 

Lastly, laughter or smiling frequendy occur in response to stimuli 
which in themselves are not comic, but merely signs or symbols for 
comic stimuli, or even symbols of symbols — Chaplin's boots, Groucho 
Marx's cigar, caricatures of celebrities reduced to a few visual hints, 
catch-phrases and allusions to familiar situations. The analysis of these 
oblique cases often requires tracing back a long and involved thread of 
associations to its source, which is not much fun; yet the procedure is 
essentially the same as the literary critic's or the art historian's when 
they try to analyse the evocative power of a poetic image or a land- 
scape. The task is made more complicated by the fact that the effect of 
such comic symbols— the sight of Colonel Blimp on a cartoon, the 
appearance of FalstafT on the stage — appears to be instantaneous; there 
seems to be no time for first accumulating and then discharging ten- 
sion. But in these cases memory serves as an accumulator, a storage 
battery whose electric charge can be sparked off any time: the smile 
which greets Papageno strutting on to the scene is derived from a 
mixture of memories and expectations. All of which goes to show that 
to find the explanation why we laugh may be a task as delicate as 
analysing the chemical composition of a perfume, with its multiple 
ingredients — some of which are never perceived, while others, 
sniffed in isolation, would make us wince. 



The Importance of not being Earnest 



Discussing the problem of man's innate aggressive tendencies, 
Aldous Huxley once said: 

On the physiological level I suppose the problem is linked with the 
fact that we carry around with us a glandular system which was 
admirably well adapted to life in the Paleolithic times but is not very 
well adapted to life now. Thus we tend to produce more adrenalin 
than is good for us, and we either suppress ourselves and turn 
destructive energies inwards or else we do not suppress ourselves 
and we start hitting people. 12 

A third alternative, which Huxley overlooked, is to laugh at 
people. There are, of course, other outlets for tame aggression: 
sport, politics, book-reviewing, and so forth; but these are conscious, 
voluntary activities, whereas laughter is a spontaneous, physiological 
reflex, a gift of nature included in our native equipment as part of the 
evolutionary package deal. Not only the functions of our glands, but 
the whole autonomous nervous system and the emotion-controlling 
centres in the mid-brain, are much older than the Paleolithic Age, 
and reflect conditions at a stage of human evolution when the struggle 
for existence was more deadly than at present and when any unusual 
sight or sound had to be answered by jumping, bristling, fight, or 
flight. As security and comfort increased in the species, the afFect- 
generating emergency mechanisms of the sympathico-adrenal system 
gradually became an anachronism. But organs and their functions do 
not atrophy at the rate at which they become redundant; and thus the 
biological evolution ofhomo sapiens (if it has not stopped altogether) 
lags dangerously behind his mental evolution. One consequence of 
this is that our brains have become 'divided houses of faith and reason, 
of thinking at odds with emotions; another, that our emotive respon- 
ses have become 'over-statements of the body* out of all proportion 
with the reactions biologically required or socially permitted— and 
cannot be worked off through their original channels. Fortunately, at 
some point along the evolutionary line, the luxury reflexes of laughter 
and weeping emerged as overflow mechanisms for the disposal of at 
least part of our redundant emotions. They are obviously twin re- 
flexes: laughter serving the disposal of aggressive emotions cast off 
by the intellect, while crying (to anticipate once more) facilitates the 
overflow of participatory emotions accepted by the intellect. 

62 



LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 



63 



It follows that two conditions had to be fulfilled before homo Helens, 
the laughing animal, could emerge: first a relative security of existence, 
which called for new outlets for excess energies; second and more 
important, a level of evolution had to be reached where reasoning had 
gained a certain degree of autonomy from the 'blind* urges of emotion; 
where thought had acquired that independence and nimbleness which 
enable it to detach itself from feeling — and to confront its glandular 
humours with a sense of humour. Only at this stage of 'cortical emanci- 
pation could man perceive his own emotions as redundant, and make 
the smiling admission 'I have been fooled'. 

Beneath the human level there is neither the possibility nor the 
need for laughter; it could arise only in a biologically secure species 
with redundant emotions and intellectual autonomy.* The sudden 
realization that one's own excitement is 'unreasonable' heralds the 
emergence of self-criticism, of the ability to see one's very own self 
from outside; and this bisociation of subjective experience with an ob- 
jective frame of reference is perhaps the wittiest discovery of homo 
sapiens. 

Thus laughter rings the bell of man's departure from the rails of 
instinct; it signals his rebellion against the smglemindedness of his 
biological urges, his refusal to remain a creature of habit, governed by 
a single set of 'rules of the game'. Animals are fanatics; but 'O / How 
the dear litde children laugh / When the drums roll and the lovely 
Lady is sawn in half. . . ,' 13 

NOTES 

To p. 56. Criticizing a paper read by a neurologist to a learned society, he 
remarked: 'The author spoke of emotions in very general terms. . . . There are 
features which he mentioned which I could recognize as characteristic of major 

emotions, as anger and rage; but after all, love is an emotion I think that 

when we discuss emotion we ought to specify the sorts of emotion we have in 
mind* (Cannon, 1929). 

To p. 61. The article in which this list appeared is characteristic of the 
behaviourist approach; it ennumerated three 'basic principles' of laughter: (a) 
'as an expression of joy', (b) 'laughter makes for group cohesion through homo- 
geneity of feeling within the group', (c) 'laughing can be used as a weapon in 
competitive situations*. The word 'humour' was not mentioned in the article; 
laughing at 'jokes, antics, etc.*, was mentioned only in passing, as obviously nor 
a phenomenon worthy of the psychologists' attention. 

To p. 63. Some domesticated animals — dogs, chimpanzees — seem to be 
capable of a humorous expression and to engage in teasing activities. These may 
be regarded as evolutionary forerunners of laughter. 



Ill 

VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 

The tools have now been assembled which should enable the 
reader to dissect any specimen of humour. The procedure to 
be followed is: first, determine the nature of M 2 and M 2 in 
the diagrams on pages 35 and 37 by discovering the type of logic, the 
rules of the game, which govern each matrix. Often these rules are 
implied, as hidden axioms, and taken for granted — the code must be 
de-coded. The rest is easy: find the 'link* — the focal concept, word, or 
situation which is bisociated with both mental planes; lastly, define 
the character of the emotive charge and make a guess regarding the 
unconscious elements that it may contain. In the sections which follow 
I shall apply this technique to various types of humour. 

Pun and Witticism 

Our spacemen, Mrs. Lamport fears, are 'heading for the "lunar 
bin".' The ageing libertine, she tells us, 'feels his old Krafft Ebbing*. 
The Reverend Spooner had a great affection, or so he said, for 'our 
queer old dean'. 

One swallow, the proverb says, does not make a summer — nor 
quench the thirst. Elijah's ravens, according to Milton, were 'though 
ravenous taught to abstain from what they brought*. Not so Napoleon, 
who, shortly after his coronation, confiscated the estates of the house 
of Orleans, which caused a contemporary to remark: *C*est le premier 
vol de Vaigle* Equally to the point was Mr. Paul Jenkin's discovery re- 
garding the pros and cons of Britain's entry into the Common Market: 
'The Cons were pro, while Lab has turned con.' 

The pun is the bisociation of a single phonetic form with two 

64 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



<55 



meanings — two strings of thought tied together by an accousric knot. 
Its immense popularity with children, its prevalence in certain forms 
of mental disorder ('punning mania') , and its frequent occurrence in 
the dream, indicate the profound unconscious appeal of association 
based on pure sound. Its opposite number is the rhyme. In between 
these two, on the central panel, the bisociation of sound and sense 
assumes a playful form in word games like Lexicon, anagram, and 
crossword puzzle; and a serious form in comparative philology and 
paleography, the deciphering of ancient inscriptions (pp. 186-7). 

Whether the two meanings associated with the pun are derived from 
the same root as in 'lunar bin'; or are homonyms as vol = flight and 
vol = theft, is irrelevant provided the two derivations have drifted 
apart far enough to become incompatible. In fact, there is a con- 
tinuous series stretching from the pun through the play of words 
(Jen de mots) to the play of ideas (jett a" esprit). Let me quote a few more 
examples of the latter. 

'The super-ego is that part of the personality which is soluble in 
alcohol/ The concept 'soluble' is bisociated (a) with the context of the 
chemical laboratory and (b) with the (metaphorical) dissolution of 
one's high principles in one's cups. The first few words of the sentence 
arouse perhaps a mild irritation with the Freudian jargon — or appre- 
hension, as the case may be; which is then tittered away through the 
now familiar mechanism. 

Here is another sample from this game of definitions: 'What is a 
sadist? A sadist is a person who is kind to a masochist.' The link-concept 
is 'kindness', bisociated with two diametrically opposed meanings; 
moreover the whole definition is open to two different interpretations: 

(a) the sadist does a kindness to the masochist by torturing him; 

(b) the sadist is torturing the masochist by being kind to him. 

In both cases the sadist must go against his own nature, and the 
definition turns out to be in fact a variant of the logical paradox about 
the Cretan who asserts that all Cretans are liars. But we can get around 
it by deciding that in either interpretation 'kind' should be understood 
both literally and metaphorically at the same time; in other words, by 
playing simultaneously two games governed by opposite rules. We 
shall see that such reversals of logic play a considerable part in scientific 
discovery (pp. 191-9). They are also a recurrent motif in poetry and 
literature. One of my favourite Donne quotations is a line from the 
Litany: 'For O, for some, not to be martyrs is a martyrdom.' 

I have given examples of the bisociation of professional with 



66 THE ACT OF CREATION 

commonsense logic, of metaphorical with literal meaning, of contexts 
linked by sound affinities, of trains of reasoning travelling, happily 
joined together, in opposite directions. The list could be extended 
beyond the limits of patience. In fact any two matrices can be made to 
yield a comic effect of sorts, by finding an appropriate link between 
them and infusing a drop of adrenalin. Take as a random example 
two associative contexts centred on the unpromising key-words 
< alliteration , and 'hydrotherapy*. (The example actually originated in 
a challenge following a discussion; I am merely quoting it, with 
apologies, to show that in principle it can be done): 

Gossip Column Item: Lady Smith-Everett, receiving me in her 
sumptuous boudoir, explained that she had always suffered from 'the 
most maddening rashes' until she met her present physician, a former 
professor of psycho-hydrotherapy at the University of Bucharest. By 
employing a new test which he invented, the Professor discovered 
that she had 'a grade 4 allergy' against sojourning in spas and 
holiday resorts with the initial letter C. No more visits to Capri and 
Carlsbad for Lady S-E.! 

It is not even necessary that the two matrices should be governed 
by incompatible codes. One can obtain comic effects by simply con- 
fronting quantitatively different scales of operations, provided that 
they differ sufficiently in order of magnitude for one scale to become 
negligible compared with the other. The result is the type of joke made 
according to the formula: the mountains laboured, the birth was a 
mouse. 

With an added twist you get this kind of dotty dialogue — between a 
nervous bus-passenger and the conductor: 
'What's the time?' 
'Thursday.' 

*Good Lord! I must get off.' 

This is a serial affair in which not two but three matrices are suc- 
cessively involved, each with a different scale of measurement, M x 
has a grid of hours and minutes; M 2 of days of the week. The two differ 
in fact only in quantity but provide qualitatively different frames of 
reference; the third matrix has spatial instead of temporal co-ordinates 
—where to get off, not when. It would be impossible to orientate one's 
behaviour with reference to these three different grids at the same 
time; yet that is precisely what the tri-sociated passenger is trying to do . 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



67 



Let me repeat: any two universes of discourse can be used to fabri- 
cate a joke. Lewis Carroll sent the following contribution to a philo- 
sophical symposium: 

'Yet what mean all such gaieties to me 
"Whose life is full of indices and surds? 
X* + 7 X+53 
= II/3' 

The universes of verbal and mathematical symbols are linked by 
pure sound-affinity — with rhyme but without reason. When T. E. 
Lawrence joined the ranks as Private Shaw, Noel Coward wrote to 
him that famous letter beginning 'Dear 338171 (may I call you 338?)'. 

Man and Animal 

In the previous chapter I discussed the bisociation of man and 
machine; related to it is the hybrid man-animal. Disney's creatures 
behave as if they were human without losing their animal appearance, 
they live on the line of intersection of the two planes; so do the car- 
toonist's piggy or mousy humans. This double-existence is comic, 
but only so long as the confrontation has the effect of a slighdy de- 
grading exposure of one or the other. If sympathy prevails over malice 
even poor Donald Duck's misfortunes cease to be laughable; and as you 
move over to the right-hand panel of the triptych, the man-animal 
undergoes a series of transformations: from the cloying lyricism of 
Bambi to the tragedy of Orwell's Boxer; from the archetypal menace 
of the werewolf to the Metamorphosis of Kafka's hero into a filth- 
devouring cockroach. As for science, the importance of learning about 
man by the experimental study of animal physiology need not be 
stressed; in psychology it has been rather overstressed to the point 
where the salivary reflexes of dogs came to be regarded as paradig- 
matic for human behaviour. 



Impersonation 

The various categories of the comic shade into each other: Disney's 
ariimals acting like humans could as well be classified under the 



68 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



heading 'imitation, impersonation, and disguise'. The impersonator is 
two different people at one time. If the result is degrading, the spec- 
tator will laugh. If he is led to sympathize or identify himself with the 
impersonated hero, he will experience that state of split-rnindedness 
known as dramatic illusion or the magic of the stage. Which of the 
two possibilities will occur depends of course partly on the actor, but 
ultimately 'a jest's prosperity lies in the ear / Of him that hears it, never 
in the tongue / Of him that makes it'. 1 The same 'narrative', a 
Victorian melodrama or a Chinese opera, acted in both cases in pre- 
cisely the same way, will make some spectators giggle, others weep. 
The same dramatic devices may serve either a comic or a tragic purpose: 
Romeo and Juliet are the victims of absurd coincidences, Oedipus's 
marriage to his mother is due to mistaken identity; Rosalind in As 
You Like It and Leonora in Fidelio are both disguised as men, yet in 
one case the result is drama, in another comedy. The technique of 
creating character-types is also shared by both: in the classical form of 
tragedy, whether Greek, Indian, or Japanese, characterization is often 
achieved by standardized masks; in the comedy, down to Moliere, 
by the creation of types: the miser, the glutton, the hypocrite, the 
cuckold. In the centre panel (where impersonation appears in the 
form of empathy, the act of self-projection which enables one to 
understand others, see below pp. 187-8) the classification of character- 
types has been the aim of incessant efforts — from the 'four tempera- 
ments' of the Greeks, to Kretschmer, Jung, Sheldon, and so on. 



The Child-Adult 

Why are puppies droll? Firstly, their helplessness, trustingness, attach- 
ment, and puzzled expression make them more 'human' than grown- 
up dogs; in the second place the ferocious growl of the puppy strikes 
us as an impersonation of adult behaviour (like the little boy with 
stuck-on beard and bowler-hat, pretending to be the family doctor); 
thirdly, the puppy's waddling and tumbling makes it a choice victim 
of nature's practical jokes; furthermore, its bodily disproportions, the 
huge padded paws, wrinkled brow, and Falstaffian belly, give it the 
appearance of a caricature; and so on. The delighted laughter which 
greets the puppy's antics seems so simple to explain; but when we try 
to analyse it we find several interlocking causes; and while the word 
'delighted' indicates a pure emotion, free from the ugly taint of 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



69 



aggressiveness, the grain of self-satisfied condescension, the conviction 
of our own superiority is nevertheless present, even if we are not 
aware of it. 

A simple shift of emphasis will move the bisociation of child and 
adult into the centre panel where it becomes a concern of pedagogues 
and psychiatrists. A further shift to the right, and the relation will be 
reversed, the child will be seen as an adult in disguise, immersed in the 
hidden tragedies of the nursery and boarding school — an inexhaustible 
subject of the autobiographical novel. 

The Trivial and the Exalted 

Parody is the most aggressive form of impersonation, designed not only 
to deflate hollow pretence but also to destroy illusion in all its forms; 
and to imdermine pathos by harping on the trivial, all-too-human 
aspects of the victim. Stage props collapsing, wigs falling off, public 
speakers forgetting their lines, dramatic gestures remaining suspended 
in the air — the parodist's favourite points of attack are all situated on 
the line of intersection between two planes: the Exalted and the 
Trivial. 

The artist reverses this technique by conferring on trivial experiences 
a new dignity and wonder: Rembrandt painting the carcass of a 
flayed ox, Manet his skinny, insipid Olympia; Hemingway drawing 
tragedy out of the repetitive, inarticulate stammer of his characters; 
Chekhov focussing the reader's attention on a fly crawling on a lump 
of sugar while Natasha is contemplating suicide. 

When 'consciousness is unawares transferred from great things to 
small' — which Spencer regarded as the prime cause of laughter — the 
result will be either a comic or an aesthetic experience, depending on 
whether the persons emotions are of the type capable of participating 
in the transfer or not. The artist, reversing the parodist's technique, 
walks on a tightrope, as it were, along the line where the exalted and 
the trivial planes meet; he 'sees with equal eye, as God of all, / A hero 
perish or a sparrow fall*. The scientist's attitude is basically similar in 
situations where he suddenly discovers the connection between a 
banal event and a general law of nature — Newton's apple or the 
boiling kettle of James Watt. 

* When F. W. H. Myers became interested in people's attitudes to 
religion he questioned an elderly widow on what she thought about 



70 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the whereabouts of her departed husband's soul. She replied: 'Oh well, 
I suppose he is enjoying eternal bliss, but I wish you wouldn't talk 
about such unpleasant subjects.' I would call this an illustration of the 
peaceful coexistence of the tragic and trivial planes in our humble 
minds. Equally convincing is this statement made by a schoolboy to 
his mathematics master: 
'Infinity is where things happen which don't.' 2 

Caricature and Satire 

The political cartoon, at its best, is a translation into visual imagery of 
a witty topical comment; at its worst, a manipulation of symbols — 
John Bull, Uncle Sam, the Russian bear — which, once comic, have 
degenerated into visual cliches. The symbols trigger off memories 
and expectations; the narrative content of the cartoon is taken in by 
visual scanning, with possibly a delayed-action effect due to the time 
needed for 'seeing the joke*. The analysis of such mixed forms is a 
lengthy affair.* 

The portrait caricature, on the other hand, relies for its effects on 
purely visual means. Its method recalls the distorting mirrors at fun- 
fairs, which reflect the human form elongated into a candle-shape, or 
absurdly compressed, or as a vague phantom with wavy outlines. As 
a result we see ourselves and yet something else; our familiar shapes 
being transformed as if the body were merely an elastic surface that 
can be stretched in all directions. 

The mirror distorts by exaggerating mechanically in one spatial 
direction at the expense of others; the caricaturist distorts by exaggera- 
ting features which he considers characteristic of his victim's appearance 
or personality. His second main trick is over-simplification: he mini- 
mizes or leaves out features which are not relevant for his purpose. A 
prominent nose, for instance, such as General de Gaulle's, can be 
exploited to the extent that the rest of the face shrinks to insignificance: 
the part has been detached from the whole and has become a nose an 
sick The product of the clever caricaturist's distortions is something 
physiologically impossible, yet at the same time visually convincing — 
he has superimposed his frame of perception on our own. For a 
caricature is comic only if we know something of the victim, if we 
have a mental image, however vague, of the person, or type of person, 
at which it is aimed— even if it is an Eskimo, a cave-man, or a Martian 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



71 



robot. The unknown cannot be distorted or misrepresented. The 
caricature of the more ferocious type is the rape of an image, an optical 
debunking of the victim; in its gender form, a semi-afFectionate kick 
at the heel of Achilles. 

Thus the malicious pleasure derived from a good caricature origin- 
ates in the confrontation of a likeness, distorted according to the 
artist's rules of the game, with reality or our image thereof. But it is a 
rather harmless form of malice because we know that the caricaturist's 
monster with the cucumber nose or enormous belly is a biological im- 
possibility, that it is not real Illustrations of elephantiasis and patholo- 
gical obesity are not comic because these distortions of the human 
shape are known to be real, and therefore arouse pity. The knowledge 
that the deformities of the caricature are merely pretence acquits us of 
all charitable obligations and allows us to laugh at the victim's expense. 

The exaggeration and simplification of features selected according to 
his judgement of what is to be considered relevant is a technique 
shared by both the caricaturist and the artist — who calls it stylization. 
(Needless to say, a caricature is also a form of art; but for convenience' 
sake I am using throughout this book the term 'art' to refer to its non- 
comic varieties.) Stylization has been carried to extreme length in a 
number of ancient and modern art forms without destroying the 
aesthetic effect: that is to say, without sliding from art into caricature. 
The elongated skulls of certain Egyptian sculptures reflect a con- 
temporary practice of deforming the princely babies' heads, but they 
obviously exaggerate the result. Nevertheless it would hardly occur to 
one to call Tutankhamen an egghead — because one feels that the 
sculptor exaggerated not with a hostile but with a worshipful intent, 
and this attitude is communicated to the spectator. Once more the 
polarity between comic and aesthetic experience is seen to derive from 
the polarity between the self-assertive and self-transcending tendencies. 

This still holds true even when communication between artist and 
spectator breaks down. In the eyes of the Philistine all experimental art 
is ludicrous, because the PhiHstine's attitude is aggressive-defensive. 
When Picasso shuffles round the eyes and limbs of his figures in a 
manner which is biologically impossible and yet has a visual logic of 
its own, he juxtaposes the seen and the known — he is walking, pre- 
cariously balanced, on the borderline between two universes of ex- 
perience, each governed by a different code. The conservative-minded 
spectator, unable to follow, suspects the artist of pulling his leg by 
deliberately distorting the human shape as the caricaturist does; and 



72 



THB ACT OP CREATION 



so the two-faced woman with three breasts becomes in his eyes a 
caricature. The ambiguity is perhaps most strikingly illustrated in 
some of the character-studies by Leonardo, Hogarth, and Daumier. 
The passions reflected in them are so violent, the grimaces so ferocious, 
that it is impossible to tell whether they were meant as portraits or 
caricatures, and the distinction becomes a purely theoretical one. If 
you feel that such distortions of the human face do not really exist, 
that Daumier, deliberately exaggerating, merely pretended that they 
exist, then you are absolved from horror and pity and can laugh at his 
grotesques. But if you feel that this is indeed what Daumier saw in 
those de-humanized faces, then you are looking at a work of art. The 
humorist thrives on deformity; the artist deforms the world to re- 
create it in his own image. 

The technique of exaggerating the relevant and simplifying or 
ignoring the irrelevant aspects of reality is shared not only by the 
artist and caricaturist but is equally indispensable to the scientist. The 
motivations of each of the three differ, of course, and with them their 
criteria of relevance. The humorist's motives are aggressive, the 
artist's participatory, the scientist's exploratory. The scientist's criteria 
of relevance are 'objective' in the sense of being emotionally neutral, 
but they still depend on the particular aspect of reality in which he 
is interested. Every drawing on the blackboard—whether it is meant 
to represent the wiring diagram of a radio set or the circulation of the 
blood, the structure of a molecule or the weather over the Adantic — 
is based on the same method as the cartoonist's: selective emphasis on 
the relevant factors and omission of the rest. A map bears the same 
relation to a landscape as a character-sketch to a face; every chart, 
diagram, or model, every schematic or symbolic representation of 
physical or mental processes, is an unemotional caricature of reality. 
At least, 'unemotional' in the sense that the bias is not of an obvious 
kind; although some models of the universe as a rigid, mechanical 
clockwork which, once wound up, must follow its unalterable course, 
or of the human mind as a slot-machine, have turned out to be crude 
caricatures inspired by unconscious bias. 

The satire is a verbal caricature which distorts characteristic features 
of an individual or society by exaggeration and simplification. The 
features picked out for enlargement by the satirist are, of course, those 
of which he disapproves: 'If Nature's inspiration fails', wrote Juvenal, 
* indignation will beget the poem.* The comic efFect of the satire is 
derived from the simultaneous presence, in the reader's mind, of the 



VARIETIES OP HUMOUS 



73 



social reality with which he is familiar, and of its reflection in the 
distorting mirror of the satirist. It focusses attention on abuses and 
deformities in society of which, blunted by habit, we were no longer 
aware; it makes us suddenly discover the absurdity of the familiar 
and the familiarity of the absurd. 

The same effect is achieved if, instead of magnifying objectionable 
features in customs and institutions, the satirist projects them by means 
of the allegory onto a different background, such as an animal society — 
e.g. Aristophanes, Swift, Orwell. In either case we are made suddenly 
conscious of conventions and prejudices which we have unquestion- 
ingly accepted, which were tacidy implied in the codes in control of 
our thinking and behaviour. The confrontation with an alien matrix 
reveals in a sharp, pitiless light what we failed to see in following our 
dim routines; the tacit assumptions hidden in the rules of the game are 
dragged into the open. The bisociative shock shatters the frame of 
complacent habits of thinking; the seemingly obvious is made to yield 
its secret. 

'In this world of perfect justice, rich and poor alike have the right to 
sleep under bridges/ Anatole France's classic epigram is a confrontation 
of abstract democracy with the brutal facts of life; it conjures up the 
image of a well-dressed bourgeois making use of his constitutional 
rights to doss down, in the name of Liberte, Egalite, and Fratemite, 
under the arches of the Pont de la Concorde. In its higher reaches the 
satirist's art merges into the social scientist's quest for truth; Brave New 
World and 1984 are extrapolations of present trends into the future; 
Gulliver s Travels and Erewhon, on the other hand, follow the method 
of the anthropologist, who deepens our understanding of our own 
society by confronting it with the equally 'self-evident* beliefs and 
customs of exotic civilizations. 

Thus, as we travel across the triptych, satire shades into social science; 
and this, in turn, branches out into the tragic allegory — Plato's Cave 
and Kafka's Casde — or into poetic Utopia. The artistic hazards of the 
latter are perhaps due to a conflict of emotions. Writers of Utopias are 
motivated by revulsion against society as it is, or at least by a rejection 
of its values; and since revulsion and rejection are aggressive attitudes, 
it comes more naturally to them to paint a picture of society with a 
brush dipped in adrenalin than in syrup or aspirin. Hence the contrast 
between Huxley's brilliant, bitter Brave New World and the goody- 
goody bores on his Island. 

The satirist's most effective weapon is irony. Its aim is to defeat the 



74 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



opponent on his own ground by pretending to accept his premisses, 
his values, his methods of reasoning, in order to expose their implicit 
absurdity. 'All animals are equal, but some are more equal than 
others/ Irony purports to take seriously what it does not; it enters into 
the spirit of the other person's game to demonstrate that its rules are 
stupid or vicious. It is a subtle weapon, because the person who wields 
it must have the imaginative power of seeing through the eyes of his 
opponent, of projecting himself into the others mental world. The 
psychiatrist who goes patiently along with the patient's fantasies, the 
teacher who adapts his language to the level of comprehension of the 
child, the dramatist who speaks through his characters' voices, employ 
the same procedure with the opposite intent and effect. 

The Misfit 

Both Cicero and Francis Bacon gave deformity a high place on their 
lists of causes for laughter. The princes of the Renaissance collected 
midgets, hunchbacks, monsters, and Blackamoors for their merriment. 
We have become too civilized for that kind of thing, but children still 
jeer and laugh at people with a limp or a stammer, at foreigners with a 
funny pronunciation, at people oddly dressed — at any form of appear- 
ance or behaviour which deviates from the familiar norm. The more 
backwoodish a social group, juvenile or adult, the stricter its concep- 
tion of the normal, and the readier it will ridicule any departure from it. 

Consider for a moment the curious fact that to a civilized person a 
stutterer causes sympathetic embarrassment, whereas a person of 
normal speech giving an imitation of stuttering makes us laugh. So 
does the youngster in love who stutters only under the effect of a 
momentary surge of emotion. Again, a person with a foreign accent 
is accepted with tolerance, but the imitation of a foreign accent is 
comic. The explanation is that we know the imitator's stutter or mis- 
prononunciation to be mere pretence; this makes sympathy both un- 
necessary and impossible, and enables us to be childishly cruel with a 
clear conscience. We have met the same phenomenon (page 71) in 
our attitude towards the bodily deformities imputed by the caricaturist 
to his victim. 

The tolerant acceptance of physical or mental malformations in 
our fellow creatures, though of relatively recent origin, has become 
deeply engrained in Western society; we are no longer aware of the 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



75 



fact that it requires a certain imagination and a good deal of empathy 
to recognize in a dwarf, or a 'thick-lipped Blackamoor', a human 
being which, though different in appearance, exists and feels as one- 
self does. In the small child this kind of projective mechanism is 
absent or rudimentary. Piaget, among others, has strikingly shown 
how late the child accords to its fellow beings a conscious ego like its 
own. The more a person deviates from the familiar norm of the 
child's surroundings, the more difficult it is for the child to project into 
him life and feelings, to grant him the faculty of having experiences 
like his own. The same applies to the attitudes shown by tribal or 
parochial societies to foreigners, slaves, members of the lower classes' 
(almost inevitably treated as comic figures in literature up to and in- 
cluding Dickens); as well as to criminals, the mentally disordered and 
physically deformed. The creature who does not 'belong' to the 
tribe, clan, caste, or parish is not really human; he only aspires or 
pretends to be 'like us'. To civilized man, a dwarf is comic only if he 
struts about pretending to be tall, which is he not; in the primitive's 
eye the dwarf is comic because he pretends to be human, which he is 
not. The Greek word 'barbarian' means both foreigner and stutterer 
(bar-bar-ous); the uncouth, repetitive, barking sounds he uttered 
were a grotesque imitation of true human speech. Bodily and func- 
tional deformities are laughable to the uncouth mind for the same 
reasons as impersonation and caricature. 



The Paradox of the Centipede 

However, an additional factor enters into the comic effect of some dis- 
orders of behaviour such as stuttering, mispronunciation, misspelling: 
one might call it the bisociation of structure and function, or of part 
and whole. The stammering barbarian was a comic figure to the Greeks 
for reasons just mentioned; but the comedian's stage-stutter is funny in 
a different way. When he struggles with a consonant, trying to take 
the same hurdle again and again, eyes bulging and face convulsed, we 
become suddenly aware of the complicated motions of lips and tongue 
required to produce the sound 'M'; our attention becomes focussed 
on these physiological details torn from their functional context and 
placed under a magnifying glass, as it were. Much the same happens 
when the gramophone needle gets stuck in a groove, and the soprano's 
voice keeps repeating the same word on the same quaver. The part has 



76 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



become detached from the whole and monopolizes attention as if it 
existed in its own right, as an independent structural entity, regardless 
of its function in the larger context from which alone its meaning is 
derived. In one of Silone's novels an innocent peasant boy from the 
Abruzzi drifts into a crowd in front of Mussolini's new forum, and 
cannot understand why everybody keeps chanting in a chorus: 'Ce-du, 
ce~du, ce-du, ce-du . . / The isolated quaver or consonant which has made 
a declaration of independence, the syllables *du and *ce* torn from 
their context, are examples of the conflict which can arise between part 
and whole, structure and function, when — to put it in a different way 
— the dependent part pretends to be an independent whole and forces 
our attention to regard it as such. 

When we exercise a well-practised skill the parts must function 
smoothly and automatically— they must never occupy the focus of 
attention. This is true whether the skill in question is riding a bicycle, 
playing the violin, ennunciating the letter *M', or forming sentences 
according to the rules of grammar and syntax. The code which 
controls the performance functions, as we repeatedly saw, on a 
lower level of consciousness than the performance itself—on the 
fringes of awareness or, in completely automatized skills, even beyond 
the fringe. The moment attention is focussed on a normally auto- 
matized part-function such as ennunciating consonants, the matrix 
breaks down, the needle gets stuck, and the performance is paralysed — 
like the centipede who was asked in which order he moved his hundred 
legs, and could walk no more. 

The paradox of the centipede is a consequence of the hierarchic 
organization of the nervous system which demands that the highest 
centres should be occupied with the task in hand conceived as a whole, 
and leave the execution of the component sub-tasks and sub-sub-tasks 
to the sub-centres, etc., on lower levels of the nervous system. A 
brigadier does not give orders to, and concentrate his attention on, 
individual soldiers during action; if he does the action goes haywire. 
The paradox of the centipede will be seen to play an important part 
in discovery and the theory of thinking in general; in humour, apart 
from the examples mentioned, it accounts for the comic effect of 
the 'self-conscious* (in fact, detail-conscious) behaviour of the person 
who does not know what to do with his hands; and also explains 
why the comedian's clothes, and some foreign or bygone fashions, are 
funny. Conventional articles of apparel are perceived as parts of a 
person's appearance as a whole, whereas the comedian's checked 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



77 



trousers and the Victorian lady's busde disrupt the unity and force 
attention on textiles and starched draperies leading an independent 
life. Except when we are in a romantic mood: then a historical costume 
on the stage is no longer seen detached from its wearer but attaches him 
to the period. 

Since I mentioned mispronunciation, I must add the obvious remark 
that if the maltreated word assumes a different meaning, we get the 
involuntary pun; and even if it does not, mispronunciation can be 
funny if it follows its own logic which exposes the absurdities of con- 
ventional spelling. Try on an innocent foreigner the sequence: a 
coughing plough and a soughing trough; then see what happens. 



Displacement 

A car dealer is boosting a new sports model to a prospective client: 

'You get into this car at midnight and at 4 a.m. you are in 
Grimsby/ 

The customer is indignant: 'And what am I to do in the middle of 
the night in Grimsby}* 

The question is perfecdy logical, but irrelevant to the subject under 
discussion, which is the speed of the car. The link-concept is * Grimsby 
at 4 a.m.' — which in one context plays the accidental part of an im- 
provised example, in the second an essential part. This sudden shift 
of emphasis — or displacement of attention — to a seemingly irrelevant 
aspect of a bisociated concept is frequently found not only in humour, 
but also in art and discovery (Chapters VIII, XXIII). It is related to the 
paradox of the centipede, but instead of displacing attention from the 
whole to the part it is displaced from a dominant to a previously neg- 
lected aspect of the whole, showing it in a new light. 

In the Ballad of Reading Gaol there are two unforgettable lines: 

How else but through a broken heart 
May Lord Christ enter in? 

The broken heart has become such a cliche that its physical implica- 
tions — splitting apart and creating a gap — are never thought of. Wilde 
shifts our attention to that forgotten physical image; he lets salvation 
enter through the aching gap, like a thief in the night. When the White 



78 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Queen complains: 'It's a poor sort of memory which only works 
backwards,' she is putting her finger on an aspect of reality — the 
irreversibility of time— which we normally take for granted; her 
apparently silly remark carries metaphysical intimations, and appeals 
to our secret yearning for the gift of prophecy — matters which would 
never occur to Alice, that little paragon of stubborn common sense. 

Coincidence 

It was once usual to classify comedies into those relying on situations, 
manners, or characters. In his discussion of the first, Bergson came 
closest to the essence of humour: 'A situation is always comic', he 
wrote, 'if it participates simultaneously in two series of events which 
are absolutely independent of each other, and if it can be interpreted 
in two quite different meanings.' One feels like crying 'Fire', but a 
couple of pages further on Bergson has dropped the clue and gone 
back to his hobby: the interference of two independent series in a given 
situation is merely a further example of the 'mechanization of life'. 

In fact the crossing of two independent causal chains through 
coincidence, mistaken identity, confusion of time and occasion, is the 
most clean-cut example of bisociated contexts. The chance-coincidence 
on which they are hinged is the dens ex machina, the intervention of 
providence in both tragedy and comedy; and, needless to say, lucky 
hazards play an equally conspicuous part in the history of scientific 
discovery. 

Nonsense 

One type of comic verse lives on the bisociation of exalted form with 
trivial content. Certain metric forms, such as hexameter and Alexan- 
drine, arouse expectations of pathos, of the heroic and exalted; the 
pouring of homely, trivial contents into these epic moulds — 'beautiful 
soup, so rich and green' — creates a comic effect of the same type as the 
parody. The rolling dactyls of the first line of the limerick, carrying, 
instead of Hector and Achilles, a young lady from Stockton as their 
passenger, make her already appear ridiculous, regardless of the calami- 
tics which are sure to befall her. In this atmosphere of malicious ex- 
pectation whatever witticism the text has to offer will have a much 
enhanced effect. 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 79 

Instead of an epic mould, a soft, lyrical one will equally do: 

. . . And what could be moister 
Than tears from an oyster? 

Another variant is what one might call the pseudo-proverb: 'The 
rule is: jam tomorrow and jam yesterday — but never jam today.* Two 
logically incompatible statements have been telescoped into a line 
whose rhythm and syntax gives the impression of being a popular 
adage or golden rule of life. Sometimes the trick is done by the sub- 
stitution of a single word in a familiar text: 'One should never work 
between meals.' The homely, admonitory structure lulls the mind 
into bored acquiescence until the preposterous subterfuge is discovered. 
Oscar Wilde was a master of this form: 'In married life three is com- 
pany and two none'; 'the only way to get rid of a temptation is to 
yield to it', etc., etc. My own favourite coinage is: 'One should not 
carry moderation to extremes/ 

Nonsense humour — as Max Eastman has pointed out — is only 
effective if it, pretends to make sense: 'It's a fact the whole world knows 
That Pobbles are happier without their toes.' Even with rhymed 
gibberish the illusion of meaning is essential. 'The slithy toves' that 
'gyre and gimble in the wabe' evoke sound associations which suggest 
some kind of action even though we are unable to say what exactly the 
action is — perhaps some small creatures gyrating and gambolling on a 
brilliant day in the web of some flowery bush. The meaning varies 
with the person as the interpretation of the ink blots in a Rohrschach 
test; but without this illusory meaning projected into the phonetic 
pattern, without the simultaneous knowledge of being fooled, and of 
fooling oneself, there would be no enjoyment of *the jabberwock with 
eyes of flame' who 'came whiffling through the tulgey wood / And 
burbled as it came'. 

Tickling 

The harmless game of tickling has resisted all attempts to find a unitary 
formula for the causes of laughter; it has been the stumbling block 
which made the theorists of the comic give up, or their theories break 
down. 

It was at one time believed that the laughter caused by tickling is a 
purely mechanical reflex in response to a purely physical stimulation. 



8o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



But — as Darwin has pointed out — the response to tickling is 
squirming, wriggling, and straining to withdraw the tickled part — 
activities which may or may not be accompanied by laughter. The 
squirming response was interpreted by Darwin and Crile as an innate 
defence mechanism to escape a hostile grip on vulnerable areas which 
are not normally exposed to attack: the soles of the feet, the neck, 
arm-pits, belly, and flank. If a fly settles on the belly of a horse a kind of 
contractile wave may pass over the skin — the equivalent of the 
squkming of the tickled child. But the horse does not laugh when 
tickled, and the child not always. As Gregory has put it: 

A child fingers the pepper-pot, waves pepper into its nose, and 
sneezes violently. Touch it under the arm-pits, or finger its waist, 
and it wriggles vigorously. It sneezes to dislodge the pepper from its 
nose, and its wriggle suggests a sneeze to relieve its whole body. The 
violent squirm of the tickled child so obviously tries to avoid the 
tickling hand that, when the truth is perceived, it is difficult to 
understand how tickling and laughter could ever be identified or 
confused. 3 

Thus tickling a child will call out a wriggling and squirming 
response. But the child will laugh only — and this is the crux of the 
matter — if an additional condition is fulfilled: it must perceive the 
1 tickling as a mack attack, a caress in a mildly aggressive disguise. This 
; explains why people laugh only when tickled by others but not when 
• they tickle themselves. (The question why this should be so was once 
put to a B.B.C. Brains Trust which, after some humming, hawing, 
and giggling, decided that it was one of the insoluble mysteries of 
human nature.) Not only must there be a second person to do the 
tickling, but her expression and attitude must be mock-aggressive — as 
mothers and nurses instinctively know. Battle cries like peekaboo* 
and 'bow-wow' pay guaranteed dividends, like the comedian's 
imitation of the lion's roar. As in every attack, the element of surprise 
plays an important part: the expert tickler's tactics never let the victim 
guess when and where the next pressure or pincer movement will occur. 
Experiments in tickling on babies under one year old showed that 
babies laughed fifteen times more often when tickled by their mothers 
than when they were tickled by strangers. For naturally the mock- 
attack will make the baby laugh only if it knows that it is a mock- 
attack; and with strangers one never knows. Even with its own mothf 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



8l 



there is an ever-so-slight feeling of uncertainty and apprehension, the 
expression of which alternates with laughter in the baby's behaviour; 
and it is precisely this element of apprehension between two tickles 
which is relieved in the laughter accompanying the squirm. The rule 
of the game is let me be just a little frightened so that I can enjoy the 
relief. 

Thus the mechanism is essentially the same as in comic impersona- 
tion: the tickler impersonates an aggressor, but is simultaneously known 
not to be one. It is probably the first situation encountered in life which 
makes the infant live on two planes at once, the first delectable ex- 
perience in bisociation — a foretaste of pleasures to come at the panto- 
mime show, of becoming a willing victim to the illusions of the stage, 
of being tickled by the horror-thriller. 

In adolescence, erotic elements enter into the game, and tickling 
assumes the role of a sexual mock-attack — acknowledged with 
giggles which betray their origin in infantile apprehensions. Some 
homosexuals claim to be extremely ticklish and display a tendency to 
squirming and wriggling as an expression of mock-fright. But these 
are secondary developments which partly iUuminate, partly confuse 
the original pattern — the tickled child's laughter is a discharge of 
apprehensions recognized as unfounded by the intellect. 

The Clown 

Most of the comic techniques I have discussed can be found in the 
repertory of the circus clown — the classic incarnation of the coarser 
type of humour. His face is a richly exaggerated caricature of stupidity, 
sometimes with an infectious grimace of laughter painted on it; in 
each piece of his apparel form battles against function; each of his 
movements is a parody of grace. He is the victim and perpetrator of 
preposterous practical jokes; he is both human and inert matter, for to 
survive all the slaps, whacks, and cracks, his skull must be made of 
ebony. He is the image in the distorting mirror, the clumsy imper- 
sonator of acrobats, ballet dancers, and fairies: Caliban imitating Ariel. 
He is a collection of deformities, bodily and functional; he stumbles 
over obstacles and words; he is timid, gauche, eccentric, and absent- 
minded. Above all, he is the man of gigantic efforts and diminutive 
accomplishments: the midwife who aids the mountain to deliver the 
mouse. 



82 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



The clown's domain is the coarse, rich, overt type of humour: he 
leaves nothing to be guessed, he piles it on. A good deal of the enjoy- 
ment he causes is a mild gloating, the discharge of sadistic, sexual, 
scatalogical impulses by way of the purifying channels of laughter. 
One means of producing and prolonging this effect is repetition. The 
clown and the clowning kind of music-hall comedian will tell, or act 
out, a long-drawn narrative in which the same type of flash, the same 
pattern, the same situation, the same key-words, recur again and 
again. Although repetition diminishes the effect of surprise, it has a 
cumulative effect on the emotive charge. The logical pattern is the 
same in each repeat, but new tension is easily drawn into the familiar 
channel. It is as if more and more liquid were being pumped into the 
same punctured pipeline. 



Originality, Emphasis, Economy 

I have discussed the logic of humour and its emotive dynamics, and 
have tried to indicate how to analyse a joke. But nothing has been said 
so far about the criteria which decide whether it is a good, bad, or 
indifferent joke. These are, of course, pardy a matter of personal taste, 
partly dependent on the technique of the humorist; only the second is 
our concern. 

There are, I shall suggest, three main criteria of comic technique: 
originality, emphasis, and economy. In the light of the previous 
chapters we shall expect them to play also a significant part in the 
techniques of scientific theorizing and artistic creation. 

An art dealer (this story is authentic) bought a canvas signed 
'Picasso' and travelled all the way to Cannes to discover whether it 
was genuine. Picasso was working in his studio. He cast a single look 
at the canvas and said: 'It's a fake'. 

A few months later the dealer bought another canvas signed 
Picasso. Again he travelled to Cannes and again Picasso, after a single 
glance, grunted: It's a fake.' 

'But cher mattre' expostulated the dealer, 'it so happens that I saw 
you with my own eyes working on this very picture several 
years ago.' 

Picasso shrugged: 'I often paint fakes.' 



VARIETIES OP HUMOUR 



83 



One measure of originality is its surprise effect. Picasso's reply — 
as the Marquis' in the Chamfort story — is truly unexpected; with its 
perverse logic, it cuts through the narrative like the blade of the 
guillotine. 

But creative originality is not so often met with either in art or in 
humour. One substitute for it is suggestiveness through emphasis. 
The cheap comedian piles it on; the competent craftsman plays in a 
subtler way on our memories and habits of thought. Whenever in the 
Contes Drolatiques Balzac introduces an abbe or a monk, our associa- 
tions race ahead of the narrative in the delectable expectation of some 
venal sin to be committed; yet when the point of the story is reached 
we still smile, sharing the narrator's mock-indignation and pretended 
surprise. In other words, anticipations of the type of joke or point to 
come do not entirely destroy the comic effect, provided that we do not 
know when and how exactly it will strike home. It is rather like a 
game: cover my eyes and I shall pretend to be surprised. Besides, the 
laughter provoked by spicy jokes is, as already said, only partly 
genuine, partly a cloak to cover publicly less demonstrable emotions 
— regardless whether the story in itself is comic or not. 

Suggestive techniques are essential; they create suspense and fac- 
ilitate the listener's flow of associations along habit-formed channels. 
A comic idea of a given logical pattern can be transposed into any 
number of different settings; local colour and dialect help to establish 
the atmosphere. The most effective stories are regional: Scottish, 
Marseilles, Cockney; the mere mention of 'a man from Aberdeen' 
establishes the matrix, the desired frame of mind. Thus suggestiveness 
depends firstly on the choice of relevant stimuli — as the biologist would 
say. Next, all non-essential elements should be omitted, even at the 
price of a certain sketchiness, otherwise attention will be sidetracked, 
the tension frittered away: this is the technique of simplification. In 
the third place the effect is increased by certain emphatic gestures, 
inflections, a stress on dialect and slang: in a word, by exaggeration. 
We have met these three related factors: selection, exaggeration, 
simplification, in the technique of the caricature (and of the portrait 
and blue-print); taken together they provide the means of high- 
lighting aspects of reality considered to be significant. It is not sur- 
prising that the same techniques enter into the artist's and humorist's 
efforts to communicate with his audience. 

However, except in the coarsest type of humour and the trashiest 
forms of art, ^suggestion. through emphasises not enough; and it can 



84 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



defeat its own purpose. It must be compensated by the opposite kind 
of virtue: the exercise of economy, or, more precisely: the technique of 
implication, 

Picasso's *I often paint fakes' is at the same time original, emphatic, 
and implicit. He does not say: * Sometimes, like other painters, I do 
something second-rate, repetitive, an uninspired variation on a theme, 
which after a while looks to me as if somebody had imitated my 
technique. It is true that this somebody happened to be myself, but 
that makes no difference to the quality of the picture, which is no 
better than if it were a fake; in fact you could call it that — an uninspired 
J Picasso apeing the style of the true Picasso.' 

None of this was said; all of it was implied. But the listener has to 
, work out by himself what is implied in the laconic hint; he has to make 
an imaginative effort to solve the riddle. If the answer were explicitly 
given, on the lines indicated in the previous paragraph, the listener 
would be both spared the effort and deprived of its reward; there would 
be no anecdote to tell. 

To a sophisticated audience any joke sounds stale if it is entirely 
explicit. If this is the case the listeners thoughts will move faster than 
tie narrator's tale or the unfolding of the plot; instead of tension it 
will generate boredom. 'Economy' in this sense means the use of 
hints in lieu of statements; instead of moving steadily on, the narrative 
jumps ahead, leaving logical gaps which the listener has to bridge by 
his own effort: he is forced to co-operate. 

The operation of bridging a logical gap by inserting the missing 
links is called interpolation. The series A, C, E, . . . K, M, O shows a 
gap which is filled by interpolating G and I. On the other hand, I can 
extend or extrapolate the series by adding to it R, T, V, etc. In the more 
sophisticated forms of humour the listener must always perform either 
or both of these operations before he can 'see the joke'. Take this 
venerable example, quoted by Freud: 

The Prince, travelling through his domains, noticed a man in the 
cheering crowd who bore a striking resemblance to himself. He 
beckoned him over and asked: 'Was your mother ever employed 
in my palace?' 

'No, Sire,' the man replied. 'But my father was.' 

The logical pattern of the story is quite primitive. Two implied 
codes of behaviour are brought into collision: feudal lords were 



VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 



85 



supposed to have bastards; feudal ladies were not supposed to have 
bastards; and there is a particularly neat, quasi-geometrical link pro- 
vided by the reversible symmetry of the situation. The mild amuse- 
ment which the story oiFers is partly derived from the malicious 
pleasure we take in the Prince's discomfiture; but mainly from the 
fact that it is put in the form of a riddle, of two oblique hints which the 
listener must complete under his own steam, as it were. The dotted 
lines in the figure below indicate the process (the arrow in M 1 may be 
taken to represent the Prince's question, the other arrow, the reply). 



I i 1 

4 


1 

I 

\-vntarpo(k 
extmpodi 


in* 

MM/ 

dm/ 




H F "P 

1111111 |T II Mill llli 


JiJi 



Figure 5 



Incidentally, Wilde has coined a terser variation on the same theme: 
'Lord Illingworth: "You should study the Peerage, Gerald. ... It is the 
best thing in fiction the English have ever done." ' 

Nearly all the stories that I have quoted show the technique of 
implication— the hint, the oblique allusion— in varying degrees: the 
good litde boy who loves his mama; the man who never aimed as 
high as that; the kind sadist, etc. Apart from inter- and extrapolation 
(there is no need for our purposes to make a distinction between them) 
a third type of operation is often needed to enable one to 'see the joke': 
transformation, or reinterpretation, of the given data into some analogous 
terms. These operations comprise the transformation of metaphorical 
into literal statements, of verbal hints into visual terms, and the in- 
terpretation of visual riddles of the New Yorker cartoon type. A good 



86 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



example ('good', I am afraid, only from a theoretical point of view) 
is provided by another story, quoted from Freud: 

Two shady business men have succeeded in making a fortune and 
were trying to elbow their way into Society. They had their portraits 
painted by a fashionable artist; framed in gold, these were shown at 
a reception in the grand style. Among the guests was a well-known 
art critic. The beaming hosts led him to the wall on which the two 
portraits were hanging side by side. The critic looked at them for a 
long time, then shook his head as if he were missing something. At 
length he pointed to the bare space between the pictures and asked: 
'And where is the Saviour?' 

A nice combination of transformation with interpolation. 

Economy, in humour as in art, does not mean mechanical brevity 
but implicitness. Implicit* is derived from the Latin word for 'folded 
in'. To make a joke like Picasso's 'unfold', the listener must fill in the 
gaps, complete the hints, trace the hidden analogies. Every good joke 
contains an element of the riddle — it may be childishly simple, or 
subtle and challenging — which the listener must solve. By doing so, 
he is lifted out of his passive role and compelled to co-operate, to 
repeat to some extent the process of inventing the joke, to re-create 
it in his imagination. The type of entertainment dished out by the mass 
media makes one apt to forget that true recreation is re-creation. 

Emphasis and implication are complementary techniques. The first 
bullies the audience into acceptance; the second entices it into mental 
collaboration; the first forces the offer down the consumer s throat; 
the second tantalizes, to whet his appetite. 

In fact, both techniques have their roots in the basic mechanisms of 
communicating thoughts by word or sign. Language itself is never 
completely explicit. Words have suggestive, evocative powers; but 
at the same time they are merely stepping stones for thought Economy 
means spacing them at intervals just wide enough to require a signi- 
ficant effort from the receiver of the message; the artist rules his sub- 
jects by turning them into accomplices. 

NOTE 

To p. 70. C£ the analysis of an Osbert Lancaster cartoon in Insight and 
Outlook, p. 80 f. 



IV 

FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 
Explosion and Catharsis 

Primitive jokes arouse crude, aggressive, or sexual emotions by 
means of a minimum of ingenuity. But even the coarse laughter 
in which these emotions are exploded often contains an additional 
element of admiration for the cleverness of the joke — and also of 
satisfaction with one's own cleverness in seeing the joke. Let us call this 
additional element of admiration plus self-congratulation the intellec- 
tual gratification offered by the joke. 

Satisfaction presupposes the existence of a need or appetite. Intellec- 
tual curiosity, the desire to understand, is derived from an urge as 
basic as hunger or sex: the exploratory drive (see below, XI, and 
Book Two, VIII). It is the driving power which makes the rat learn 
to find its way through the experimental maze without any obvious 
incentive being offered in the form of reward or punishment; and also 
the prime-mover behind human exploration and research. Its 'detached* 
and 'cttsmtejrested' character — the scientists' self-transcending absorption 
hi the riddles of nature — is, of course, often combined with ambition, 
competition, vanity. But these self-assertive tendencies must Be restrained 
and highly sublimated to find fulfilment in the mostly unspectacular 
rewards of his slow and patient labours. There are, after all, more direct 
methods of asserting one's ego than the analysis of ribonucleic acids. 

When I called discovery the emotionally 'neutral' art I did not mean 
by neutrality the absence of emotion — which would be equivalent to 
apathy — but that nicely balanced and sublimated blend of motivations, 
where self-assertiveness is harnessed to the task; and where on the other 
hand heady speculations about the Mysteries of Nature must be 
submitted to the rigours of objective verification. 

We shall see that there are two sides to the manifestation of emotions 
at the moment of discovery, which reflect this polarity of motivations. 

87 



88 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



One is the triumphant explosion of tension which has suddenly become 
redundant since the problem is solved — so you jump out of your bath 
and run through the streets laughing and shouting Eureka! In the 
second place there is the slowly fading after-glow, the gradual catharsis 
of the self-transcending emotions — a quiet, contemplative delight in 
the truth which the discovery revealed, closely related to the artist's 
experience of beauty. The Eureka cry is the explosion of energies which 
must find an oudet since the purpose for which they have been 
mobilized no longer exists; the carthartic reaction is an inward un- 
folding of a kind of 'oceanic feeling*, and its slow ebbing away. The 
first is due to the fact that T made a discovery; the second to the fact 
that a discovery has been made, a fraction of the infinite revealed. The 
first tends to produce a state of physical agitation related to laughter; 
the second tends towards quietude, the 'earthing' of emotion, some- 
times a peaceful overflow of tears. The reasons for this contrast will be 
discussed later; for the time being, let us remember that, physiologically 
speaking, the self-assertive tendencies operate through the massive 
sympadiico-adrenal system which galvanizes the body into activity — 
whereas the sel£transcending emotions have no comparable trigger- 
mechanism at their disposal, and their bodily manifestations are in 
every respect the opposite of the former: pulse and breathing are 
slowed down, the muscles relax, the whole organism tends towards 
tranquillity and catharsis. Accordingly, this class of emotions is devoid 
of the inertial momentum which makes the rage-fear type of reactions 
so often fall out of step with reasoning; the participatory emotions do 
not become dissociated from thought. Rage is immune to understand- 
ing; love of the self-transcending variety is based on understanding, 
and cannot be separated from it. 

Thus the impact of a sudden, bisociative surprise which makes 
reasoning perform a somersault will have a twofold effect: part of the 
tension will become detached from it and exploded while the remain- 
ing part will slowly ebb away. The symbols 



Figure 6 ~ 
on the triptych are meant to refer to these two modes of the discharge 



FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 



8 9 



of tension: the explosion of the aggressive-defensive and the gradual 
catharsis, or 'earthing', of the participatory emotions. 

'Seeing the Joke' and 'Solving the Problem* 

The dual manifestation of emotions at the moment of discovery is 
reflected on a minor and trivial scale in our reactions to a clever joke. 
The pleasant after-glow of admiration and intellectual satisfaction, 
gradually fading, reflects the cathartic reaction; while the self-con- 
gratulatory impulse — a faint echo of the Eureka cry — supplies added 
voltage to the original charge detonated in laughter: that 'sudden 
glory* (as Hobbes has it) 'arising out of our own eminency'. 

Let our imagination travel once more across the triptych of creative 
activities, from left to right, as it were. We can do this as we have seen, 
by taking a short-cut from one wing to another, from the comic to the 
tragic or sublime; or alternatively by following the gradual transitions 
which lead from the left to the centre panel. 

On the extreme left of the continuum — the infra-red end of the 
emotive spectrum — we found the practical joke, the smutty story, the 
lavatory humour of children, each with a heavy aggressive or sexual or 
scatalogical load (which may be partly unconscious) ; and with a logical 
structure so obvious that it required only a minimum of intellectual 
effort to 'see the joke*. Put into a formula, we could say that the ratio 
A : I — where A stands for crude emotion, and I for intellectual stimu- 
lation — is heavily loaded in favour of the former. 

As we move across the panel towards the right, this ratio changes, and 
is ultimately reversed. In the higher forms of comedy, satire, and irony 
the message is couched in implicit and oblique terms; the joke gradually 
assumes the character of an epigram or riddle, the witticism becomes a 
challenge to our wits: 

'Psychoanalysis is the disease for which it pretends to be the cure/ 

'Philosophy is the systematic abuse of a terminology specially 
invented for that purpose/ 

'Statistics are like a bikini. What they reveal is suggestive. What they 
conceal is vital/ 

Or, Heine's description of a young virgin: 

'Her face is like a palimpsest — beneath the Gothic lettering of the 
monk's sacred text lurks the pagan poet's hahveffaced erotic verse/ 
The crude aggression of the practical joke has been sublimated into 



90 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



malicious ingenuity; gross sexuality into subtle eroticism. Incidentally, 
if I had not mentioned that the last quotation was by Heine, whose 
name combined with 'virgin arouses ominous expectations, but had 
pretended instead that it was from a novel by D. H. Lawrence, it would 
probably have impressed the reader as profoundly poetic instead of 
malicious — a short-cut from wing to wing, by reversal of the charge 
from minus to plus. Again, imagine for a moment that the quotation 
occurred in an essay by a Jungian psychologist — and it will turn into an 
emotionally neutral illustration of 'the intrusion of archetypes into 
perception. 

In cases like this the wording of the narrative (or the picture on the 
canvas) can remain unaltered, and its transformation from a comic into 
a poetic or intellectually enlightening message depends entirely on the 
subjective attitude of the percipient.* However, the lines of correspon- 
dence across the panels are meant to indicate more general patterns of 
creative activity. Thus, as we move from coarse humour towards the 
neutral zone, we find the bisociation of sound and meaning first exempli- 
fied in the pun, then in word games (ranging from the crossword 
puzzle to the decyphering of the Rosetta stone); lastly in alliteration, 
asonance, and rhyme. The mind-matter theme we found expressed in 
countless variations on all three panels; and each variation of it — the 
puppet on strings or Jack-in-the-Box — was again seen as tri-valent. 
Impersonation is used both in comedy and tragedy; but in between them 
the medicine man in his mask, the cassocked priest in the confessional, 
the psychiatrist in the role of the father, each impersonate a person or 
power other than himself. The distorting mirror, with its emphasis on 
one significant aspect to the exclusion of others, is used alike in the 
caricature and in the scientist's diagrams and schemata; when Clavdia in 
the Magic Mountain offers her lover an X-ray portrait of her chest as a 
souvenir we hardly know on which of the three panels we are. Nor can 
we draw a sharp line between social satire and sociological discovery: 
Animal Farm and 1 984 taught a whole generation more about the nature 
of totalitarianism than academic science did. One last example: 

In i960 an anecdote in the form of an imaginary dialogue circulated 
in the satellite countries of the East: 

*Te51 me, Comrade, what is capitalism?' 

'The exploitation of man by man/ 

'And what is Communism?' 

'The reverse.' 



FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 



91 



The double entendre on reverse* — 'it pretends to be the opposite, but it 
comes down to the same, only the exploiting is done by a different 
gang' — casts a new, sharp light on a hoary problem; it has the same 
power of sudden iMumination as an epigram by Voltaire. 

Similar borderline cases are brain-twisters, logical paradoxes, 
mathematical games. Even chess problems can be both 'witty* and 
'funny' if they contain some sudden reversal of logic, an ironical twist, 
or an affront to chess common sense; the connoisseur will smile, or even 
laugh, when he is shown the solution, and the tension suddenly snaps. 
His laughter may signify 'how stupid of me not to have seen it* or 'not 
to have seen it at once' or 'how clever of me', etc. To distinguish 
between these cases would be splitting hairs, for the basic process is the 
same: the tension has been dissociated from its original purpose and 
must find some other oudet. When the string of the guitar snaps it 
gives out a twang — for precisely the same reason. 

But this tension is no longer comparable to the emotions aroused in 
the grosser types of humour. The intellectual challenge, which in the 
coarse joke played such a subsidiary part, now dominates the picture; 
the A : I ratio has been reversed. There may be vanity and competitive- 
ness in rising to the challenge; but they are sublimated and held in 
balance by a self-forgetting absorption in the problem. 

As we cross the fluid boundary leading into the central panel of the 
triptych, the task of 'seeing the joke* becomes the task of 'solving the 
problem*. And when we succeed we no longer roar with laughter as at 
the clowns antics; laughter gradually shades into an amused, then an 
admiring smile — reflecting the harmonic balance of opposites, the 
sudden glory and quiet glow of intellectual satisfaction. 

The Creation of Humour 

Up to now I have been discussing the effects of humour on the 
audience: the reader, listener, spectator. Let me turn from the con- 
sumer's reactions to the processes which go in on the mind of the 
producer — the inventor of the joke, the creator of humour. 

Humour depends primarily on its surprise effect: the bisociative 
shock. To cause surprise the humorist must have a modicum of 
originality — the ability to break away from the stereotyped routines of 
thought. Caricaturist, satirist, the writer of nonsense-humour, and even 
the expert tickler, each operates on more than one plane. Whether his 



92 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



purpose is to convey a social message, or merely to entertain, he must 
provide mental jolts, caused by the collision of incompatible matrices. 
To any given situation or subject he must conjure up an appropriate — 
or appropriately inappropriate — intruder which will provide the jolt. 

The first schoolboy to have the idea of sawing through the legs of 
the master's chair must have been a genius (such practices were not 
uncommon in my school-days in Hungary). His habitual outlets for 
aggression being barred by the heavy penalties they would entail, he 
must have been labouring under a creative stress which initiated his 
search for an original solution of his problem. A chance observation — 
like the fall of Newton's apple — may have provided the link to a 
different frame of reference, where the object of his resentment was 
merely a mass subject to the pull of gravity. Now all he had to do was 
to transfer the scene of operations from the blocked matrix M 2 to this 
auxiliary matrix M 2 . If this sounds facetious let us remember that 
Bergson's theory of humour is based on this single facet. 

In all forms of malicious wit there is an aggressive tendency at work 
which, for one reason or another, cannot be satisfied by the usual 
methods of reasoned argument, physical violence, or straight invective. 
I shall call a matrix 'blocked' when its rules of the game' prove in- 
applicable to the existing situation or problem in hand; when none of 
the various ways of exercising a skill, however plastic and adaptable 
that skill is, leads to the desired goal. The young officer in the Viennese 
anecdote, resenting the courtesan's pretentious reply, is in the same 
position as the frustrated schoolboy: he cannot reply: 'Come off the 
high horse, I know that cash is all that matters to you,' without incur- 
ring the penalties of vulgarity. Chamfort's Marquis cannot kill the 
Bishop — it would be an unpardonable lack of savoir-faire. Picasso 
cannot tell the dealer that he is an insufferable bore who does not know 
a Kokoschka from a Klee; that would be unkind. 

But how do they discover the inspired reposte which saves the 
situation? It sounds a simple question, but if psychology knew the 
answer to it there would be no point in writing this book. 

As a first step let us note a trivial fact: the officer's mental leap from 
the metaphorical to the literal plane indicates a phenomenon already 
discussed: the displacement of attention to a seemingly irrelevant feature 
— in this case from the poetic connotations of the lady's heart to its 
concrete spatial location. (We remember that Wilde used a similar 
displacement effect for a different purpose in 'How else but through a 
broken heart . . .'). The Marquis achieves his aim— to kill by ridicule— 



FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 



93 



by transferring his attention from the glaringly obvious consideration 
that the Bishop is usurping his privileges, to an irrelevant side-line — that 
he is doing another man's job; as if the issue were a demarcation dispute 
between the Boilermakers' and the Shipwrights' Unions on who should 
drill the holes. 

Thus in some of the cases we have discussed, the solution is arrived 
at by a kind of 'thinking aside', a shift of attention to some feature of 
the situation, or an aspect of the problem, which was previously 
ignored, or only present on the fringes of awareness. The humorist 
may stumble on it by chance; or, more likely, guided by some intuition 
which he is unable to define. This gives us a first intimation of un- 
conscious processes intervening in the creative act. The humorist's 
achievement, represented on the neat diagrams in previous chapters, 
appears as an exercise in pure intellectual geometry: 'Construct two 
planes inclined at a given angle and generate two curves which intersect 
in a given point.' In actual fact, however, the bisociative act, in humour 
as in other branches of creativity, depends in varying degrees on 
assistance from fringe-conscious or unconscious processes. Picasso's 
illuminating grunt was certainly inspired by a process of this kind. On 
the other hand, the mediocre cartoonist and other professional crafts- 
men of the comic operate mostly with the same familiar matrices, fixed 
at a given angle, as it were, governed by familiar rules of the game; and 
their task is reduced to devising new links — puns, gags, pegs for 
parody. It is a mechanized kind of bisociative technique, which also has 
its practitioners in science and art. 



Paradox and Synthesis 

There is an obvious contrast between the emotive reactions of creator 
and consumer: the person who invents the joke or comic idea seldom 
laughs in the process. The creative s tress under which he labours is not 
of the same kind as T fe~emotIons aroused in t£e~aucUence. He is 
cngage3 in an intellectual exercise, a feat of mental acrobatics; even if 
motivated by sheer venom it must be distilled and sublimated. Once he 
has hit on the idea and worked out the logical structure, the basic 
pattern of the joke, he uses his tricks of the trade— suspense, emphasis, 
implication — to work up the audience's emotions; and to make these 
explode in laughter when he springs his surprise-effect on them. 
Now the humorist may also experience surprise at the moment 



94 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



when the idea hits him — particularly if it was generated by the un- 
conscious. But there is a basic difference between a shock imposed from 
outside and a quasi sel£adniinistered shock. The humorist has solved 
his problem by joining two incompatible matrices together in a para- 
doxical synthesis. His audience, on the other hand, has its expectations 
shattered and its reason affronted by the impact of the second matrix 
on the first; instead of fusion there is collision; and in the mental dis- 
array which ensues, emotion, deserted by reason, is flushed out in 
laughter. 

In the humorist's mind no such divorce occurs; he has nothing to 
laugh about. At most he may, at the moment of inspiration, hit his 
desk: 'I have got it.' But the creative stress which is relieved in such 
minor gestures, symbolic of victory, of opposition vanquished, is of a 
sublimated nature — quite unlike the more primitive emotions puffed 
away in the massive laughter of the audience. The contrast is further 
illustrated in situations where a person fails to find the solution of a 
brain-teaser — and, on being told it, starts hitting, not the desk, but his 
own benighted head. The redundant tension is worked off in a sym- 
bolic gesture of self-punishment — again a more specific oudet for 
energies harnessed to intellectual tasks, than the laughter-channels of 
least resistance. 

The less suggestive and the more implicit the joke, the more will the 
consumer's reactions approximate the producer's — whose mental 
effort he is compelled to re-create. When the witticism is transformed 
into epigram, and teasing into challenge, the overflow reflex for 
primitive emotions is no longer needed, and de-tension assumes more 
individualized and sophisticated forms; the roar of Homeric laughter is 
superseded by Archimedes's piercing cry or Kepler's holy ravings. 

The creative act of the humorist consisted in bringing about a 
momentary fusion between two habitually incompatible matrices, 
i Scientific discovery, as we shall presendy see, can be described in very 
similar terms — as the permanent fusion of matrices of thought previ- 
ously believed to be incompatible. Until the seventeenth century the 
Copernican hypothesis of the earth's motion was considered as 
obviously incompatible with commonsense experience; it was accord- 
ingly treated as a huge joke by the majority of Galileo's contemporaries. 
One of them, a famous wit, wrote: 'The disputes of Signor Galileo 
have dissolved into alchemical smoke. So here we are at last, safely 
back on a solid earth, and we do not have to fly with it as so many ants 
crawling around a balloon.* 1 



PROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 



95 



The history of science abounds with examples of discoveries greeted 
with howls of laughter because they seemed to be a marriage of in- 
compatibles — until the marriage bore fruit and the alleged incompati- 
bility of the partners turned out to derive from prejudice. The humorist, 
on the other hand, deliberately chooses discordant codes of behaviour 
or universes of discourse to expose their hidden incongruities in the 
resulting clash. Comicdiscovery is paradox stated— scientific discovery 
is paradox resolved. 

gut here again we find, instead of a cleiu:.j3iyiding line, ^continuous 
transitions. The paradoxes of Achilles and the Tortoise, or of the Cretan 
Liar, have, during two millennia, tickled philosophers and teased 
mathematicians into creative efforts; and Juvenal's 67 Natura negaujacit 
indignatio versum remains as true as ever. 

Summary 

I have started this inquiry with an analysis of humour because it is 
the only domain of creative activity where a complex pattern of 
intellectual stimulation elicits a sharply defined response in the nature 
of a physiological reflex. 

The pattern underlying all varieties of humour is 'bisociative' — 
perceiving a situation or event in two habitually incompatible associa- 
tive contexts. This causes an abrupt transfer of the train of thought from 
one matrix to another governed by a different logic or 'rule of the 
game'. But certain emotions, owing to their greater inertia and per- 
sistence, cannot follow such nimble jumps of thought; discarded by 
reason, they are worked off along channels of least resistance in 
laughter. 

The emotions in question are those of the self-assertive, aggressive- 
defensive type, which are based on the sympathico-adrenal system and 
tend to beget bodily activity. Their counter-parts are the participatory 
or self-transcending emotions — compassion, identification, raptness — 
which are mediated by physiological processes of a different type, and 
tend to discharge not in laughter but in tears. As a rule our emotions 
are a rnixture of both; but even in the more subtle or affectionate 
varieties of humour, an element of aggression — a drop of adrenalin — 
must be present to trigger off the reaction. Laughter is a luxury reflex 
which could arise only in a creature whose reason has gained a 
degree of autonomy from the urges of emotion, and enables him to 



96 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



perceive his own emotions as redundant — to realize that he has been 
fooled. 

After applying the theory to various types of the comic, I discussed 
the criteria of the humorist's technique: originality or unexpectedness; 
emphasis through selection, exaggeration and simplification; and 
economy or implicitness which calls for extrapolation, interpolation 
and transposition. 

The term 'matrix' was introduced to refer to any skill or ability, to 
any pattern of activity governed by a set of rules — its 'code'. All 
ordered behaviour, from embryonic development to verbal thinking, 
is controlled by 'rules of the game', which lend it coherence and 
stability, but leave it sufficient degrees of freedom for flexible strategies 
adapted to environmental conditions. The ambiguity of the term 'code' 
('code of laws' — 'coded message*) is deliberate, and reflects a character- 
istic property of the nervous system: to control all bodily activities by 
means of coded signals. 

The concept of matrices with fixed codes and adaptable strategies, 
proposed as a unifying formula, appears to be equally applicable to 
perceptual, cognitive, and motor skills and to the psychological 
structures variously called 'frames of reference*, 'associative contexts', 
'universes of discourse', mental 'sets', or 'schemata', etc. The validity of 
the formula will be tested in the chapters which follow, on various 
levels from morphogenesis to symbolic thought. 

Matrices vary from fully automatized skills to those with a high 
degree of plasticity; but even the latter are controlled by rules of the 
game which function below the level of awareness. These silent codes 
can be regarded as condensations of learning into habit. Habits are the 
indispensable core of stability and ordered behaviour; they also have a 
tendency to become mechanized and to reduce man to the status of a 
conditioned automaton. The creative act, by co nnecting previous ly 
unrelated dimensions of ex perience, enaTfl eTnim to attain to a higher 
lev^rc7m"ental evo IuttonTiris ; an ."act of liberation — the defeat of habit 
byS3g!naTity? fE ~~~ """"* * 



NOTES 

To p. po. This, of course, equally applies to pictures. The same Rubens 
nude will call forth different responses from a schoolboy, an art critic, and a nun. 
In the National Gallery in Vienna there was once to be seen an admirable Leda of 
the Venetian school, which bore the inscription: Nackend Weib von boser Gam 
Gebissen (Naked Wench Bitten by Angry Goose). 



FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 



97 



To. p. 96. As this book was nearing completion, Professor Burt kindly 
brought to my attention a paper he wrote on "The Psychology of Laughter' for 
a seminar of his post-graduate students, in which he had come to somewhat 
similar conclusions: 

'Laughter may be regarded as providing a safety-valve for the overflow of 
emotional energy, instinctively excited by the perception of some specific situa- 
tion which automatically tends to stimulate the instinct, but which on closer 
examination is seen not to require energetic action. . . . Every stimulus to laughter 
thus involves a double-entendre: there is first the superficial or manifest meaning 
which tends to arouse an emotion appropriate to some serious situation (and 
thus momentarily disturbing equilibrium), and secondly the deeper or latent 
meaning (which contradicts the first impression); and the outlet of laughter is 
provided to give immediate relief to the superfluous emotional excitement. . . .* 
(Burt, 1945). 



■ 



PART TWO 

THE SAGE 



V 

MOMENTS OF TRUTH 

The Chimpanzee and the Stick 

That animals can display originality and inventiveness has been 
asserted since Aesop, but experimentally demonstrated for the 
first time by the German psychologist Wolfgang Kohler. In 
19 1 8 Kohler published The Mentality of Apes, an account of his experi- 
ments with chimpanzees on TenerifFe, which has since become a classic. 
Here is a characteristic description of an animal discovering the use of 
tools (my italics): 

Nueva, a young female chimpanzee, was tested 3 days after her 
arrival (nth March, 1914). She had not yet made the acquaintance of 
the other ammals but remained isolated in a cage. A little stick is 
introduced into her cage; she scrapes the ground with it, pushes the 
banana skins together in a heap, and then carelessly drops the stick 
at a distance of about three-quarters of a metre from the bars. Ten 
minutes later, fruit is placed outside the cage beyond her reach. She 
grasps at it, vainly of course, and then begins the characteristic 
complaint of the chimpanzee: she thrusts both lips — especially the 
lower — forward, for a couple of inches, gazes imploringly at the 
observer, utters whimpering sounds, and finally flings herself on to 
the ground on her back — a gesture most eloquent of despair, which 
may be observed on other occasions as well. Thus, between 
lamentations and entreaties, some time passes, until — about seven 
minutes after the fruit has been exhibited to her — she suddenly casts 
a look at the stick, ceases her moaning, seizes the stick, stretches it out 
of the cage, and succeeds, though somewhat clumsily, in drawing the 
bananas within arm's length. Moreover, Nueva at once puts the end of 
her stick behind and beyond her objective. The test is repeated after an 
hour's interval; on this second occasion, the ariimal has recourse to 

xox 



102 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the stick much sooner, and uses it with more skill; and at a third 
repetition, the stick is used immediately, as on all subsequent 
occasions. 1 

It is obvious that Nueva was not led to her discovery by any process 
of conditioning, or trial and error. Her behaviour from the moment 
when her eyes fell on the stick was, in Kohler's words, 'unwaveringly 
purposeful' : she seized the stick, carried it without hesitation to the bars, 
stretched it out of the cage, and placed it behind the banana — a 
smooth, integrated sequence of actions, quite different from the erratic, 
hit-and-miss behaviour of rats trying to find their way through a maze, 
or cats trying to get out of a puzzle-box. It was an original, self-taught 
accomplishment, which had no precedent in the chimpanzee's past. The 
process which led to her discovery can be described as a synthesis of two 
previously unconnected skills, acquired in earlier life. In the first place, 
Nueva had learned to get at bananas outside her cage by squeezing an 
arm or foot through the bars; the ensemble of variations of this simple 
skill constitutes matrix number one. She had also acquired the habit — 
matrix number two — of scraping the earth with a stick and of pushing 
objects about with it. But in this playful activity the stick was never 
used for any utilitarian purpose; to throw, push, or roll things about is 
a habit common to a variety of young animals. Nueva's discovery 
consisted in applying this playful habit as an auxiliary matrix to get at 
the banana. The moment of truth occurred when Nueva's glance fell 
on the stick while her attention was set on the banana. At that moment 
the two previously separate matrices fused into one, and the 'stick to 
play with* became a 'rake to reach with' — an implement for obtaining 
otherwise unobtainable objects. 

Like many other discoveries, Nueva's seems a simple and obvious 
one — but only after the fact. A dog, for instance, will carry a stick 
between his teeth, but he will never learn to use it as a rake. Moreover, 
chimpanzees are not the only species which finds it difficult to apply a 
'playful* technique to a utilitarian purpose with which it had not been 
connected in previous experience; a number of discoveries in the 
history of human science consisted in just that. Galileo astonished the 
world when he turned the telescopic toys, invented by Dutch opticians, 
to astronomic use; the invention of the steam engine as a mechanical 
toy by Hero of Alexandria in the second century B.C. had to wait two 
thousand years before it was put to practical use; the geometry of conic 
sections which Apollonius of Perga had studied in the fourth century 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



103 



B.C. just for the fun of it, gave Kepler, again two thousand years later, 
his elliptical orbits of the planets; the passion for dice of the Chevalier 
de Mere, made him approach Pascal for advice on a safe gambling 
system, and thus was the theory of probability born, that indispensable 
tool of modern physics and biology, not to mention the insurance 
business. 'It is remarkable', wrote Laplace, 'that a science which began 
with considerations of play has risen to the most important objects of 
human knowledge.' Thus at the very start of our inquiry we hit on a 
pattern — the discovery that a playful or Vart pour Van technique 
provides an unexpected clue to problems in a quite different field — 
which is one of the leitmotifs in the history of science. 

Nueva's discovery was the use of tools; the next one to be described 
is the making of tools. Its hero is Sultan, the genius among Kohler's 
chimpanzees: 

(17.2. 1914) Beyond some bars, out of arm's reach, lies an objective 
[a banana]; on this side, in the background of the experiment room, 
is placed a sawn-off castor-oil bush, whose branches can be easily 
broken off. It is impossible to squeeze the tree through the railings, on 
account of its awkward shape; besides, only one of the bigger apes 
could drag it as far as the bars. Sultan is let in, does not immediately 
see the objective, and, looking about him indifferently, sucks one of 
the branches of the tree. But, his attention having been drawn to the 
objective, he approaches the bars, glances outside, the next moment 
turns round, goes straight to the tree, seizes a thin slender branch, 
breaks it off with a sharp jerk, runs back to the bars, and attains the 
objective. From the turning round upon the tree up to the grasping 
of the fruit with the broken-off branch, is one single quick chain of 
action, without the least 'hiatus', and without the slightest movement 
that does not, objectively considered, fit into the solution described. 2 

Had Sultan known Greek he would certainly have shouted Eureka! 
Kohler comments: 

For adult man with his mechanized methods of solution, proof is 
sometimes needed, as here, that an action was a real achievement, not 
something self-evident; that the breaking off a branch from a whole 
tree, for instance, is an achievement over and above the simple use of a 
stick, is shown at once by animals less gifted than Sultan, even when 
they understand the use of sticks beforehand. 3 



104 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



It has been said that discovery consists in seeing an analogy which 
nobody had seen before. Solomon discovered the analogy between the 
Shulamite's neck and a tower of ivory. Sultan discovered that a 
twisted branch on a tree with leaves on it had something in common 
with a straight, lifeless bamboo-pole lying on the ground. What they 
had in common was very little: let us say that both looked 'hardish' and 
longish', but that is all. The branch, which previously was part and 
parcel of the tree, was wrenched out of its visual context — both 
figuratively and literally speaking — and made into a part of another, 
functional, context. 

The now familiar shift of awareness to the previously unimportant 
'pole-like* aspect of the branch was very prettily demonstrated by 
another of Kohler's chimpanzees, Koko. It took Koko much longer 
to make the same discovery as Sultan; and when at last he had broken 
off a branch from the tree to use it as a stick, and marched with it 
towards the banana outside the cage, he: 

eagerly picked off one leaf after the other, so that only the long, bare 
stem was left . . . The pulling off of the leaves is both correct and 
incorrect; incorrect because it does not make the stem any longer, 
correct because it makes its length show up better and the stem thus 
becomes optically more like a stick. . . . There can be no doubt that 
Koko did not pull off the leaves in play only; his look and his move- 
ments prove distinctly that throughout the performance his attention 
is wholly concentrated on the banana; he is merely concerned now 
with preparing the implement. Play looks quite different; and I have 
never seen a chimpanzee play while (like Koko in this case) he was 
showing himself distinctly intent upon his ultimate purpose. 4 

Before the chimpanzee actually broke off the branch there must 
have been a moment when he perceived it as a member of both matrices 
at the same time — still a part of the tree but already a detached tool. Thus 
one could say that Sultan had seen a visual pun: a single form (the 
branch) attached to two different functions. 

The act of discovery has a disruptive and a constructive aspect. It 
must disrupt rigid patterns of mental organization to achieve the new , 
synthesis. Sultan's habitual way of looking at the tree as a coherent, j 
visual whole had to be shattered. Once he had discovered that branches 
can be made into tools he never again forgot it, and we may assume 
that a tree never again looked the same to him as before. He had lost 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



105 



the innocence of his vision, but from this loss he derived an immense 
gain: the perception of 'branches' and the manipulation of 'tools' were 
now combined into a single, sensory-motor skill; and when two 
matrices have become integrated they cannot again be torn asunder. 
This is why the discoveries of yesterday are the commonplaces of today, 
and why we always marvel how stupid we were not to see what pos^ 
factum appears to be so obvious. 



Archimedes 

Let me illustrate the last point by a human discovery which has much 
in common with Sultan's: the Principle of Archimedes. I must tell the 
story in a somewhat simplified form. 

Hiero, tyrant of Syracuse and protector of Archimedes, had been 
given a beautiful crown, allegedly of pure gold, but he suspected that 
it was adulterated with silver. He asked Archimedes's opinion. 
Archimedes knew, of course, the specific weight of gold — that is to 
say, its weight per volume unit. If he could measure the volume of the 
crown he would know immediately whether it was pure gold or not; 
but how on earth is one to determine the volume of a complicated 
ornament with all its filigree work? Ah, if only he could melt it down 
and measure the liquid gold by the pint, or hammer it into a brick of 
honest rectangular shape, or . . . and so on. At this stage he must have 
felt rather like Nueva, flinging herself on her back and uttering 
whimpering sounds because the banana was out of her grasp and the 
road to it blocked. 

Blocked situations increase stress. Under its pressure the chimpanze e 
reverts to erratic and repetitive! random a ttemp ts ; in Archimedes's ca se 
we can imagine his th oughts movin g round in circles w itHn the frame 
o f his geometricalTaiowle d ge; and finding all approaches to th e target 
Socked, returning again and again to the starting point. This 
frustrating situation, familiar to everybody trying to solve a difficult 
problem, may be schematized as in the following diagram, where 'S' 
represents the starting point, the loops are trains of thought within the 
blocked matrix, and "T represents the target (that is: a method of 
measuring the volume of the crown') — which, unfortunately, is 
located outside the plane of the matrix. 

One day, while getting into his bath, Archimedes watched absent- 
rnindedly the familiar sight of the water-level rising from one smudge 




Figure 7 



on the basin to the next as a result of the immersion of his body, and 
it occurred to him in a flash that the volume of water displaced was 
equal to the volume of the immersed parts of his own body — which 
therefore could simply be measured by the pint. He had melted his 
body down, as it were, without harming it, and he could do the same 
with the crown. 

Once more, as in the case of the chimpanzee, the matter is childishly 
simple after the fact — but let us try to put ourselves in Archimedes's 
place. He was in the habit of taking a daily bath, but the experiences 
and ideas associated with it moved along habit-beaten tracks: the 
sensations of hot and cold, of fatigue and relaxation, and a pretty slave- 
girl to massage his limbs. Neither to Archimedes nor to anybody else 
before him had it ever occurred to connect the sensuous and trivial 
occupation of taking a hot bath with the scholarly pursuit of the 
measurement of solids. No doubt he had observed many times that the 
level of the water rose whenever he got into it; but this fact, and the 
distance between the two levels, was totally irrelevant to him — until it 
'suddenly became bisociated with his problem. At that instant he 
realized that the amount of rise of the water-level was a simple measure 
of the volume of his own complicated body. 
The discovery may now be schematized as follows (Figure 8): 
M x is the same as in the preceding diagram, governed by the habitual 
rules of the game, by means of which Archimedes originally tried to 
solve the problem; M 2 is the matrix of associations related to taking a 
bath; m 2 represents the actual train of thought which effects die 
connection. The Link L may have been a verbal concept (for instance: 

106 









II 

1 


1 III 

1 1? 

IL 


-T rr 

. : 


a 

11/ 


Z^C§^ Kid 




III 


III 


fl 


ii' 1 


! liil 



Figure 8 



'rise of water-level qw<ik melting down of my solid body!); it may 
equally well have been a visual impression in which the water-level 
was suddenly seen to correspond to the volume of the immersed parts 
of the body and hence to that of the crown — whose image was 
constandy lurking on the fringe of his consciousness. The essential 
point is, that at the critical moment both matrices M t and M 2 were 
simultaneously active in Archimedes's mind — though presumably on 
different levels of awareness. The creative stress resulting from the 
blocked situation had kept the problem on the agenda even while the 
beam of consciousness was drifting along quite another plane. With- 
out this constant pressure, the favourable chance-constellation would 
have passed unnoticed— and joined the legion of man's missed 
opportunities for a creative departure from the stale habits of thought 
which numb his mental powers. 

The sequel to the discovery is well known; because of its picturesque A 
appeal I shall occasionally refer to discovery in its psychological aspect 
as the 'Eureka process' or 'Eureka act'. 

Let us look at Archimedes's discovery from a different angle. 
When one climbs into a bath one knows that the water-level will 
rise owing to its displacement by the body, and that there must be as 
much water displaced as there is body immersed; moreover, one 
mechanically estimates the amount of water to be let into the bath 
because of this expectation. Archimedes, too, must have known all this 

107 



io8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



— but he had probably never before verbalized, that is, consciously 
formulated that bit of knowledge. Yet implicitly it was there as part of 
his mental equipment; it was, so to speak, included in the code of 
rules of bath-taking behaviour. Now we have seen that the rules which 
govern the matrix of a skill function on a lower level of awareness than 
the actual performance itself— whether it is playing the piano, carrying 
on a conversation, or taking a bath. We have also seen that the 
bisociative shock often has the effect of making such implicit rules 
explicit, of suddenly focussing awareness on aspects of experience 
which had been unverbalized, unconsciously implied, taken for 
granted; so that a familiar and unnoticed aspect of a phenomenon — like 
the rise of the water-level — is suddenly perceived at an unfamiliar and 
significant angle. Discovery often means simply the uncovering of 
something which has always been there but was hidden from the eye 
by the blinkers of habit. 

This equally applies to the discoveries of the artist who makes us see 
familiar objects and events in a strange, new, revealing light — as if 
piercing the cataract which dims our vision. Newton's apple and 
Cezanne's apple are discoveries more closely related than they seem. 

Chance and Ripeness 

Nearly all of Kohler's chimpanzees sooner or later learned the use of 
implements, and also certain methods of making implements. But a dog, 
however skilful in carrying a stick or a basket around, will never learn 
to use the stick to get a piece of meat placed outside its reach. We might 
say that the chimpanzees were ripe to discover the use of tools when a 
favourable chance-opportunity presented itself— such as a stick lying 
around just when needed. The factors which (among others) constitute 
ripeness for this type of discovery are the primates' manual dexterity 
and advanced oculo-motor co-ordination, which enable them to 
develop the playful habit of pushing objects about with branches and 
sticks. Each of the separate skills, whose synthesis constitutes the new 
discovery, was well established previously and frequently exercised. In 
a similar way Archimedes's mental skill in manipulating abstract 
concepts like volume and density, plus his acute powers of observation, 
even of trivia, made him 'ripe' for his discovery. In more general terms: 
the statistical probability for a relevant discovery to be made is the 
greater the more firmly established and well exercised each of the still 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



109 



separate skills, or thought-matrices, are. This explains a puzzling but 
recurrent phenomenon in the history of science: that the same discovery 
is made, more or less at the same time, by two or more people; and it 
may also help to explain the independent development of the same 
techniques and similar styles of art in different cultures. 

Ripeness in this sense is, of course, merely a necessary, not a sufficient, 
condition of discovery. But it is not quite such an obvious concept as 
it might seem. The embittered controversies between different schools 
in experimental psychology about the nature of learning and under- 
standing can be shown to derive to a large extent from a refusal to take 
the factor of ripeness seriously. The propounders of Behaviouristic 
psychology were wont to set their animals tasks for which they were 
biologically ill-fitted, and thus to prove that new skills could be 
acquired only through conditioning, chaining of reflexes, learning by 
rote. Kohler and the Gestalt school, on the other hand, set their 
chimpanzees tasks for which they were ripe or almost ripe, to prove that 
all learning was based on insight. The contradictory conclusions at 
which they arrived need surprise us no more than the contrast between 
the learning achievements of a child of six months and a child of six 
years. This is a necessarily over-simplified description (for a detailed 
treatment see Book Two, XII); the only point I wish to make is that 
the more ripe a situation is for the discovery of a new synthesis, the 
less need there is for the helping hand of chance. 

Archimedes's eyes falling on the smudge in the bath, or the 
chimpanzee's eyes falling upon the tree, are chance occurrences of such 
high probability that sooner or later they were bound to occur; chance 
plays here merely the part of triggering off the fusion between two 
matrices by hitting on one among many possible appropriate links. We 
may distinguish between the biological ripeness of 'a species to form a new 
adaptive habit or acquire a new skill, and the ripeness of a culture t o 
make and to exploit a ne w discovery. Hero's steam e ngine could^ 
o bviously fee exploitednToTrn duscrial purposes on 
technological and social conditions mack k bo^ 
Lastly (or firstly), there is the personal factor — the role of the creative 
individual in achieving a synthesis for which the time is more or less ripe. 

The emphasis is on the 'more or less*. If ripeness were all — as 
Shakespeare and the Marxist theory affirm — the role of Renins, in 
history would be r educed from hero to mi3w ife. who assists th e 
inevitable birt h; and the act of cre atio n would be merely a consumma- 
ttonoTthe preordained. But the old controversy whether individuals 



110 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



make or are made by history acquires a new twist in the more limited 
field of the history of science. The twist is provided by the phenomenon 
of multiple discoveries. Historical research into this curious subject is 
of fairly recent origin; it came as a surprise when, in 1922, Ogburn and 
Thomas published some hundred and fifty examples of discoveries and 
inventions which were made independently by several persons; and, 
more recently, Merton came to the seemingly paradoxical conclusion 
that 'the pattern of independent multiple discoveries in science is . . . 
the dominant pattern rather than a subsidiary one'. 5 He quotes as an 
example Lord Kelvin, whose published papers contain 'at least thirty- 
two discoveries of his own which he subsequendy found had also been 
made by others'. The 'others' include some men of genius such as 
Cavendish and Helmholtz, but also some lesser lights. 

The endless priority disputes which have poisoned the supposedly 
serene atmosphere of scientific research throughout the ages, and the 
unseemly haste of many scientists to establish priority by rushing into 
print — or, at least, depositing manuscripts in sealed envelopes with 
some learned society — point in the same direction. Some — among them 
Galileo and Hooke — even went to the length of publishing half- 
completed discoveries in the form of anagrams, to ensure priority 
without letting rivals in on the idea. Kohlers chimpanzees were of a 
more generous disposition. 

Thus one should not underestimate ripeness as a factor facilitating 
discoveries which, as the saying goes, are 'in the air' — meaning, that 
the various components which will go into the new synthesis are all 
lying around and only waiting for the trigger-action of chance, or the 
catalysing action of an exceptional brain, to be assembled and welded 
together. If one opportunity is missed, another will occur. 

But, on the other hand, although the infinitesimal calculus was 
developed independendy by Leibniz and by Newton, and a long line 
of precursors had paved the way for it, it still required a Newton or a 
Leibniz to accomplish the feat; and the greatness of this accomplish- 
ment is hardly diminished by the fact that two among millions, instead 
of one among millions, had the exceptional genius to do it. We are 
concerned with the question how they did it — the nature of creative 
originality— and not with the undeniable, but trivial consideration that 
if they had not lived somebody else would have done it some time; for 
that leaves the same question to be answered, to wit, how that someone 
else did it. I shall not presume to guess whether outstanding individuals 
such as Plato and Aristode, Jesus of Nazareth and Paul of Tarsus, 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



III 



Aquinas, Bacon, Marx, Freud, and Einstein, were expendable in the 
above sense, so that the history of ideas in their absence would have 
taken much the same course — or whether it is the creative genius who 
determines the course of history. I merely wish to point out that some 
of the major break-throughs in the history of science represent such 
dramatic tours de force, that 'ripeness* seems a very lame explanation, 
and chance* no explanation at all. Einstein discovered the principle of 
relativity 'unaided by any observation that had not been available for at 
least fifty years before*; 6 the plum was overripe, yet for half a century 
nobody came to pluck it. A less obvious example is Everist Galois, one 
of the most original mathematicians of all times, who was killed in an 
absurd duel in 1832, at the age of twenty. In the night before the duel 
he revised a paper to the Academie des Sciences (which had previously 
rejected it as unintelligible); then, in a letter to a friend, he hurriedly 
put down a number of other mathematical discoveries. 'It was only 
after fifteen years, that, with admiration, scientists became aware of the 
memoir which the Academy had rejected. It signifies a total transforma- 
tion of higher algebra, projecting a full light on what had been only 
glimpsed thus far by the greatest mathematicians . . .' 7 Furthermore, in 
the letter to his friend, Galois postulated a theorem which could not 
have been understood by his contemporaries because it was based on 
mathematical principles which were discovered only a quarter century 
after his death. It must be admitted,* another great mathematician 
commented, 'first, that Galois must have conceived these principles in 
some way; second, that they must have been unconscious in his mind 
since he makes no allusion to them, though they by themselves 
represent a significant discovery.* 8 

This leads us to the problem of the part played by unconscious 
processes in the Eureka act. 

Pythagoras, according to tradition, is supposed to have discovered 
that musical pitch depends on the ratio between the length of vibrating 
chords — the starting point of mathematical physics— by passing in 
front of the local blacksmith on his native island of Samos, and 
noticing that rods of iron of different lengths gave different sounds 
under the blacksmith's hammer. Instead of ascribing it to chance, we * 
suspect that it was some obscure intuition which made Pythagoras stop 
at the blacksmith's shop. But how does that kind of intuition work? 
Here is the core of the problem of discovery — both in science and in art. 



Logic and Intuition 



I shall briefly describe, for the sake of contrast, two celebrated discov- 
eries of entirely different kinds: the first apparently due to conscious, 
logical reasoning aided by chance; the second a classic case of the 
intervention of the unconscious. 

Eighteen hundred and seventy-nine was the birth-year of immun- 
ology — the prevention of infectious diseases by inoculation. By that 
time Louis Pasteur had already shown that cattle fever, rabies, silkworm 
disease, and various other afflictions were caused by micro-organisms, 
and had firmly established the germ theory of disease. In the spring of 
1879 — he was fifty-seven at that time — Pasteur was studying chicken 
cholera. He had prepared cultures of the bacillus, but for some reason 
this work was interrupted, and the cultures remained during the whole 
summer unattended in the laboratory. In the early autumn, however, 
he resumed his experiments. He injected a number of chickens with the 
bacillus, but unexpectedly they became only slightly ill and recovered. 
He concluded that the old cultures had been spoilt, and obtained a new 
culture of virulent bacilli from chickens afflicted by a current outbreak 
of cholera. He also bought a new batch of chickens from the market 
and injected both lots, the old and the new, with the fresh culture. The 
newly bought chicks all died in due time, but, to his great surprise the 
old chicks, who had been injected once already with the ineffective 
culture, all survived. An eye-witness in the lab described the scene 
which took place when Pasteur was informed of this curious develop- 
ment. He 'remained silent for a minute, then exclaimed as if he had 
seen a vision: "Don't you see that these animals have been vaccinated?' 9 

Now I must explain that the word vaccination was at that time 
already a century old. It is derived from v acca, cow. Some time in the 
1760s a young medical student, Edward Jenner, was consulted by a 
Gloucester dairymaid who felt out of sorts. Jenner thought that she 
might be suffering from smallpox, but she prompdy replied: 'I cannot 
take the smallpox because I have had the cow-pox/ After nearly 
twenty years of struggle against the scepticism and indifference of the 
medical profession, Jenner succeeded in proving the popular belief that 
people who had once caught the cow-pox were immune against 
smallpox. Thus originated Vaccination' — the preventive inoculation of 
human beings against the dreaded and murderous disease with material 
taken from the skin sores of afflicted catde. Although Jenner realized 
that cow-pox and smallpox were essentially the same disease, which 

112 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



113 



became somehow modified by the organism which carried it, he did 
not draw any general conclusions from his discovery. 'Vaccination' 
soon spread to America and became a more or less general practice in 
a number of other countries, yet it remained limited to smallpox, and 
the word itself retained its exclusively bovine connotations. 

The vision which Pasteur had seen at that historic moment was, once 
again, the discovery of a hidden analogy: the surviving chicks of the 
first batch were protected against cholera by their inoculation with the 
'spoilt* culture as humans are protected against smallpox by inoculation 
with pox bacilli in a modified, bovine form. 

Now Pasteur was well acquainted with Jenner's work. To quote one 
of his biographers, Dr. Dubos (himself an eminent biologist): 'Soon 
after the beginning of his work on infectious diseases, Pasteur became 
convinced that something similar to "vaccination" was the best ap- 
proach to their control. It was this conviction that made him per- 
ceive immediately the meaning of the accidental experiment with 
chickens.' 

In other words, he was 'ripe' for his discovery, and thus able to 
pounce on the first favourable chance that offered itself. As he himself 
said:jFortune favours the prepared mind.' Put in this way, there seems 
to be nothing very awe-inspiring in Pasteur's discovery. Yet for about 
three-quarters of a century Vaccination had been a common practice 
in Europe and America; why, then, did nobody before Pasteur hit on 
the 'obvious' idea of extending vaccination from smallpox to other 
diseases? Why did nobody before him put two and two together? 
Because, to answer the question literally, the first 'two* and the second 
'two' appertained to different frames of reference. The first was the 
technique of vaccination; the second was the hitherto quite separate 
and independent research into the world of micro-organisms: fowl- 
parasites, silkworm-bacilli, yeasts fermenting in wine-barrels, invisible 
viruses in the spittle of rabid dogs. Pasteur succeeded in combining 
these two separate frames because he had an exceptional grasp of the 
rules of both, and was thus prepared for the moment when chance 
provided an appropriate link. 

He knew— what Jenner knew not — that the active agent in Jenner's 
'vaccine* was the microbe of the same disease against which the subject 
was to be protected, but a microbe which in its bovine host had under- 
gone some kind of 'attenuation'. And he further realized that the 
cholera bacilli left to themselves in the test-tubes during the whole 
summer had undergone the same kind of 'attenuation' or weakening. 



114 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



as the pox bacilli in the cow's body. This led to the surprising, almost 
poetic, conclusion, that life inside an abandoned glass tube can have 
the same debilitating effect on a bug as life inside a cow. From here 
on the implications of the Gloucestershire dairymaid's statement 
became gloriously obvious: 'As attenuation of the bacillus had oc- 
curred spontaneously in some of his cultures [just as it occurred 
inside the cow], Pasteur became convinced that it should be possible 
to produce vaccines at will in the laboratory. Instead of depending upon 
the chance of naturally occurring immunizing agents, as cow-pox was 
for smallpox, vaccination could then become a general technique 
applicable to all infectious diseases.' 9 

One of the scourges of humanity had been eliminated — to be 
replaced in due time by another. For the story has a sequel with an 
ironic symbolism, which, though it does not strictly belong to the 
subject, I cannot resist telling. The most famous and dramatic applica- 
tion of Pasteur's discovery was his anti-rabies vaccine. It was tried for 
the first time on a young Alsatian boy by name of Josef Meister, who 
had been savagely bitten by a rabid dog on his hands, legs, and thighs. 
Since the incubation period of rabies is a month or more, Pasteur hoped 
to be able to immunize the boy against the deadly virus which was 
already in his body. After twelve injections with rabies vaccine of 
increasing strength the boy returned to his native village without 
having suffered any ill effects from the bites. The end of the story is 
told by Dubos: 'Josef Meister later became gatekeeper at the Pasteur 
Institute in Paris. In 1940, fifty-five years after the accident that gave 
him a lasting place in medical history, he committed suicide rather 
than open Pasteur's burial crypt for the German invaders.' 9 * He was 
evidently predestined to become a victim of one form of rabidness 
or another. 

Now for a discovery of a diametrically opposite kind, where 
intuition plays the dominant part. The extracts which follow are from 
a celebrated lecture by Henri Poincare at the Societi de Psychologie in 
Paris, and concern one of his best-known mathematical discoveries: the 
theory of the so-called 'Fuchsian functions'. To reassure the reader I 
hasten to quote from Poincare's own introductory remarks: 

I beg your pardon; I am about to use some technical expressions, 
but they need not frighten you for you are not obliged to understand 
them. I shall say, for example, that I have found the demonstration 



MOMENTS OB TRUTH 



115 



of such a theorem under such circumstances. This theorem will 
have a barbarous name unfamiliar to many, but that is unimportant; 
what is of interest for the psychologist is not the theorem but 
the circumstances. . . . 

And now follows one of the most lucid introspective accounts of 
the Eureka act by a great scientist: 

For fifteen days I strove to prove that there could not be any 
functions like those I have since called Fuchsian functions. I was 
then very ignorant; every day I seated myself at my work table, 
stayed an hour or two, tried a great number of combinations, and 
reached no results. One evening, contrary to my custom, I drank 
black coffee and could not sleep. Ideas rose in crowds; I felt them 
collide until pairs interlocked, so to speak, making a stable com- 
bination. By the next morning I had established the existence of a 
class of Fuchsian functions, those which come from the hypergeo- 
metric series; I had only to write out the results, which took but a 
few hours. 

Then I wanted to represent these functions by the quotient of two 
series; this idea was perfecdy conscious and deliberate, the analogy 
with elliptic functions guided me. I asked myself what properties 
these series must have if they existed, and I succeeded without diffi- 
culty in forming the series I have called theta-Fuchsian. 

Just at this time I left Caen, where I was then living, to go on a 
geologic excursion under the auspices of the school of mines. The 
changes of travel made me forget my mathematical work. Having 
reached Coutances, we entered an omnibus to go some place or 
other. At the moment when I put my foot on the step the idea came 
to me, without anything in my former thoughts seeming to have 
paved the way for it, that the transformations I had used to define 
the Fuchsian functions were identical with those of non-Euclidean 
geometry. I did not verify the idea; I should not have had time, as, 
upon taking my seat in the omnibus, I went on with a conversation 
already commenced, but I felt a perfect certainty. On my return to 
Caen, for conscience' sake I verified the result at my leisure. 

Then I turned my attention to the study of some arithmetical 
questions apparently without much success and without a suspicion 
of any connection with my preceding researches. Disgusted with my 
failure, I went to spend a few days at the seaside, and thought of 



Il6 THE ACT OF CREATION 

something else. One morning, walking on the bluff, the idea came to 
me, with just the same characteristics of brevity, suddenness, and 
immediate certainty, that the arithmetic transformations of indeter- 
minate ternary quadratic forms were identical with those of non- 
Euclidean geometry. 

Returned to Caen, I meditated on this result and deduced the 
consequences. The example of quadratic forms showed me that there 
were Fuchsian groups other than those corresponding to the hyper- 
geometric series; I saw that I could apply to them the theory of 
theta-Fuchsian series and that consequendy there existed Fuchsian 
functions other than those from the hypergeometric series, the ones 
I then knew. Naturally I set myself to form all these functions. I made 
a systematic attack upon them and carried all the outworks, one after 
another. There was one, however, that still held out, whose fall 
would involve that of the whole place. But all my efforts only served 
at first the better to show me the difficulty, which indeed was 
something. All this work was perfectly conscious. 

Thereupon I left for Mont-Valcrien, where I was to go through 
my military service; so I was very differendy occupied. One day, 
going along the street, the solution of the difficulty which had 
stopped me suddenly appeared to me. I did not try to go deep into 
it immediately, and only after my service did I again take up the 
question. I had all the elements and had only to arrange them and 
put them together. So I wrote out my final memoir at a single stroke 
and without difficulty. 

I shall limit myself to this single example; it is useless to multiply 
them. In regard to my other researches I would have to say 
analogous things . . . 

Most striking at first is this appearance of sudden illumination, a 
manifest sign of long, unconscious prior work. The role of this 
unconscious work in mathematical invention appears to me 
incontestable. . . . 10 

Similar experiences have been reported by other mathematicians. 
They seem to be the rule rather than the exception. One of them is 
Jacques Hadamard: 11 

. . . One phenomenon is certain and I can vouch for its absolute 
certainty: the sudden and immediate appearance of a solution at the 
very moment of sudden awakening. On being very abruptly 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



117 



awakened by an external noise, a solution long searched for appeared 
to me at once without the slightest instant of reflection on my part — 
the fact was remarkable enough to have struck me unforgettably — 
and in a quite different direction from any of those which I had 
previously tried to follow. 

A few more examples. Andre Marie Ampere (1775-18 3 6), after 
whom the unit of electric current is named, a genius of childlike 
simplicity, recorded in his diary the circumstances of his first 
mathematical discovery: 

On April 27, 1802, he tells us, I gave a shout of joy ... It was seven 
years ago I proposed to myself a problem which I have not been able 
to solve directly, but for which I had found by chance a solution, and 
knew that it was correct, without being able to prove it. The matter 
often returned to my mind and I had sought twenty times unsuccess- 
fully for this solution. For some days I had carried the idea about 
with me continually. At last, I do not know how, I found it, together 
with a large number of curious and new considerations concerning 
the theory of probability. As I think there are very few math- 
ematicians in France who could solve this problem in less time, I have 
no doubt that its publication in a pamphlet of twenty pages is a good 
method for obtaining a chair of mathematics in a college. 12 

The memoir did in fact get him a professorship at the Lycee in 
Lyon. It was called Considerations of the Mathematical Theory of Games of 
Chance, and demonstrated, among other things, that habitual gamblers 
are, in the long run, bound to lose. 

Another great mathematician, Karl Friedrich Gauss, described in a 
letter to a friend how he finally proved a theorem on which he had 
worked unsuccessfully for four years: 

At last two days ago I succeeded, not by dint of painful effort but 
so to speak by the grace of God. As a sudden flash of light, the 

enigma was solved For my part I am unable to name the nature 

of the thread which connected what I previously knew with that 
which made my success possible. 13 

On another occasion Gauss is reported to have said: 'I have had my 
solutions for a long time, but I do not yet know how I am to arrive at 



n8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



them/ Paraphrasing him, Polya — a contemporary mathematician — 
remarks: 'When you have satisfied yourself that the theorem is true, 
you start proving it.' 14 

We have seen quite a few cats being let out of the bag — the mathe- 
matical mind, which is supposed to have such a dry, logical, rational 
texture. As a last example in this chapter I shall quote the dramatic case 
of Friedrich August von Kekule, Professor of Chemistry in Ghent, 
who, one afternoon in 1865, fell asleep and dreamt what was probably 
the most important dream in history since Joseph's seven fat and seven 
lean cows: 

I turned my chair to the fire and dozed, he relates. Again the 
atoms were gambolling before my eyes. This time the smaller 
groups kept modestly in the background. My mental eye, rendered 
more acute by repeated visions of this kind, could now distinguish 
larger structures, of manifold conformation; long rows, sometimes 
more closely fitted together; all twining and twisting in snakelike 
motion. But look ! What was that? One of the snakes had seized 
hold of its own tail, and the form whirled mockingly before my eyes. 
As if by a flash of Hghtning I awoke ... Let us learn to dream, 
gentlemen. 15 

The serpent biting its own tail gave Kekule the clue to a discovery 
which has been called 'the most brilliant piece of prediction to be 
found in the whole range of organic chemistry' and which, in fact, is 
one of the cornerstones of modern science. Put in a somewhat 
simplified manner, it consisted in the revolutionary proposal that the 
molecules of certain important organic compounds are not open 
structures but closed chains or 'rings' — like the snake swallowing its 
tail. 

Summary 

When life presents us with a problem it will be attacked in accordance 
with the code of rules which enabled us to deal with similar problems 
in the past. These rules of the game range from manipulating sticks to 
operating with ideas, verbal concepts, visual forms, mathematical 
entities. When the same task is encountered under relatively un- 
changing conditions in a monotonous environment, the responses will 
become stereotyped, flexible skills will degenerate into rigid patterns, 



MOMENTS OF TRUTH 



119 



and the person will more and more resemble an automaton, governed 
by fixed habits, whose actions and ideas move in narrow grooves. He 
may be compared to an engine-driver who must drive his train along 
fixed rails according to a fixed timetable. 

Vice versa, a changing, variable environment will tend to create 
flexible behaviour-patterns with a high degree of adaptability to 
circumstances — the driver of a motor-car has more degrees of freedom 
than the engine-driver. But novelty can be carried to a point — by life 
or in the laboratory — where the situation still resembles in some respects 
other situations encountered in the past, yet contains new features or 
complexities which make it impossible to solve the problem by the 
same rules of the game which were applied to those past situations. 
"When this happens we say that the situation is blocked — though the 
subject may realize this fact only after a series of hopeless tries, or never 
at all. To squeeze the last drop out of the metaphor: the motorist is 
heading for a frontier to which all approaches are barred, and all his 
skill as a driver will not help him — short of turning his car into a 
helicopter, that is, playing a different kind of game. 

A blocked situation increases the stress of the frustrated drive. What 
happens next is much the same in the chimpanzee's as in Archimedes's 
case. When all hopeful attempts at solving the problem by traditional 
methods have been exhausted, thought runs around in circles in the 
blocked matrix like rats in a cage. Next, the matrix of organized, 
purposeful behaviour itself seems to go to pieces, and random trials 
make their appearance, accompanied by tantrums and attacks of 
despair — or by the distracted absent-mindedness of the creative obses- 
sion. That absent-mindedness is, of course, in fact smgle-mindedness; 
for at this stage — the 'period of incubation — the whole personality, 
down to the unverbalized and unconscious layers, has become saturated 
with the problem, so that on some level of the mind it remains active, 
even while attention is occupied in a quite different field — such as 
looking at a tree in the chimpanzee's case, or watching the rise of the 
water-level; until either chance or intuition provides a link to a quite 
different matrix, which bears down vertically, so to speak, on the 
problem blocked in its old horizontal context, and the two previously 
separate matrices fuse. But for that fusion to take place a condition must 
be fulfilled which I called 'ripeness'. 

Concerning the psychology of the creative act itself, I have men- 
tioned the following, interrelated aspects of it: the displacement of 
attention to something not previously noted, which was irrelevant in 



120 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the old and is relevant in the new context; the discovery of hidden 
analogies as a result of the former; the bringing into consciousness of 
tacit axioms and habits of thought which were implied in the code and 
taken for granted; the un-covering of what has always been there. 

This leads to the paradox that the more original a discovery the more 
obvious it seems afterwards. The creative act is not an act of creation 
in the sense of the Old Testament. It does not create something out of 
nothing; it uncovers, selects, re-shuffles, combines, synthesizes already 
existing facts, ideas, faculties, skills. The more familiar the parts, the 
more striking the new whole. Man's knowledge of the changes of the 
tides and the phases of the moon is as old as his observation that apples 
fall to earth in the ripeness of time. Yet the combination of these and 
other equally familiar data in Newton's theory of gravity changed 
mankind's outlook on the world. 

'It is obvious', says Hadamard, 'that invention or discovery, be it in 
mathematics or anywhere else, takes place by combining ideas. . . . 
The Latin verb cogito for "to think" etymologically means "to shake 
together". St. Augustine had already noticed that and also observed 
that intelligo means "to select among"/ 

The 'ripeness' of a culture for a new synthesis is reflected in the 
recurrent phenomenon of multiple discovery, and in the emergence 
of similar forms of art, handicrafts, and social institutions in diverse 
cultures. But when the situation is ripe for a given type of discovery 
it still needs the intuitive power of an exceptional mind, and sometimes 
a favourable chance event, to bring it from potential into actual exist- 
ence. On the other hand, some discoveries represent striking tours de 
force by individuals who seem to be so far ahead of their time that their 
contemporaries are unable to understand them. 

Thus at one end of the scale we have discoveries which seem to be 
due to more or less conscious, logical reasoning, and at the other end 
sudden insights which seem to emerge spontaneously from the depth of 
the unconscious. The same polarity of logic and intuition will be found 
to prevail in the methods and techniques of artistic creation. It is 
summed up by two opposite pronouncements: Bernard Shaw's 'Ninety 
per cent perspiration, ten per cent inspiration, on the one hand, 
Picasso's 'I do not seek— I find* (je ne cherchepasje trouve), on the other. 



i 



VI 

THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 

Before proceeding further, let me return for a moment to the 
^ basic, bisociative pattern of the creative synthesis: the sudden 
' interlocking of two previously unrelated skills, or matrices of 
thought I shall give three somewhat more detailed examples which 
display this pattern from various angles: Gutenberg's invention of 
printing with movable types; Kepler's synthesis of astronomy and 
physics; Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection. 

i. The Printing Press 

At the dawn of the fifteenth century printing was no longer a novelty 
in Europe. Printing from wooden blocks on vellum, silk, and cloth 
apparendy started in the twelfth century, and printing on paper was 
widely practised in the second half of the fourteenth. The blocks were 
engraved in relief with pictures or text or both, then thoroughly wetted 
with a brown distemper-like substance; a sheet of damp paper was laid 
on the block and the back of the paper was rubbed with a so-called 
frotton — a dabber or burnisher — until an impression of the carved relief 
was transferred to it. Each sheet could be printed on only one side by 
this method, but the blank backs of the sheets could be pasted together 
and then gathered into quires and bound in the same manner as 
manuscript-books. These 'block books' or xylographs circulated already 
in considerable numbers during Gutenberg's youth. 

He was born in 1398 at Mainz and was really called Gensfleisch, 
meaning gooseflesh, but preferred to adopt the name of his mother's 
birthplace. The story of his life is obscure, highlighted by a succession 
of lawsuits against money-lenders and other printers; his claim to 

121 



122 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



priority is the subject of a century-old controversy. But there exists a 
series of letters to a correspondent, Frere Cordelier, which has an 
authentic ring and gives a graphic description of the manner in which 
Gutenberg arrived at his invention. 1 Whether others, such as Costa of 
Haarlem, made the same invention at the same time or before 
Gutenberg is, from our point of view, irrelevant. 

Oddly enough, the starting point of Gutenberg's invention was not 
the block-books — he does not seem to have been acquainted with them 
— but playing-cards. In his first letter to Cordelier he wrote: 

For a month my head has been working; a Minerva, fully armed, 

must issue from my brain You have seen, as I have, playing-cards 

and pictures of saints. . . . These cards and pictures are engraved on 
small pieces of wood, and below the pictures there are words and 

entire lines also engraved A thick ink is applied to the engraving; 

and upon this a leaf of paper, slightly damp, is placed; then this wood, 
this ink, this paper is rubbed and rubbed until the back of the paper is 
polished. This paper is then taken off and you see on it the picture 
just as if the design had been traced upon it, and the words as if they 
had been written; the ink applied to the engraving has become 
attached to the paper, attracted by its softness and by its moisture 

Well, what has been done for a few words, for a few lines, I must 
succeed in doing for large pages of writing, for large leaves covered 
entirely on both sides, for whole books, for the first of all books, the 
Bible. . . . 

How? It is useless to think of engraving on pieces of wood the 
whole thirteen hundred pages. . . . 

What am I to do? I do not know: but I know what I want to do: I 
wish to manifold the Bible, I wish to have the copies ready for the 
pilgrimage to Aix la Chapelle. 

Here, then, we have matrix or skill No. i: the printing from wood- 
blocks by means of rubbing. 

In the letters which follow we see him desperately searching for a 
simpler method to replace the laborious carving of letters in wood: 

Every coin begins with a punch. The punch is a little rod of steel, 
one end of which is engraved with the shape of one letter, several 
letters, all the signs which are seen in relief on a coin. The punch is 
moistened and driven into a piece of steel, which becomes the 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



'hollow' or 'stamp'. It is into these coin-stamps, moistened in their 
turn, that are placed the little discs of gold, to be converted into 
coins, by a powerful blow. 

This is the first intimation of the method of type-casting. It leads 
Gutenberg, by way of analogy, to the seal: 'When you apply to the 
vellum or paper the seal of your community, everything has been said, 
everything is done, everything is there. Do you not see that you can 
repeat as many times as necessary the seal covered with signs and 
characters?' 

Yet all this is insufficient. He may cast letters in the form of coins, 
or seals, instead of engraving the wood, yet they will never make a 
clear print by the clumsy rubbing method; so long as his search remains 
confined to this one and only traditional method of making an 
'imprint', the problem remains blocked. To solve it, an entirely 
different kind of skill must be brought in. He tries this and that; he 
thinks of everything under the sun: it is the period of incubation. 
When the favourable opportunity at last offers itself he is ready 
for it: 

I took part in the wine harvest. I watched the wine flowing, and 
going back from the effect to the cause, I studied the power of this 
press which nothing can resist. . . . 

At this moment it occurs to him that the same, steady pressure might 
be applied by a seal or coin — preferably of lead, which is easy to cast — 
on paper, and that owing to the pressure, the lead would leave a trace 
on the paper — Eureka! 

... A simple substitution which is a ray of light. ... To work then! 
God has revealed to me the secret that I demanded of Him. ... I have 
had a large quantity of lead brought to my house and that is the pen 
with which I shall write. 

'The ray of light' was the bisociation of wine-press and seal — which, 
added together, become the letter-press. The wine-press has been lifted 
out of its context, the mushy pulp, the flowing red liquid, the jolly 
revelry — as Sultan's branch was wrenched out of the context of the 
tree — and connected with the stamping of vellum with a seal. From 
now onward these separate skills, which previously had been as 



124 THE ACT OF CREATION 

different as the butchers, the baker's, and the candlestick-maker's, will 
appear integrated in a single, complex matrix: 

One must strike, cast, make a form like the seal of your commun- 
ity; a mould such as that used for casting your pewter cups; letters in 
relief like those on your coins, and the punch for producing them 
like your foot when it multiplies its print. There is the Bible! 

2. Gravity and the Holy Ghost 

c If I have been able to see farther than others,' said Newton, 'it was 
because I stood on the shoulders of giants.' One of the giants was 
Johannes Kepler (1471-1530) whose three laws of planetary motion 
provided the foundation on which the Newtonian universe was built. 
They were the first 'natural laws' in the modern sense: precise, 
verifiable statements expressed in mathematical terms; at the same 
time, they represent the first attempt at a synthesis of astronomy and 
physics which, during the preceding two thousand years, had developed 
on separate lines. 

Astronomy before Kepler had been a purely descriptive geometry 
of the skies. The motion of stars and planets had been represented by 
the device of epicycles and eccentrics — an imaginary clockwork of 
circles turning on circles turning on circles. Copernicus, for instance, 
had used forty-eight wheels to represent the motion of the five known 
planets around the sun. These wheels were purely fictitious, and meant 
as such — they enabled astronomers to make more or less precise 
predictions, but, above all, they satisfied the dogma that all heavenly 
motion must be uniform and in perfect circles. Though the planets 
moved neither uniformly nor in perfect circles, the imaginary cog- 
wheels did, and thereby 'saved the appearances'. 

Kepler's discoveries put an end to this state of affairs. He reconciled 
astronomy with physics, and substituted for the fictitious clockwork a 
universe of material bodies not unlike the earth, freely floating and 
turning in space, moved by forces acting on them. His most important 
book bears the provocative tide: A New Astronomy Based on Causation 
Or Physics of the Sky (1609). It contains the first and second of Kepler's 
three laws. The first says that the planets move around the sun not in 
circles but in elliptic orbits; the second says that a planet moves in its 
orbit not at uniform speed but at a speed that varies according to its 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



125 



position, and is defined by a simple and beautiful law: the line connect- 
ing planet and sun sweeps over equal areas in equal times. The 
third law establishes an equally elegant mathematical correlation 
between the length of a planet's year and its mean distance from the 
sun. 

Kepler did not start his career as an astronomer, but as a student of 
theology (at the Lutheran University of Thuebingen); yet already as a 
student he was attracted by the Copernican idea of a sun-centred 
universe. Now Canon Copernicus's book, On the Revolutions of the 
Heavenly Spheres, had been published in the year of his death, 1543; 
that is, fifty years before Kepler first heard of him; and during that half 
century it had attracted very little attention. One of the reasons was its 
supreme unreadability, which made it into an all-time worst-seller: 
its first edition of a thousand copies was never sold out. Kepler was the 
first Continental astronomer to embrace the Copernican theory. His 
Mysterium Cosmographicum, published in 1597 (fifty-four years after 
Copernicus's death), started the great controversy — Galileo entered the 
scene fifteen years later. 

The reason why the idea of a sun-centred universe appealed to Kepler 
was repeatedly stated by himself: 'I often defended the opinions of 
Copernicus in the disputations of the candidates and I composed a 
careful disputation on the first motion which consists in the rotation of 
the earth; then I was adding to this the motion of the earth around the 
sun for physical or, if you prefer \ metaphysical reasons. 9 2 1 have emphasized 
the last words because they contain the leitmotif of Kepler's quest, and 
because he used the same expression in various passages in his works. 
Now what were those physical or, if you prefer, metaphysical 
reasons' which made Kepler prefer to put the sun into the centre of the 
universe instead of the earth? 

My ceaseless search concerned primarily three problems, namely, 
the number, size, and motion of the planets — why they are just as 
they are and not otherwise arranged. I was encouraged in my daring 
inquiry by that beautiful analogy between the stationary objects, 
namely, the sun, the fixed stars, and the space between them, with 
God the Father, the Son, and the Holy Ghost. I shall pursue this 
analogy in my future cosmographical work. 8 

Twenty-five years later, when he was over fifty, Kepler repeated his 
credo: 'It is by no means permissible to treat this analogy as an empty 



126 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



comparison; it must be considered by its Platonic form and archetypal 
quality as one of the primary causes.' 

He believed in this to the end of his life. Yet gradually the analogy 
underwent a significant change: 

The sun in the middle of the moving stars, himself at rest and yet the 
source of motion, carries the image of God the Father and Creator. 
He distributes his motive force through a medium which contains 
the moving bodies, even as the Father creates through the Holy 
Ghost. 4 

Thus the 'moving bodies' — that is, the planets — are now brought 
into the analogy. The Holy Ghost no longer merely fills the space 
between the motionless sun and the motionless fixed stars. It has 
become an active force, a vis motrix, which drives the planets. Nobody 
before Kepler had postulated, or even suspected, the existence of a 
physical force acting between the sun and the planets. Astronomy was 
not concerned with physical forces, nor with the causes of the heavenly 
motions, merely with their description. The passages which I have just 
quoted are the first intimation of the forthcoming marriage between 
physics and astronomy — the act of betrothal, as it were. By looking at 
the sky, not through the eyes of the geometrician only, but of the 
physicist concerned with natural causes, he hit upon a question which 
nobody had asked before, The question was: 'Why do the planets 
closer to the sun move faster than those which are far away? What is 
the mathematical relation between a planet's distance from the sun and 
the length of its year?' 

These questions could only occur to one who had conceived the 
revolutionary hypothesis that the motion of the planet — and therefore 
its velocity and the duration of its year — was governed by a physical 
force emanating from the sun. Every astronomer knew, of course, that 
the greater their distance from the sun the slower the planets moved. 
But this phenomenon was taken for granted, just as it was taken for 
granted that boys will be boys and girls will be girls, as an irreducible 
fact of creation. Nobody asked the cause of it because physical causes 
were not assumed to enter into the motion of heavenly bodies. The 
greatness of the philosophers of the scientific revolution consisted not 
so much in finding the right answers but in asking the right questions; 
in seeing a problem where nobody saw one before; in substituting a 
'why' for a 'how*. 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



127 



Kepler's answer to the question why the outer planets move slower 
than the inner ones, and how the speed of their motion is related to 
their distance from the sun, was as follows: 

There exists only one moving soul in the centre of all the orbits; 
that is the sun which drives the planets the more vigorously the closer 
the planet is, but whose force is quasi-exhausted when acting on the 
outer planets because of the long distance and the weakening of the 
force which it entails. 5 

Later on he commented: 'If we substitute for the word "soul" the 
word "force", then we get just the principle which underlies my 
"Physics of the Skies". As I reflected that this cause of motion diminishes 
in proportion to distance just as the light of the sun diminishes in 
proportion to distance from the sun, I came to the conclusion that this 
force must be substantial — "substantial" not in the literal sense but . . . 
in the same manner as we say that light is something substantial, 
meaning by this an unsubstantial entity emanating from a substantial 
body.' 6 

We notice that Kepler's answer came before the question — that it was 
the answer that begot the question. The answer, the starting point, was 
the analogy between God the Father and the sun — the former acting 
through the Holy Ghost, the latter through a physical force. The 
planets must obey the law of the sun — the law of God — the mathe- 
matical law of nature; and the Holy Ghost's action through empty 
space diminishes, as the light emanating from the sun does, with 
distance. The degenerate, purely descriptive astronomy which 
originated in the period of the Greek decline, and continued through 
the Dark and Middle Ages until Kepler, did not ask for meaning and 
causes. But Kepler was convinced that physical causes operate between 
heavenly, just as between earthly, bodies, and more specifically that 
the sun exerts a physical force on the planets. It was this conviction 
which enabled him to formulate his laws. Physics became the auxiliary 
matrix which secured his escape from the blocked situation into which 
astronomy had manoeuvred itself. 

The blockage — to cut a very long story short — was due to the fact 
that Tycho de Brahe had improved the instruments and methods of 
star-gazing, and produced observational data of a hitherto unequalled 
abundance and precision; and the new data did not fit into the 
traditional schemes. Kepler, who served his apprenticeship under 



128 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Tycho, was given the task of working out the orbit of Mars. He spent 
six years on the task and covered nine thousand folio-sheets with 
calculations in his small handwriting without getting anywhere. When 
at last he believed he had succeeded he found to his dismay that certain 
observed positions of Mars differed from those which his theory 
demanded by magnitudes up to eight minutes arc. Eight minutes arc 
is approximately one-quarter of the apparent diameter of the moon. 

This was a catastrophe. Ptolemy, and even Copernicus, could afford 
to neglect a difference of eight minutes, because their observations were 
accurate only within a margin of ten minutes, anyway. 'But/ Kepler 
wrote in the New Astronomy, 'but for us, who by divine kindness were 
given an accurate observer such as Tycho Brahe, for us it is fitting that 

we should acknowledge this divine gift and put it to use Henceforth 

I shall lead the way towards that goal according to my ideas. For if I 
had believed that we could ignore these eight minutes, I would have 
patched up my hypothesis accordingly. But since it was not permissible 
to ignore them, those eight minutes point the road to a complete 
reformation of astronomy. . . . ,? 

Thus a theory, built on years of labour and torment, was instantly 
thrown away because of a discord of eight miserable minutes arc. 
Instead of cursing those eight minutes as a stumbling block, he 
transformed them into the cornerstone of a new science. For those 
eight minutes arc had at last made him realize that the field of 
astronomy in its traditional framework was weD and truly blocked. 

One of the recurrent frustrations and tragedies in the history of 
thought is caused by the uncertainty whether it is possible to solve a 
given problem by traditional methods previously applied to problems 
which seem to be of the same nature. Who can say how many lives 
were wasted and good minds destroyed in futile attempts to square the 
circle, or to construct a perpetuum mobile? The proof that these problems 
are insoluble was in each case an original discovery in itself (such as 
Maxwell's second law of thermodynamics) ; and such proofs could only 
be found by looking at the problem from a point of view outside its 
traditional matrix. On the other hand, the mere knowledge that a 
problem is soluble means that half the game is already won. 

The episode of the eight minutes arc had convinced Kepler that his 
problem— the orbit of Mars — was insoluble so long as he felt bound by 
the traditional rules of sky-geometry. Implied in those rules was the 
dogma of 'uniform motion in perfect circles'. Uniform motion he had 
already discarded before the crisis; now he felt that the even more 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



129 



sacred one of circular morion must also go. The impossibility of 
constructing a circular orbit which would satisfy all existing observa- 
tions suggested to him that the circle must be replaced by some other 
curve. 

The conclusion is quite simply that the planet's path is not a circle 
— it curves inward on both sides and outward again at opposite ends. 
Such a curve is called an oval. The orbit is not a circle but an oval 
figure. 8 

This oval orbit was a wild, frightening new departure for him. To 
be fed up with cycles and epicycles, to mock the slavish imitators of 
Aristode was one thing; to assign an entirely new, lopsided, implausible 
path for the heavenly bodies was quite another. Why indeed an oval? 
There is something in the perfect symmetry of spheres and circles 
which has a deep, reassuring appeal to the unconscious mind — other- 
wise it could not have survived two millennia. The oval lacks that 
archetypal appeal. It has an arbitrary, distorted form. It destroyed the 
dream of the 'harmony of the spheres', which lay at the origin of the 
whole quest. At times he felt like a criminal, or worse: a fool. All he 
had to say in his own defence was: 'I have cleared the Augean stables 
of astronomy of cycles and spirals, and left behind me only a single 
cartful of dung.' 9 

That cartful of dung — non-uniform motion in non-circular orbits 
— could only be justified and explained by arguments derived not 
from geometsy, but from physics. A phrase kept humming in his ear 
like a catchy tune, and crops up in his writings over and again: there 
is a force in the sun which moves the planets, there is a force in the sun. 
. . . And since there is a force in the sun, there must exist some simple 
relationship between the planet's distance from the sun, and its speed. 
A light shines the brighter the nearer one is to its source, and the same 
must apply to the force of the sun: the closer the planet to it, the 
quicker it will move. This had been his instinctive conviction; but now 
he thought that he had found the proof for it. 'Ye physicists, prick your 
ears, for now we are going to invade your territory.' The next six 
chapters in the Astronomia Nova are a report on that invasion into 
celestial physics, which had been out of bounds for astronomy since 
Plato. He had found the second matrix which would unblock his. 
problem. 

That excursion was something of a comedy of errors— which 



130 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



nevertheless ended with finding the truth. Since he had no notion of 
the principle of inertia, which makes a planet persist in its tangential 
motion under its own momentum, and had only a vague intuition of 
gravity, he had to invent a force which, emanating from the sun, 
sweeps the planet round its path like a broom. In the second place, to 
account for the eccentricity of the orbits he had to postulate that the 
planets were 'huge round magnets' whose poles pointed always in the 
same direction so that they would alternately be drawn closer to and 
be repelled by the sun. But although today the whole thing seems 
cockeyed, his intuition that there are two antagonistic forces acting on the 
planets, guided him in the right direction. A single force, as previously 
assumed — the divine Prime Mover and its allied hierarchy of angels — 
would never produce elliptic orbits and periodic changes of speed. 
These could only be the result of some dynamic tug of war going on in 
the sky — as indeed there is. The concept of two antagonistic forces 
provided rules for a new game in which elliptic orbits and velocities 
depending on solar distance had their legitimate place. 

He made many mistakes during that wild flight of thought; but as 
if by miracle' — as he himself remarked — the mistakes cancelled out. It 
looks as if at times his conscious critical faculties had been anaesthetized 
by the creative impulse, by the impatience to get to grips with the 
physical forces in the solar system. The problem of the planetary orbits 
had been hopelessly bogged down in its purely geometrical frame of 
reference, and when he realized that he could not get it unstuck he tore 
it out of that frame and removed it into the field of physics. That there 
were inconsistencies and impurities in his method did not matter to 
"him in the heat of the moment, hoping that somehow they would 
J right themselves later on — as they did. This inspired cheating — or, 
rather, borrowing on credit — is a characteristic and recurrent feature in 
the history of science. The latest example is sub-atomic physics, which 
may be said to live on credit — in the pious hope that one day its inner 
» contradictions and paradoxes will somehow resolve themselves. 

Kepler's determination of the orbit of Mars became the unifying 
link between the two formerly separate realms of physics and astron- 
omy* His was the first serious attempt at explaining the -mechanism of 
the solar system in terms of physical forces; and once the example was 
set, physics and cosmology could never again be divorced. 



J. Darwin and Natural Selection 



Charles Darwin is perhaps the most outstanding illustration of the 
thesis that 'creative originality' does not mean creating or originating 
a system of ideas out of nothing but rather out of the combination of 
well-established patterns of thought — by a process of cross-fertilization, 
as it were. With a pinch of salt it could be said that Darwin's essen- 
tial achievement was to combine the evolutionary philosophy of 
Anaximander, who taught that man's ancestor was an aquatic animal 
and that the earth and its inhabitants were descended from the same 
Prime Material, with the philosophy of Empedokles who taught the 
survival of the fittest among the random aggregations of organic forms. 
Aristotle the naturalist believed that nature fashions organs in the order 
of their necessity, whereas Aristotle the Platonist asserted that the 
species are immutable and denied the continuity between homo sapiens 
and the animal kingdom. 

From this point onward two basic metaphysical doctrines of 
opposite nature can be more or less clearly discerned throughout the 
history of European thought; one might call them — provided the 
words are not taken too literally — the 'descending' and 'ascending* 
views of the universe. The former is represented by Plato, the 
Neoplatonists, and by the fundamentalist trend in Christianity from 
the Fathers to the Victorians; it postulates an absolute act of creation, 
followed by a descent (Plato's cave, the Fall), followed by a static, 
immutable, deep-freeze state of affairs, a marking of time until the 
Last Judgement. The ascending or evolutionary doctrine, which had 
flourished during the heroic age of Greek science and was still partially 
upheld by Epicureans such as Lucretius, went into a long period of 
hibernation, but awoke with renewed vigour at the dawn of the 
Scientific Revolution. Tycho, Kepler, Galileo, destroyed the dogma of 
immutabiHty; Newton in his Optics declared that nature was 'delighted 
with transmutations'; and from there onward through Leibniz, de 
Maillet, Locke to Kant (to mention only a few), the idea of a growing 
'Tree of Nature', on which the species branched out from a common 
root, gained increasing support among the leading spirits. 

The conflict between the two doctrines came to a head a century 
before the Darwin scandal—in the great controversy between 
Linnaeus and BufFon, who were both born in the same year, 1707. Carl 
von Linne's published works amount to a hundred and eighty 
volumes; the Comte de Buffons Histoire Naturelle had forty-four 

131 



132 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



quarto volumes, and took fifty years to publish. Linne, who laid down 
the laws for defining genera and species, and whose system of 
classification survives to this day, started as a believer in immutability; 
but later in life he admitted that new species may arise as 'daughters of 
Time'. BufFon attacked not only Linnaeus's classification, but the 
principles underlying it; he denied the existence of rigid boundaries 
between one species and another, between vegetable and animal, 
between animal and man: species arose, transformed themselves, and 
became extinct according to climatic and other changes in nature. 
Judged by the form and organization of its body, he wrote, 'the 
orangutang would approach nearer to man than to any other animal*. 
A century later Darwin admitted that 'whole pages [in BufFon] are 
laughably like mine'. 

By the end of the eighteenth century the cumulative evidence from 
'the genera] facts in the affinities, embryology, rudimentary organs, 
geological history, and geographical distribution of organic beings' 
(Darwin to Asa Gray) 10 led to the simultaneous appearance of 
evolutionary theories in a number of European countries. It is a rather 
singular instance,' he remarked elsewhere, 'of the manner in which 
similar views arise at about the same time, that Goethe in Germany, 
Dr. [Erasmus] Darwin in England and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire in France 
. . . came to the same conclusion on the origin of the species, in the 
years 1794-95' 11 — that is, fifteen years before Charles Darwin was born. 

The second great public controversy between evolutionists and anti- 
evolutionists originated in the fateful years 2 and 3 — according to the 
calendar of the French Revolution — when the three main protagonists 
in the drama were all given chairs at the University of Paris by the 
Revolutionary Government. They were Lamarck, Cuvier, Geoffroy 
Saint-Hilaire. The climax came in 1830, when Geoffroy, the evolu- 
tionist, and Cuvier, who denied evolution, confronted each other in 
public debate before the French Academy of Sciences. Cuvier won the 
debate — and rightly so because Geoffroy had tried to demonstrate a 
good cause by a badly chosen example — but the outcome' mattered 
less than the debate itself, which Goethe declared to be an event far 
more memorable than the French Revolution. This was a quarter of a 
century before Darwin submitted his first paper on evolution to the 
Royal Society. 

A further scandal broke in 1844 — still fifteen years before the 
publication of The Origin of Species—when Robert Chambers 
published anonymously his Vestiges of Creation, an impassionate if 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



133 



dilettantic plea for the evolutionary doctrine. Its impact may be 
gathered from a scene in Disraeli's Tancred, in which the heroine sings 
the book's praises: 'You know, all is development. The principle is 
perpetually going on. First, there was nothing, then there was some- 
thing; then — I forget the next — I think there were shells, then fishes; 
then we came — let me see — did we come next? Never mind that; we 
came at last. And at the next change there will be something very 
superior to us — something with wings. Ah! that's it: we were fishes, 
and I believe we shall be crows. But you must read it ... it is all proved 
. . . You understand, it is all science; it is not like those books in which 
one says one thing and another the contrary, and both may be wrong. 
Everything is proved . . 

The passage has that particular flavour which we have come to 
associate with the Darwinian controversy. Even Tancred's rejoinder to 
the enthusiastic lady: 'I do not believe I ever was a fish/ has the familiar 
ring of music-hall jokes about my grandpa was an ape'. And yet, I 
repeat, all this excitement pre-dates the publication of Darwin's first 
paper by more than ten years. 

Thus Darwin originated neither the idea nor the controversy about 
evolution, and in his early years was fully aware of this. When he 
decided to write a book on the subject, he jotted down several versions 
of an apologetic disclaimer of originality for the preface of the future 
work: 

State broadly [that there is] scarcely any novelty in my theory . . . 
The whole object of the book is its proof, its extension, its adaptation 
to classification and affinities between species. 

Seeing what von Buch (Humboldt), G. H. Hilaire [sic] and 
Lamarck have written I pretend to no originality of idea (though I 
arrived at them quite independently and have read them since). The 
line of proof and reducing facts to law [is the] only merit, if merit 
there be, in following work. 12 

The remark that he had arrived at his ideas independendy from his 
predecessors should not perhaps be taken at face value, for Darwin's 
own notebooks are conclusive proof that he had certainly read 
Lamarck, the greatest among his precursors, and a number of other 
works on evolution, before he arrived at formulating his own theory. 
Even so, the intended apology never found its way into the book which 
it was meant to preface. In his early notebooks, not intended for 



134 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



publication, Darwin paid grateful tribute to Lamarck as a source of 
inspiration, endowed with the prophetic spirit in science, the highest 
endowment of lofty genius'. Later on he called Lamarck's work 
Veritable rubbish* which did the cause 'great harm' — and insisted that 
he had got 'not a fact or idea' from Lamarck. 13 In this respect he 
resembled Copernicus and Galileo who also excelled in denying credit 
where credit was due, and other great men who, at the beginning of 
their career, gratefully acknowledged indebtedness to their spiritual 
forbears, but later on quietly forgot or denied them. In some cases, of 
which Galileo is a striking example, the motive was an overwhelming 
vanity; in others, a subtler form of self-deception seemed to operate. 
Once one embraces an idea and lives with it day and night, one can no 
longer bear the thought that she, the idea, has formerly belonged to 
someone else; to possess her completely and be possessed by her, one 
must extinguish her past. That seems to have been Darwin's case; for, 
throughout the decisive ten years in which the battle was fought, he 
behaved like a jealous husband about his theory; but once the battle 
was won he relented and gave others their due — including Lamarck, 
whose ghost was never to be exorcized from the edifice that Darwin 
built. 

On his own account, Darwin became an evolutionist after his voyage 
on the Beagle, which ended in 1836, when he was twenty-seven; but 
The Origin of Species was only published twenty-three years later. It 
opens with the statement: 

When on board H.M.S. Beagle as naturalist, I was much struck 
with certain facts in the distribution of the organic beings inhabiting 
South America, and in the geological relations of the present to the 
past inhabitants of that continent. These facts, as will be seen in the 
latter chapters of this volume, seemed to throw some light on the 
origin of species — that mystery of mysteries, as it has been called by 
one of our great philosophers. 

After my return to England it appeared to me that ... by collect- 
ing all facts which bore in any way on the variation of animals and 
plants under domestication and nature, some light might perhaps be 
thrown on the whole subject. My first notebook was opened in 
July 1837. I worked on true Baconian principles and without any 
theory, collected facts on a wholesale scale . . . After five years' work 
I allowed myself to speculate on the subject and drew up some 
short notes. 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



135 



As Darwin's own notebooks show, the last two sentences in this 
account again should not be taken at face value — they are pious Hp- 
service to the fashionable image of the scientist collecting facts with an 
unprejudiced mind', without permitting himself, God forbid, to 
speculate on them. In reality, as the notebooks show, shortly after his 
return from the voyage (and not 'five years later), Darwin became 
committed to the evolutionary theory — and then set out to collect facts 
to prove it. A month after publication of The Origin, in December 1859, 
he admitted this — apparently forgetting what he had said m the 
Preface — in a letter eloquently defending the procedure of 'inventing a 
theory and seeing how many classes of facts the theory would ex- 
plain'. 14 In another letter he remarks that 'no one could be a good 
observer unless he was an active theorizer'; and again: 'How odd it is 
that anyone should not see that all observation must be for or against 
some view if it is to be of any service.' 15 I am stressing this point 
because scientists adhering to the positivist tradition take a perverse 
pride in seeing themselves in the role of rag-pickers in the dustbin of 
'empirical data' — unaware that even the art of rag-picking is guided 
by intuition. 

How, then, did Darwin become an evolutionist? The answer is in 
the notebooks for 1837-8, written after his return. The five years spent 
on the Beagle had taught him a wealth of lessons about living and 
extinct species, and about the gradual shading of one species into 
another. While the voyage lasted he did not draw any conscious 
conclusions from this; much later he wrote that although 'vague 
doubts occasionally flitted' across his mind, he still believed, while on 
the voyage, in the doctrine of the immutability of all species. 16 Yet the 
rich experiences of those five years must have sunk in, together with 
the Vague doubts'. When, on his return, he read Lamarck and other 
standard works on evolution, the seeds began to germinate, the 
accumulated facts began to whirl through his head, then arrange 
themselves into a meaningful pattern. The notebooks start with the 
drawing of analogies between individuals and whole species: 

If [the] individual cannot propagate he has no issue — so with 
species. 

l£ species generate other species, their race is not utterly cut off- 
otherwise all die. 



Absolute knowledge that species die and others replace them. 



136 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



. . . The permanent variations produced by confined breeding and 
changing circumstances are continued and produced according to the 
adaptation [to] such circumstances and therefore . . . death of species 
is a consequence . . . of non-adaptation [to] circumstances. 

If we choose to let conjecture run wild, then animals, our fellow 
brethren in pain, disease, death, suffering and famine — our slaves in 
the most laborious works, our companions in our amusements — 
they may partake our origin in one common ancestor — we may be 
all melted away. 

. . . Organized beings represent [a] tree irregularly branched . . . 
[This is probably an echo of Lamarck's 'branching series irregularly 
graded'.] 

Species according to Lamarck disappear as collections made 
perfect. 

If all men were dead, then monkeys may make men, men make 
angels. 

Let man visit orang-outang in domestication, hear expressive 
whine, see its intelligence when spoken, as if it understood every 
word ... see its affection to those it knows, see its passion and rage, 
sulkiness and . . . despair; let him look at savage, roasting his parent, 
naked, artless, not improving yet improvable; and then let him dare 
to boast of his proud preeminence. 

Man in his arrogance thinks himself a great work, worthy the 
interposition of a deity. More humble and I believe true to consider 
him created from animals. 

By now he is fully committed. Moreover (after all, he is only 
twenty-eight) he sees himself in the future role of a hero and possible 
martyr: 

Mention persecution of early astronomers. Then add chief good 
of individual scientific men is to push their science a few years in 
advance of their age (differently from literary men). Must remember 
that if they believe and do not openly avow their belief, they do as 
much to retard. 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



137 



That was easily said, but in fact Darwin did retard the publication of 
his theory by twenty years, until his hand was forced. The reasons were 
chronic illness, other pressing work, and, in his own words: 'I was so 
anxious to avoid prejudice, that I determined not for some time to 
write even the briefest sketch of it.' To counteract prejudice' he had to 
assemble and build massive pillars of fact in support of the slender 
bridge of his theory. For, contrary to the pious assertions in the preface, 
the bridge had come first and the pillars afterwards — as was nearly 
always the case in the history of scientific thought. The result proved 
that this caution was justified. Without those pillars, assembled with 
heroic patience and effort, the bridge would have collapsed in the 
ensuing storm. Here is one of the cases where the process of elaboration, 
verification, and confirmation — the long donkey-work following the 
brief flash of insight — is more decisive than the discovery itself. That is 
why Darwin is remembered, whereas Wallace, who made the same 
discovery, is all but forgotten. 

Given the long line of evolutionists, from Anaximander to Charles's 
own grandfather Erasmus, wherein lies Darwin's greatness, the 
originality of his contribution? In picking up, one might say, the 
disjointed threads, plaiting them into a braid, and then weaving an 
enormous carpet around it. The main thread was the evolutionist's 
credo that the various species in the animal and vegetable kingdom 
'had not been independently created, but had descended, like varieties, 
from other species'. 17 Now this doctrine disposed of the idea of the 
Creator putting down separately the first serpent, giraffe and walrus as 
ready-made products on the earth; but it gave no explanation of the 
reasons which caused the common ancestor to transform itself gradually 
into serpents, walruses, and giraffes. Only Lamarck had attempted to 
provide a comprehensive reason for evolution in his four 'laws'. They 
said, in essence, that an animal's physical characteristics and particu- 
larities of behaviour are shaped by its needs, that is, by adaptation to 
its natural environment; that specialized organs grow and decline in 
proportion to their use or disuse; and that these adaptive changes which 
the animal acquires in its lifetime are inherited by its offspring. 

Contrary to popular belief, Darwin had no objection against the last 
point, the 'inheritance of acquired characteristics' — decried as a mortal 
heresy by necnDarv/inians. On the contrary, in his Variations of Animals 
and Plants under Domestication, and in the later editions of the Origin, he 
gave a series of examples of what he believed to be inherited character- 
istics in the offspring, due to adaptive changes in their ancestors. But he 



138 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



refused to accept such direct adaptations as the only, or even the main 
cause of evolution, because the evidence seemed to speak against it. 
Evidence showed that a great variety of species lived under identical 
environmental conditions; and vice versa, that the same species could 
be found under widely varying conditions. If species evolved, as 
Lamarck's theory proposed, by direct adaptations to the environment, 
then their variety remained unexplained. Evolution was a fact; but 
what caused it? What was the nature of the force which transformed 
animals and plants into new shapes? 

The second thread that he picked up was of almost as trivial a nature 
for a country-bred English gentleman as Archimedes's daily bath: 
domestic breeding. The improvement of domestic breeds is achieved 
by the selective mating of favourable variations: 

It seemed to me probable that a careful study of domesticated 
animals and of cultivated plants would offer the best chance of 
making out this complicated problem. Nor have I been disappointed; 
in this and in all other perplexing cases I have invariably found that 
our knowledge, imperfect though it be, of variation under 
domestication, afforded the best and safest clue. I may venture to 
express my conviction of the high value of such studies, although they 
have been very commonly neglected by naturalists. 18 (my italics) 

We might say that Darwin had discovered Evolution through 
artificial selection'. Incidentally the discovery is again not quite as 
original as the last sentence might suggest. Darwin's notebooks of that 
period show that he had been reading and pondering Lamarck; and 
twenty years earlier, in his Philosophie Zoologique, Lamarck had written: 
What nature does in the course of long periods we do every day 
when we suddenly change the environment in which some species of 
living plants is situated . . . Where in nature do we find our cabbages, 
lettuces, etc., in the same state as in our kitchen gardens? And is not 
the case the same with regard to many animals which have been 
altered or greatly modified by domestication? 19 

Whether Darwin read this passage from Lamarck, or similar 
passages, we do not know. But the question is irrelevant except for 
historians who specialize in priority claims. At any rate,, Darwin now 
set out to collect facts about domestic breeding patiently and indiscrim- 
inately*, not only from technical journals but from 'skilful breeders and 
gardeners*. A great number of the 'facts* were spurious, and some of his 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



139 



theorizings were as wild and fantastic as Kepler's speculations on the 
broom-like sweeping force emanating from the sun: 

The cat had its tail cut off at Shrewsbury and its kittens had all 
short tails; but one a little longer than the rest; they all died. She had 
kittens before and afterwards with tails. 

My father says on authority of Mr. Wynne, the bitch's offspring is 
affected by previous marriages with impure breed . . . 

Dr. Smith says he is certain that when white men and Hottentots 
or Negroes cross at Cape of Good Hope, the children cannot be made 
intermediate. The first children partake more of the mother, the later 
ones of the father. 

In his book on Variations of Animals and Plants under Domestication 
we are further informed that a cow having lost its horn owing to an 
infected wound, gave birth 'to three calves, each with a small bony 
lump in place of a horn'. 

A contemporary biologist has commented on Darwin's 'amiable 
credulity'. 20 It is a character trait which he shared with Tycho, Kepler, 
Freud, Pasteur, and a large number of other great scientists. Ernest 
Jones 21 remarked in an essay about Freud that creative genius seems to 
be a mixture of scepticism and naivete: scepticism regarding the 
dogmas implied in traditional modes of thought, combined with the 
willingness of a wide-open mind to consider far-fetched theories. 
Darwin himself, as one of his biographers remarked, 'was able to give 
ultimate answers because he asked ultimate questions. His colleagues, 
the systematizers, knew more than he about particular species and 
varieties, comparative anatomy and morphology. But they had delib- 
erately eschewed such ultimate questions as the pattern of creation, or 
the reasons for any particular form, on the grounds that these were not 
the proper subjects of science. Darwin, uninhibited by these restrictions, 
could range more widely and deeply into the mysteries of Nature. . . . 
It was with the sharp eyes o£the primitive, the open mind of the 
innocent, that he looked at his subject, daring to ask questions that his 
more learned and sophisticated colleagues could not have thought to 
ask' (Himmelfarb). 28 

However, the study of domestic breeding led into another cul-de- 
sac; for, in the case of domestic animals, man acts as the agent of 



140 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



selection; but who or what selects the favourable variations for breed- 
ing in the case of undomesticated animals or plants? 'How selection 
could be applied to organisms living m a state of nature remained for 
some time a mystery to me.' 

The deadlock lasted a year and three months. He tried a number of 
hypotheses, but none of them worked. He toyed with the idea of 
some universal law, according to which species were born, matured, and 
died, just as individuals do. 'There is nothing stranger in the death of a 
species than in the death of individuals.' Then he assumed, by a 
perverse analogy, that since nothing is preserved of an individual who 
dies without leaving offspring, so a species too will die out unless it 
gives rise to another species. But they were wrong guesses, and his 
thoughts kept running in circles in the blocked matrix — as Sultan's did 
until his eyes fell on the stick. 

In Darwin's case the stick was Malthus's An Essay on the Principle of 
Population. It had been published in 1797 — more than forty years earlier. 
When Darwin read the essay — among other books which he read 'for 
amusement', as he said — he saw in a flash the 'natural selector', the 
causative agent of evolution, for which he had been searching: 

As many more individuals of each species are born than can 
possibly survive; and as consequently there is a frequently recurring 
struggle for existence, it follows that any being, if it vary ever so 
slightly in a manner profitable to itself. . . will have a better chance 
of survival, and thus be naturally selected (Darwin's italics). Thus 
, favourable variations would tend to be preserved, and unfavourable 
ones to be destroyed. Here, then, I had at last got a theory by which 
to work. 23 

He had found the third thread. Now the pattern of the theory was 
complete: what remained to be done was its elaboration — the weaving 
of the huge carpet which took him most of the rest of his life. 

The odd thing about the story is — as others have pointed out — that 
Darwin had completely misunderstood Malthus. The struggle for 
existence, in which Darwin discovered the causative mechanism of 
evolutionary improvement, Malthus himself had regarded as a cause 
of misery, frustration, and decline. The increase of population was for 
Malthus an unmitigated evil and an obstacle to progress. The-essay had 
actually been written as a polemic against Condorcet and Godwin, who 
had argued the perfectability of the human species. Domestic breeding, 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



141 



Malthus retorted, could improve animals and plants only to a very 
limited degree; but a carnation could never be made to reach the size 
of a cabbage, and similar limits were set to human progress. Thus the 
struggle for existence was for Malthus not the whiphand of evolution, 
but a scourge. What Darwin found in Malthus' s essay he had read into 
it himself— as Kepler had read his brooms and planetary lodestones 
into the skies. 

Even odder is the fact that Wallace arrived at the same discover/ 
also by way of Malthus. Alfred Russell Wallace was even more 
gullible, and at the beginning of his career even more of a dilettante 
than the young Darwin. He was fourteen years younger than Darwin; 
he had been educated at an indifferent grammar school and learned the 
trade of land-surveying. Before he took up that occupation, he had 
shown no interest in nature, and 'it took another four years for him to 
advance beyond the recognition of rose and buttercup, and to learn, 
from a shilling booklet published by the Society for the Diffusion of 
Useful Knowledge, the elementary classifications of botany'. 24 

At twenty-one he became a schoolteacher of sorts. In that year he 
read, among other books, Darwin's Journal of a Naturalist's Voyage on 
the Beagle and Malthus's Essay on Population. But his mind did not 
click. He struck up a friendship with the entymologist Henry Walter 
Bates and became an expert collector of beetles. This led him to 
speculate about 'the almost infinite number of specific forms [among 
beetles], the endless modifications of structure, shape, colour, and 
surface-markings . . . and their innumerable adaptations to diverse 
environments'; he was 'bitten by the passion for species', 25 and the 
secret of their origin. Like Darwin he became an evolutionist by an act 
of faith; like Darwin he was searching for its cause; like Darwin he 
embarked — with his friend Bates — on a naturalist expedition to collect 
insects, shells, birds, and animals; like Darwin he wrote a book about it 
(Traueb on the Amazon and Rio Negro). 

The expedition lasted four years; two years later, in 1854, he 
published an article in a scientific journal in which he postulated that 
'every species has come into existence coincident both in space and 
time with a pre-existing, closely allied species'; all species together thus 
formed a 'branching tree*. But, like Darwin earlier on, he did not know 
what made the tree grow: 'the question of how changes of species 
could have been brought about was rarely out of my mind'. Darwin 
read the paper and wrote to Wallace that he agreed with 'almost every 
word* in it; he added that he himself had been working for twenty 



142 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



years on the problem and had a 'distinct and tangible idea of its 
solution*. 

One year later the same 'distinct and tangible idea* came to Wallace. 
In his autobiography Wallace described how he was 'lying muffled in 
blankets in the cold fit of a severe attack of intermittent fever at 
Ternate' (an island near New Guinea) when he suddenly remembered 
Malthus's essay on population which he had read 'twelve or more years 
earlier'. 26 

The effect was analogous to that of friction upon the specially 
prepared match, producing that flash of insight which led immediately 
to the simple but universal law of the 'survival of the fittest' ... 'It 
suddenly flashed upon me that this self-action process [i.e. the struggle 
for existence] would necessarily improve the race, because in every genera- 
tion the inferior would inevitably be killed off and the superior would 
remain — that is, the fittest would survive. The more I thought over it the 
more I became convinced that I had at length found the long-sought- 
for law of nature that solved the problem of the origin of the species.' 27 
In the course of the next two evenings, 'in a few feverish hours', he 
put his theory into a paper of four thousand words and sent it off to 
Darwin, in the pleasant belief that it would be a surprise to him — since 
Darwin had not yet published his own theory, although he had put it 
on paper years earlier in several versions and shown it to his friends. 

'I never saw a more striking coincidence', Darwin wrote. 'If Wallace 
had my manuscript sketch written out in 1842, he could not have made 
a better short abstract.' 

Luckily, both Wallace and Darwin acted with a generosity and 
reasonableness rare in the annals of science; the result was the presenta- 
tion on 1 July 1848 of a joint memoir by Darwin and Wallace to 
the Linnean Society, under the tide 'On the Tendency of Species to 
form Varieties; and on the Perpetuation of Varieties and Species by 
Natural Means of Selection'. Neither author was present; Wallace was 
overseas, Darwin ill in bed. When the paper was read out there was 
no discussion and no sign of interest. At the end of the year the 
President of the Society said in his annual report: 'The year which has 
passed ... has not, indeed, been marked by any of those striking dis- 
coveries which at once revolutionize, so to speak, the department of 
science on which they bear.' 28 In November next year The Origin of 
Species was published, and only then did the storm break. 

Though both men were constantly ailing from real and perhaps 
also from imaginary diseases, Darwin lived to be seventy-three, and 



THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 



143 



Wallace ninety. Though they differed on some points of theory and 
though their opponents tried to play them out against each other, they 
managed to remain life-long friends; towards the end of his life Darwin 
obtained a pension for Wallace from Mr. Gladstone, and Wallace was 
one of Darwin's pall-bearers. At the fiftieth anniversary, in 1909, 
commemorating the joint publication of the Darwin- Wallace papers, 
Wallace modesdy declared that their relative contributions 'could be 
jusdy estimated as the proportion of twenty years to one week* 29 — 
which was an exaggeration, as Wallace's later works, particularly the, 
'Contributions' and 'Darwinism' were of considerable importance. 

The psychologically fascinating aspect of the story is that the same 
bisociative process was triggered off in Darwin's case by reading 
Malthus, in Wallace's by the buried memory of Malthus, whom he 
had read many years earlier, popping into consciousness at a feverish 
moment. Thus Darwin's discovery strikes one as more rational, 
Wallace's as more dramatic and bizarre, and this is in keeping with the 
character of the two men. If Darwin had more patience and clarity of 
mind, Wallace had more fantasy and perhaps even more depth. His 
remark that selection through survival of the fittest was a 'self-acting 
process' anticipated the concept of negative feed-back. His conviction 
that the rise of organic life, the rise of consciousness, and the rise of man 
represent jumps' in the evolutionary series, due to some 'unknown 
reality' which has to be added to the mechanical operation of natural 
selection, had a religious flavour; yet his conclusion that 'man and his 
rise now appear short in time — explosively short' has been confirmed 
by contemporary anthropology. If Darwin had an 'amiable credulity', 
Wallace believed, among other things, in phrenology and in the cruder 
forms of mesmerism and spiritualism. No wonder he had to dive 
into the depths of his unconscious mind to bring up the same trophy 
which Darwin spied drifting on the surface, and secured with a boat- 
hook. 

That both read Malthus is not much of a coincidence as his essay 
was well known and discussed at the time; and had it not been 
Malthus, they could have extracted the same idea from other sources — 
from Erasmus Darwin, for instance, or from certain passages in 
Lamarck. The time was ripe; 'it was not the coincidence of discovery 
that is surprising but rather the fact that the coincidence was so long 
delayed*. 30 This remark by one of Darwin's biographer's is not based 
on hind-sight, but on the opinion of Darwin's friends and contem- 
poraries: 



144 THE ACT OP CREATION 

'How extremely stupid not to have thought of that,' was Huxley's 
first reaction, reflecting that 'Columbus' companions had probably 
felt the same way when he made the egg stand on end*. The same 
thought suggested itself to the ornithologist Alfred Newton, who 
did not know whether to be 'more vexed at the solution not having 
occurred to me, than pleased that it had been found at all', partic- 
ularly since it was 'a perfectly simple solution of the problem that 
had been plaguing him for months. . . . Many of Darwin's friends 
must have felt as Huxley did . . . and many of his enemies must have 
agreed with Samuel Butler: 'Buffon planted, Erasmus Darwin and 
Lamarck watered, but it was Mr. Darwin who said "that fruit is 
ripe", and shook it into his lap/ 31 



I 



VII 

THINKING ASIDE 
Limits of Logic 

In an old Alchemist's Rosarium, whose author I have forgotten, I once 
saw two pieces of advice for finding the Philosopher's Stone 
printed side by side: 

The Stone can only be found when the search lies heavily on the 
searcher. — Thou seekest hard and findest not. Seek not and thou 
wilst find. 

The introspective reports of artists and scientists on their sources of 
inspiration and methods of work often display the same contradiction. 
'Saturate yourself through and through with your subject . . . and 
wait' was Lloyd Morgan's advice. 'Chance only favours invention for 
minds which are prepared for discoveries by patient study and persever- 
ing efforts.' This was said by Pasteur, and his meaning goes here beyond 
what I have called the factor of 'ripeness': he seems to regard chance as 
a kind of legitimate reward, causally related to the effort — an almost 
mystic conception. Souriau's famous 'to invent you must think aside' — 
'pour inventef ilfaut penser & c$ti* quoted with approval by Poincare, 
points in the same direction. The consensus, at least among mathe- 
maticians, seems to be that if you strive hard enough to get to India 
you are bound to get to some America or other. 'One sometimes 
finds,' Fleming once said, 'what one is not looking for. For instance, the 
technician who set out to find a way to synchronize the rate of fire of a 
machine-gun with the revolutions of an air-screw discovered an 
excellent way of imitating the lowing of a cow.' 

The history of discovery is full of such arrivals at unexpected 
destinations, and arrivals at the right destination by the wrong boat. 
Kepler set out to prove that the universe is built on simple geometrical 
or musical principles — and found that it was built 'on a cartload of 

145 



146 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



dung*: the elliptic orbits. He celebrated his discovery with a quotation 
from Virgil's Eclogues where Truth appears as a teasing hussy: you 
chase after her until you almost collapse; then when you have given 
up she smilingly surrenders. 

At times one almost suspects that all these references to mysterious 
inspirations and sudden flashes of insight, all these protestations about 
'I have no idea how I did it' and 'je ne cherche pas, je trouve, may stem 
from an unconscious desire to appear as the privileged master of some 
Socratic demon. Yet the evidence for large chunks of irrationality 
embedded in the creative process, not only in art (where we are ready 
to accept it) but in the exact sciences as well, cannot be disputed; and it 
is particularly conspicuous in the most rational of all sciences: mathe- 
matics and mathematical physics. From Kepler and Descartes to 
Planck and de Broglie, the working methods of the great pioneers 
seem to have been inspired by Einstein's jingle, improvised for the 
benefit of an unknown lady who asked him for a dedication on a 
photograph: 

A thought that sometimes makes me hary: 
Am I — or are the others crazy? 

In the popular imagination these men of science appear as sober 
ice-cold logicians, electronic brains mounted on dry sticks. But if one 
were shown an anthology of typical extracts from their letters and 
autobiographies with no names mentioned, and then asked to guess 
their profession, the likeliest answer would be: a bunch of poets or 
musicians of a rather romantically naive kind. The themes that 
reverberate through their intimate writings are: the belittling of logic 
and deductive reasoning (except for verification after the act); horror 
of the one-track mind; distrust of too much consistency ('One should 
carry one's theories lightly', wrote Titchener); scepticism regarding 
all-too-conscious thinking (It seems to me that what you call full 
consciousness is a limit case which can never be fully accomplished. 
This seems to me connected with the fact called the narrowness of 
consciousness Bnge des Bewusstseins, 1 — Einstein). This sceptical reserve 
is compensated by trust in intuition and in unconscious guidance by 
quasi-religious or by aesthetic sensibilities. 1 cannot believe that God 
plays dice with the world,' Einstein repeated on several occasions, 
rejecting the tendency in modern physics to replace causality by 
statistical probabilities. 'There is a scientific taste just as there is a 



THINKING ASIDE 



147 



literary or artistic one*, wrote Renan. Hadamard emphasized that the 
mathematician is in most cases unable to foresee whether a tentative 
line of attack will be successful; but he has a 'sense of beauty that can 
inform us, and I cannot see anything else allowing us to foresee. This is 
undoubtedly the way the Greek geometers thought when they 
investigated the ellipse, because there is no other conceivable way.* 
Poincare was equally specific: f It may be surprising to see emotional 
sensibility invoked a propos of mathematical demonstrations which, it 
would seem, can interest only the intellect. This would be to forget the 
feeling of mathematical beauty, of the harmony of numbers and forms, 
of geometric elegance. This is a true aesthetic feeling that all real 
mathematicians know. The useful combinations [of ideas] are precisely 
the most beautiful, I mean those best able to charm this special sensibil- 
ity.' Max Planck, the father of quantum theory, wrote in his autobiog- 
raphy that the pioneer scientist must have *a vivid intuitive imagination 
for new ideas not generated by deduction, but by artistically creative 
imagination. The quotations could be continued indefinitely, yet I 
cannot recall any explicit statement to the contrary by any eminent 
mathematician or physicist. 

Here, then, is the apparent paradox. A branch of knowledge which 
operates predominantly with abstract symbols, whose entire rationale 
and credo are objectivity, verifiability, logicality, turns out to be depen- 
dent on mental processes which are subjective, irrational, and verifiable 
only after the event. 

The Unconscious before Freud 

The apparent paradox arises out of certain misconceptions about the 
process of thinking and about the methods of science. Both originated 
in the Age of Enlightenment, and hardened into a dogmatic creed 
during the nineteenth century; the rapid expansion of thd area of 
knowledge exacted its price in a temporary loss of depth. The depth- 
psychologies of men like Nietzsche, Freud, and Jung bore through the 
shallow crust, but each drove its shafts into one particular direction 
inhabited by demons of a particular breed. The concept of the uncon- 
scious acquired a mystical halo and a clinical odour; it became a kind of 
Pandora's box, which sceptical psychologists asserted to be empty, 
while to others it served as a stage-magician's trunk, equipped with a 
trapdoor underneath and secret drawers. A good many of these violent 



148 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



reactions originated in the mistaken belief that 'the unconscious mind' 
was, like the Relativity Theory and sub-atomic physics, an invention of 
the twentieth century. 

In fact, however, the unconscious was no more invented by Freud 
than evolution was invented by Darwin, and has an equally impressive 
pedigree, reaching back to antiquity; a brief historic retrospect may 
help to see it in a broader perspective and a more balanced context. The 
larger part of the quotations which follow are taken from L. L. 
Whyte's book on The Unconscious Before Freud (1962) — a remarkable 
contribution to that neglected branch of historiography, the History 
of Ideas. 

I shall not bore the reader with obscure quotations from the 
Upanishads, or ancient Egypt and Greece. At the dawn of Christian 
Europe the dominant influence were the Neoplatonists; foremost 
among them Plotinus, who took it for granted that 'feelings can be 
present without awareness of them', that 'the absence of a conscious 
perception is no proof of the absence of mental activity', and who 
talked confidently of a 'mirror' in the mind which, when correctly 
aimed, reflects the processes going on inside it, when aimed in another 
direction, fails to do so— but the process goes on all the same. Augustine 
marvelled at man's immense store of unconscious memories — 'a 
spreading, limidess room within me — who can reach its limitless 
depth?' 

The knowledge of unconscious mentation had always been there, 
as can be shown by quotations from theologians like St. Thomas 
Aquinas, mystics like Jacob Boehme, physicians like Paracelsus, 
astronomers like Kepler, writers and poets as far apart as Dante, 
Cervantes, Shakespeare, and Montaigne. This in itself is in no way 
remarkable; what is remarkable is that this knowledge was lost during 
the scientific revolution, more particularly under the impact of its most 
influential philosopher, Rene Descartes, who flourished in the first half 
of the seventeenth century. 

As modem phy&ics started with the Newtonian revolution, so 
modem philosophy starts with what one might call the Cartesian 
Catastrophe. The catastrophe consisted in the splitting up of the world 
into the realms of matter and mind, and the identification of 'mind' with 
conscious thinking. The result of this identification was the shallow 
rationalism o£V esprit Cartesien, and an impoverishment of psychology 
which it took three centuries to remedy even in part. But it also had a 
further, unexpected consequence. To quote Whyte: 



THINKING ASIDE 



149 



Prior to Descartes and Lis sharp definition of the dualism there was 
no cause to contemplate the possible existence of unconscious men- 
tality as part of a separate realm of mind. Many religious and spec- 
ulative thinkers had taken for granted factors lying outside but 
influencing immediate awareness. . . . Until an attempt had been 
made (with apparent success) to choose awareness as the defining 
characteristic of mind, there was no occasion to invent the idea of 
unconscious mind ... It is only after Descartes that we find, first the 
idea and then the term 'unconscious mind' entering European 
thought. 1 

Only gradually did the reaction set in — the realization that 'if there 
are two realms, physical and mental, awareness cannot be taken as the 
criterion of mentality [because] the springs of human nature He in the 
unconscious ... as the realm which links the moments of human 
awareness with the background of organic processes within which they 
emerge 4 . 2 

Among the first to take up the cudgels against Descartes's 'Cogito 
ergo sum was the Cambridge philosopher Cudworth: 

. , . Those philosophers themselves who made the essence of the 
soul to consist in cogitation, and again, the essence of cogitation in 
clear and express consciousness, cannot render it in any way 
probable, that the souls of men in all profound sleeps, lethargies, and 
apoplexies ... are never so much as one moment without expressly 
conscious cogitations; which, if they were, according to the principles 

of their philosophy, they must, ipso facto, cease to have any being 

It is certain, that our human souls themselves are not always conscious 
of whatever they have in them; for even the sleeping geometrician 
hath, at that time, all his geometrical theorems some way in him; as 
also the sleeping musician, all his musical skills and songs. . . . We 
have all experience of our doing many animal actions non-attend- 
ingly, which we reflect upon afterwards; as, also, that we often 
continue a long series of bodily motions, by a mere virtual intention 
of our minds, and as it were by half a cogitation. . . . 3 

John Locke sided with Descartes, declaring boldly: 'It is impossible 
to perceive without perceiving that he does perceive/ John Norris 
(1657-1711) retorted with equal boldness: 



150 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



We may have ideas of which we are not conscious. . . . There are 
infinitely more ideas impressed on our rninds than we can possibly 
attend to or perceive. . . . There may be an impression of ideas 
without any actual perception of them. 4 

This was written in 1690. 

At about the same time the Earl of Shaftesbury wrote: 

One would think, there was nothing easier for us, than to know 
our own minds. . . . But our thoughts have generally such an 
obscure implicit language, that it is the hardest thing in the world to 
make them speak out distinctly. 5 

Leibniz — Newton's rival as a mathematician, and Descartes's oppo- 
nent as a philosopher — tried to determine quantitative thresholds of 
awareness. He came to the conclusion: 

Our clear concepts are like islands which arise above the ocean of 

o'bscure ones. 6 

We now enter the eighteenth century. Leibniz's concept of the 
unconscious found many followers in Germany, among them 
Christian Wolff: 

Let no-one imagine that I would join the Cartesians in asserting 
that nothing can be in the mind of which it is not aware. That is a 
prejudice which impedes the understanding of the mind. 7 

Lichtenberg, a hunch-backed genius, satirical writer, and professor 
of physics at Goettingen, regarded dreams as a means to self-know- 
ledge, and thoughts as products of the Id: 

It thinks, one ought to say. We become aware of certain 
representations which do not depend on us; others depend on us, or 
at least so we believe; where is the boundary? One should say, it 
thinks, just as one says, it rains. To say cogito is already too much if 
one translates it by I think'. 

The same protest is echoed by Lamartine: e I never think — my 
thoughts think for me.' 

Kant is probably the driest among the great philosophers — who 
would have suspected him among the forerunners of Freud? — : 

The field of our sense-perceptions and sensations, of which we are 
not conscious, though we. undoubtedly can infer that we possess 
them, that is, the dark ideas in man, is immeasurable. The clear ones 



THINKING ASIDE 



151 



in contrast cover infinitely few points which he open to conscious- 
ness; so that in fact on the great map of our spirit only a few points 
are iUuminated. 8 

The German physician and philosopher E. Platner — of whom I 
confess never to have heard before — was, according to Whyte, the first 
to use the term Unhewusstsein, unconsciousness, and to assert that 
thinking is a constant oscillation between conscious and unconscious 
processes: 

Consciousness is no essential part of an idea. Ideas with conscious- 
ness I call apperceptions following Leibniz; ideas without conscious- 
ness perceptions, or dark images. The life of the mind is an unbroken 
series of actions, a continuous series of ideas of both kinds. For 
apperceptions alternate with perceptions throughout life. Ideas with 
consciousness are often the psychological results of ideas without 
consciousness. 9 

As we approach the nineteenth century, the single voices grow into 
a chorus in praise of the creative faculties of the unconscious mind. It is 
perhaps most audible in Germany; among those who join in are, to 
mention only a few, Herder, Schelling, Hegel, Goethe, Fichte. Here, 
for instance, is Goethe: 

Man cannot persist long in a conscious state, he must throw himself 
back into the Unconscious, for his root lives there. . . . Take for 
example a talented musician, composing an important score: 
consciousness and unconsciousness will be Eke warp and weft. 10 

Jean-Paul Richter, an outstanding novelist (unfortunately little 
known in England): 

The unconscious is really the largest realm in our minds, and just 
on account of this unconsciousness it is an inner Africa, whose 
unknown boundaries may extend far away. Why should everything 
come to consciousness that lies in the mind since, for example, that 
of which it has already been aware, the whole great realm of 
memory, only appears to it iUurriinated in small areas while the 
entire reniaining world stays invisible in the shadows? And may 
there not be a second half world of our mental moon which never 
turns towards consciousness? 

The most powerful thing in the poet, which blows the good and 
the evil spirit into his works, is precisely the unconscious. . . . u 



152 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



I. H. Echte (a psychologist, son of the philosopher) postulated the 
existence of pre-conscious states: 

Beneath active consciousness there must He consciousness in a 
merely potential state, that is a middle condition of the mind, which 
though not yet conscious, none the less positively carries the specific 
character of Intelligence; from those conditions of preconscious 
existence the true consciousness must be explained and developed 
step by step. 12 

in France the Cartesian spirit survived longest — until the second half 
of the nineteenth century in fact, when Charcot and his colleagues 
revolutionized psychiatry (Freud, at one time, had studied under 
Charcot). But in England the concept of the unconscious had a long 
and distinguished line of ancestors, some of whom I have already 
quoted. Here is Abraham Tucker, an influential philosopher, writing 
around 1750: 

. . . our mental organs do not stand idle the moment we cease to 
employ them, but continue the motions we put into them after 
they have gone out of our sight, thereby working themselves to a 
glibness and smoothness and falling into a more regular and orderly 
posture than we could have placed them with all our skill and 
industry. 13 

The term 'unconscious cerebration* was coined by W. B. Carpenter, 
a nineteenth-century physician and naturalist: 

. . . That action of the brain which, through unconscious cerebra- 
tion, produces results w T hich might never have been produced by 
thought. 14 

Other characteristic English coinages are Wordsworth's 'caverns in 
the mind which sun can never penetrate*, Coleridge's 'twilight realm 
of consciousness', William James's 'fringe consciousness', and Myers's 
'subliminal self'. In i860 Sir Thomas Laycock wrote that — 

no general fact is so well established by the experience of mankind or 

so universally accepted as a guide in the affairs of life, as that of 

unconscious life and action 16 

And Maudsley, writing a few years later: 

The most important part of mental action, the essential process on 
which thinking depends, is unconscious mental activity. 16 



THINKING ASIDE 



153 



For the climax of this story we must return to Germany in the 
second half of the nineteenth century. The pioneers of German 
experimental psychology were Fechner ('Fechner 's law') and Wilhelm 
Wundt. Fechner's attitude is summed up in his famous metaphor of 
the mind as an iceberg, with only a fraction of it above the surface of 
consciousness, moved by the winds of awareness, but mostly by hidden 
under-water currents. Wundt continued where Fechner had left off: 
Our mind is so fortunately equipped, that it brings us the most 
important bases for our thoughts without our having the least know- 
ledge of this work of elaboration. Only the results of it become 
conscious. This unconscious mind is for us like an unknown being 
who creates and produces for us, and finally throws the ripe fruits in 
our lap. 17 

At about the same time, in 1868, Erich von Hartmann published his 
Philosophy of the Unconscious, which became a best-seller. From a period 
novel by the popular Spielhagen we learn that in 1870 two main topics 
dominated conversation in the intellectual salons of Berlin: Wagner 
and the Unconscious. We are reminded of the scene in the London 
salon of Disraeli's play, where the fashionable topic of Evolution is 
discussed — fifteen years before anybody had heard the name of 
Darwin. Whyte lists six philosophical works published within ten 
years after von Hartmann' s which carry the word 'unconscious' in 
their tides. In the literature of the period Nietzsche was the towering 
giant. He took over the unconscious Id from Lichtenberg (which 
Groddeck then took over from Nietzsche, and Freud from Groddeck); 
it is one of the leitmotifs in Nietzsche's work: 

Where are the new doctors of the soul?. . . Consciousness is the last 
and latest development of the organic, and is consequendy the most 
unfinished and least powerful of these developments. Every extension 
of knowledge arises from making conscious the unconsciousness. The 
great basic activity is unconscious. For it is narrow, this room of 
human consciousness. 

Whyte concludes: 'The general conception of unconscious mental 
process was conceivable (in post-Cartesian Europe) around 1700, topical 
around 1800, and fashionable around 1870-1880. ... It cannot be 
disputed that by 1870-1880 the general conception of the unconscious 
mind was a European commonplace and that many special applications 
of this general idea had been vigorously discussed for several decades.* 18 



154 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



I have confined this digest to unconscious thinking] there is an equal 
abundance in relevant quotations which refer to the motivational, 
affective, and pathological aspects of the unconscious, and of the dream. 
My intent was not to belitde either the greatness or the originality of 
Freud — that would be as stupid as trying to run down Newton because 
he had 'stood on the shoulders of giants'. But while Newton was aware 
of this — the expression is his own — Freud, curiously, was not. He never 
realized how respectable the idea was on which he built his edifice. 

The Mechanization of Habits 

The feeling of mystery — or of wary scepticism — which mention of 
'the unconscious' evokes is part of our mental heritage, derived from 
the Cartesian tradition. The tenacity of that tradition, deeply engrained 
in our thinking habits, makes us constantly forget the obvious fact — 
rubbed in by everyday experience — that awareness is a matter of 
degrees. Conscious and unconscious experiences do not belong to 
different compartments of the mind; they form a continuous scale of 
gradations, of degrees of awareness. .We may call, as Leibniz did, 
conscious events 'light', unconscious ones 'dark* — provided that we 
remember the infinite shadings from lighter to darker grey between 
them. The dark end of the scale extends well below the human level to 
an unknown limit — which may possibly be some form of 'proto- 
plasmic consciousness'; Bergson even asserted that 'the unconscious- 
ness of a falling stone is something different from the unconsciousness 
of a growing cabbage*. 

In human beings we find at the bottom of the scale the self- 
regulating activities which control the viscera and glands, the circula- 
tion of the blood and other physiological processes of which we are 
normally unaware; yet in their ensemble they may supply that 
vegetative or bovine consciousness of being warmly alive and kicking. 
From here on the scale of awareness ascends to the more or less 
mechanical — i.e. less or more conscious — exercise of practised skills: 
from walking along a road to picking one's way through puddles in 
the rain, to climbing an exposed rock-face; from tying one's shoe- 
strings to knotting a broken shoe-string; humming a tune absent- 
mindedly — singing it to an audience; adding up a column of figures 
mechanically — checking it, after a mistake has been discovered, with 
great attention. At the top of the scale we find the quasi-hypnotic state 



THINKING ASIDB 



155 



of utter concentration on a problem, or absorption in a thriller, blind 
and deaf to one's surroundings. 

Equally continuous gradients of awareness are found in the exercise 
of perceptual and cognitive skills, the working of memory, the ebbs 
and tides of emotion. We are conscious only of a fraction of the input 
into our eyes, ears, and skin; yet the intake is registered nevertheless. 
We are unaware of the ticking of the clock, but aware that it has 
stopped. While reading we are unaware of the shape of the letters 
because the skill of transforming them into words is fully automatized* 
and awareness is focussed on the meaning behind the shapes — a pheno- 
menon known as the 'transparency' of language. We summon 
memories asleep in the dormitory of the mind, while others barge in 
uninvited. Oddest of all, we hold ourselves and others responsible for 
forgetting something which ought to have been remembered. The 
schoolboy who has left his gym-shoes at home, the maid who has 
forgotten to put sugar on the breakfast tray, are held responsible for 
unconscious acts of omission. 

The greater mastery and ease we gain in the exercise of a skill, the 
more automatized it will tend to become, because the code of rules 
which controls it now operates below the threshold of awareness. But 
the degree of conscious attention which accompanies the performance 
depends also on a second factor: the prevailing environmental condi- 
tions, the lie of the land—whether it is familiar, or contains unusual 
features. The inexperienced driver must concentrate even on an empty 
road. The experienced driver functions automatically; but he must 
concentrate in heavy traffic. 

We may then, somewhat paradoxically, describe awareness as that 
experience which decreases and fades away with our increasing mastery 
of a skill exercised under monotonous conditions. Mastery of the code 
and stability of environment are the two factors which lead to the 
formation of habit; and habit-formation is accompanied by a gradual 
dimming and darkening of the lights of awareness. On the other hand, 
we may regard this tendency towards the progressive automatization 
of skills as an act of mental parsimony, as a handing-down of the 
controls to lower levels in the hierarchy of nervous functions, enabling 
the higher levels to turn to more challenging tasks. Thus the typist can 
go on transcribing letters while t&inking of her boy friend; and the boy 
friend can drive the car while discussing with her their weekend plans 
— thanks to the benevolent workings of the principle of parsimony, 
which seems to be an essential factor in mental progress. 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



To revert to an earlier example: the beginner, hopefully facing a 
chessboard, feels uncertain about the manner in which bishops and 
rooks are permitted to move, and has to consult his textbook or his 
teacher. After some practice it becomes impossible for him to move a 
rook diagonally without a feeling of aesthetic and moral revulsion, of 
having committed an obscenity or violated a sacred taboo: the rules 
have become automatized, encoded in the circuitry of his nervous 
system. At a still later stage he learns to apply certain stratagems just as 
automatically: to avoid 'pins' and 'forks', not to expose the king, to 
seek open rook files, etc. In games simpler than chess the same type of 
situation will recur over and again, and the appropriate stratagems will 
be codified in their turn. Computer engineers have actually built elec- 
tronic brains in which both the rules and the stratagems of simple board 
games, such as noughts and crosses, are built into the memory' of the 
machine. They can beat any opponent if he blunders, and draw if he 
plays a correct game. The machine illustrates the process of relegating 
familiar tasks to lower levels of the mental hierarchy which function 
as unawares — or nearly — as involuntary reflexes. 

But how does all this relate to mental creativity? Only indirectly. 
The intervention of unconscious processes in the creative act is a 
phenomenon quite different from the automatization of skills; and our 
unawareness of the sources of inspiration is of a quite different order 
from the unawareness of what we are doing while we tie our shoe- 
strings or copy a letter on the typewriter. In the creative act there is an 
upward surge from some unknown, fertile, underground layers of the 
mind; whereas the process I have described is a downward relegation of 
the controls of skilled techniques. 

In fact I have so far discussed only one aspect or dimension of 
consciousness: let us call it the linear scale, or linear gradient of aware- 
ness. At one end of the scale we found routines performed without 
awareness; at the opposite end the smgle-minded, hyper-awake 
concentration on a problem, where consciousness is focussed into a 
narrow beam with darkness all round. But such a one-dimensional 
interpretation of the varieties of consciousness, as a line running from 
automatism to obsession, seems highly unsatisfactory. Consciousness 
is a multi-dimensional affair, as I hope to show in the pages that follow. 
The 'linear* gradient of awareness which I have discussed is only one of 
these dimensions— though nevertheless an important one. It is along 
that gradient that learning is transformed into habit, that the control 
of new skills, once mastered, slides down under its own gravity 



THINKING ASIDE 



157 



as it were, into the basement, making room upstairs for new 
acquisitions. 

A pianist, after practising a piece for some time, can reel it off 'in his 
sleep*, as the saying goes. The exact opposite of this process is illustrated 
by the famous case of Tartini composing the Devil's Trill Sonata while 
asleep. The first example shows the unconscious as a repository of 
habits which no longer need being attended to'; the second, as a 
breeding ground of novelties. 

It is essential to bear both processes in mind—and not to confuse 
them. Most Behaviourists accept only the first: they regard habit- 
formation as the essence of mental progress; original ideas, on this 
view, are lucky hits among random tries, retained because of their 
utility value— just as biological evolution is held to be the outcome of 
random mutations retained because of their survival value. 

Among those prepared to accept the positive role of the unconscious, 
there is a frequent tendency to confuse downward' and 'upward* 
traffic — to equate automatism with intuition. Some highly developed, 
semi-automatized skills have a great amount of flexibility — the result of 
years of hard trairiing; but their practitioners are devoid of originality. 
Tightrope walkers, acrobats, night-club pianists, and calculating 
prodigies display virtuosity; a virtuoso is denned by the Oxford 
Dictionary as a person skilled in the mechanical part of a fine art*. 
Needless to say, virtuosity may combine in the same person with 
creativity; but in itself it is no more than the highest elaboration of a 
routine with fixed, automatized rules of the game and a malleable 
strategy. 

Such mechanical virtuosity has probably reached its highest devel- 
opment in the Japanese arts inspired by Zen Buddhism: swordsmanship, 
archery, Judo, calligraphic painting. The method to reach perfection 
has been authoritatively described as practice, repetition, and repetition 
of the repeated with ever-increasing intensity', 19 until the adept 
'becomes a kind of automaton, so to speak, as far as his own 
consciousness is concerned*. 20 * That is the method by which Professor 
Skinner of Harvard University, a leader of the Behaviourist school, 
trained pigeons to perform circus acts, intended as an explanation of 
mental development in man. 



i 



Exploring the Shallows 



We have heard conscious thoughts being compared to icebergs, or 
islands in the ocean of unconscious mentation; we have heard Einstein 
affirm that 'full consciousness is a limit case which can never be fully 
accomplished'. Let me proceed from these metaphors to a closer 
analogy, which may help to dispel common illusions about the clarity 
of conscious thought. 

Most people with normal eyesight tend to the flattering belief that 
they see the world around them at any time in sharp focus; in fact, 
however, they see a blur. Only a minute fraction of tie visual field — 
about one-thousandth of it — is seen distinctly; outside of this centre 
vision becomes increasingly vague and hazy. If you gaze fixedly at a 
single word in the centre of the page you are reading, and try to 
prevent your gaze from straying along the line (which is not easy 
because reading is an automatized skill), you will see only about, a 
couple of words sharp in focus, the rest of the line on both sides trails 
off into a haze. And how about the whole page, and the rest of the 
room around you? 

Focal vision subtends an angle of only about four degrees, less than 
the angle at the point of a pin, out of a total field of a hundred and 
eighty degrees. Yet we are unaware of this, because we constandy scan 
the field with, mostly unconscious, movements of the eye, to bring the 
blurred periphery into the narrow beam of focal vision — pinpointed at 
the fovea, the tiny spot at the centre of the retina which alone conveys 
true and distinct sight. 

This much every schoolboy learns (and forgets); but in i960 
experiments at McGill University led to the rather surprising discovery 
that the unconscious movements of the eye are not merely aids to 
clearer vision, but a sine qua non of vision. When the subject's gaze 
remained really fixed on a stationary object (by means of a mechanical 
device, see Book Two, X), his vision went haywire, the image 
of the object disintegrated and disappeared— then reappeared after a 
while but in distorted shape or in fragments. Static vision does not 
exist; there is no seeing without exploring. 

With due caution we can draw a limited analogy between visual 
scanning and mental scamiing — between the blurred, peripheral vision 
outside the focal beam, and the hazy, half-formed notions which 
accompany thinking on the fringes of consciousness. 'Every definite 
image in the mind', wrote William James, 'is steeped and dyed in the 

158 



THINKING ASIDE 



159 



free water that flows round it. With it goes the sense of its relations, 
near and remote, the dying echo of whence it came to us, the dawning 
sense of whither it is to lead. The significance, the value of the image, 
is all in this halo or penumbra that surrounds and escorts it'. 21 

If one attempts to hold fast to a mental image or concept — to hold it, 
immobile and isolated, in the focus of awareness, it will disintegrate, 
like the static, visual image on the fovea: a word, constantly repeated, 
becomes meaningless; an idea, stripped of its hazy penumbra, vanishes 
like the Cheshire Cat, Thinking is never a sharp, neat, linear process; 
it could rather be compared to the progress of a boat on a lake. When 
you day-dream you drift before the wind; when you read or listen to a 
narrative you travel like a barge towed by a tug. But in each case the 
progress of the boat causes ripples on the lake, spreading in all directions 
— memories, images, associations; some of these move quicker than the 
boat itself and create anticipations; others penetrate into the deep. The 
boat symbolizes focal awareness, the ripples on the surface are the 
fringes of consciousness, and you can furnish the deeps, according to 
taste, with the nasty eddies of repressed complexes, the deep-water 
currents of the collective unconscious, or with archetypal coral-reefs. 
When thinking is in the tow of a narrative, focal awareness must stick to 
its course and cannot follow the ripples on their journey across the lake; 
but it is their presence all round the horizon,on the peripheries of aware- 
ness, which provides resonance, colour, and depth, the atmosphere 
and feel of the story. When it comes to productive thinking, however, 
the metaphor breaks down — unless we equip it with an outboard 
motor, a gyro-compass, servo-steering, and other paraphernalia. 

The existence of an intermediary region between the 'limit case' of 
sharp, narrow focal awareness and the vast unconscious regions of the 
mind has been recognized for a long time. Fichte (and later Freud) 
called it the pre-conscious (das Vorbewusstsein), James called it the 
fringe; Polanyi 'subsidiary awareness'; the analogy with vision yielded 
'peripheral awareness'; but since awareness is a matter of degrees, it 
would be mistaken to draw a sharp line between pre- and unconscious 
processes, between the shallows and the deep. What matters is the 
distinction between the single event (the percept, or concept, or word, 
or muscle-action) which for a fleeting moment occupies the focus of* 
attention — and the processes on the periphery which define the context, 
the purpose and meaning of the former. 

But how do they interact? How do pre- or unconscious processes 
influence the direction of thought; how do some enter focal awareness 



i6o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



and sink back again into twilight and darkness; how do they assist 
mental creativity? The answers we have heard up to now were of 
a general nature; they all asserted that such assistance was indispensable 
and did in fact occur; but they had little to say regarding the concrete 
mechanism or procedure through which it was rendered. Perhaps the 
most lucid attempt in this direction was made by that versatile genius 
Francis Galton in a famous analogy: 

When I am engaged in trying to think anything out, the process 
of doing so appears to me to be this: the ideas that lie at any 
moment within my full consciousness seem to attract of their own 
accord the most appropriate out of a number of other ideas that are 
lying close at hand, but imperfectly within the range of my 
consciousness. There seems to be a presence-chamber in my mind 
where full consciousness holds court, and where two or three ideas 
are at the same time in audience, and an ante-chamber full of more 
or less allied ideas, which is situated just beyond the full ken of 
consciousness. Out of this ante-chamber the ideas most nearly allied 
to those in the presence-chamber appear to be summoned in a 
mechanically logical way, and to have their turn of audience. 22 

The italics are mine, and are meant to register protest. Assuming the 
idea in the presence-chamber of my mind is, as it happens to be, Mr. 
Galton himself, I can recall six distinct occasions in the last few months 
when I thought of him. He helped to ease the gloom of my last birth- 
day — because Galton lived to the age of eighty-nine; and the idea 
'most nearly allied', which was summoned from the ante-chamber 
'in a mechanically logical way', was 'Methuselah*. On another occasion 
I read about the acquittal of a woman who had been tried for the 
mercy-killing of her malformed baby; Galton was summoned because 
he had invented the word 'eugenics'; next came, logically, the 'most 
nearly allied' idea of Adolf Hider, whose S.S. men practised eugenics 
after their own fashion. On yet another occasion the closest association 
was 'colour-blindness' — first studied by Dalton which rhymes with 
Galton; and so forth. Each summons into the presence-chamber had 
its own 'mechanical logic', if you wish to call it that; and the choice of 
the 'most nearly allied idea', the order of precedence in the ante- 
chamber, depended on what sort of logic, or rule of the game, was at 
the time in control of the mind. Galton was a pioneer of the experimen- 
tal method in word-association tests; but as a follower of the English 



THINKING ASIDE l6l 

associationist school, he failed to realize that association is always con- 
trolled by a code of rules, whether the subject is aware of it or not; and 
that different codes are active at different times. 

Thus the famous analogy of the ante-chamber of the mind does not 
get us much further; but it helps us to ckrify the problem by showing 
the pitfalls of the mechanistic approach, and leading us back, as it were, 
to our starting point. It was the comparison between the blurred 
periphery of the visual field and the vague intimations which pass 
through the twilight of the pre-conscious. We can now venture a step 
further, and draw a parallel between the part-automatic visual scanning 
of a landscape, and the mental scanning of a land of inner landscape 
in purposive thinking. In both cases, the scanning process is controlled 
by a specific, selective code that determines which features in the 
landscape are relevant and which are not. Scanning a panorama 
through my window purely for pleasure corresponds to the aimless 
drift of thought along the most gratifying features — memories, 
images, pleasurable anticipations — of the inner landscape. But if I 
explore with my eyes the mountain before me for the safest route to 
the summit, or the amount of timber it will yield; for a sign of 
edelweiss, or a strategic gun-site safe from air attack, the whole visual 
field will in each case become organized and patterned in different ways; 
and the scanning motions of my eyes, guiding the beam of focal vision, 
will automatically be governed by certain rules which I am unable to 
name, and by a purposeful strategy determined by the He of the land. 

In this example visual exploration and mental exploration are 
actually indistinguishable; the observational data derived from looking 
at the rock face, and the lessons derived from previous experience 
combine into one. In other situations, the exploratory process may be 
confined to the inner landscape, to the exclusion of all stimuli from 
the world outside. The poet's or the mathematician's trance-like 
condition while he concentrates on a problem, the vivid fantasies of 
the day-dreamer, the delusions of the insane, the dreams of the sleeper, 
are products of widely different games of the mind; but they all have 
this in common, that the beam of focal awareness is exploring the inner 
environment, and ignoring the input from the senses. The features on 
which the beam alights are images of a pictorial or verbal nature, 
memories in abstracted, conceptualized, or distorted shape; in a word, 
they are past experiences internalized. The inner landscape may be 
regarded as a kind of private, miniature model — or caricature — of the 
world in the subject's brain-mind (see Book Two). 



102 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Thus the objects of the scanning process are ultimately the individual's 
past experiences (including his pre-natal past) incorporated in one form 
or another into his mental landscape. And the rules which control the 
scanning process (the pattern of 'mental eye motions 5 , as it were) are 
also derived from past experiences by abstraction and generalization; 
they are the results of learning compressed into the operational codes 
of thinking skills. 

As an example, take the parlour game 'Towns with M' (see page 38). 
The moment I start playing it a fixed code takes control of my mental 
processes, and their freedom is whittled down to strategic choices. 
These may be based on exploring an imagined geographical map, or 
on the 'tuning-fork' method. The mental map is a blurred, ha2y, and 
distorted replica of what I learned in school and on travels; but as I 
proceed to scan it, from west to east with the mind's eye, name after 
name emerges from the misty twilight: Manchester, Munich, Moscow, 
Murmansk, Michigan, etc. If, on the other hand, I apply the tuning- 
fork method, Manchester will call out Mannheim, Madrid, Madras, 
and so forth. All of these names were learned in the past; all of them were 
members of the 'M' matrix (otherwise they could not have been 
summoned on the 'wavelength' of that particular code); all of them 
were unconscious or pre-conscious the moment before the beam of 
focal awareness alighted on them. The beam was guided firstly by the 
rule of the game (Tind towns with M, not rivers with 5'), and secondly 
by strategy ('move from west to east'). The rule was fixed, the strategy 
variable. A further point to note is (though it does not concern us yet) 
that strategy operates by a kind of feed-back from the lie of the land: 
I was searching for towns with 'M' between Munich and Moscow, 
but found none: so I moved on. Other factors enter: I might have 
remembered Mannheim, but did not because of an unpleasant exper- 
ience there: emotional disturbances interfering with 'mechanical logic'. 
Incidentally, the forming of a sentence in ordinary conversation 
follows a similar pattern. Instead of scanning a map for towns with 'M', 
you must scan your vocabulary for words which will fit a given 
meaning. 

Take an even simpler practical example. I live in London and have 
to spend a day in Paris some time next week to see my French publisher. 
If this were a pleasure-trip the fringes of my consciousness would at 
once be crowded with half-remembered, floating images of bistros, 
streets, galleries, metro stations; but, as it is a business trip, a different 
code enters into action and the matrix is cluttered with timetables, 



THINKING ASIDE 



appointment books, galley proofs, and dustcovers, which strategic 
planning must co-ordinate into the proper sequence. 

Purposive thinking, even of this ordinary, humdrum kind, proceeds 
in several steps. First, the code of rules appropriate to the task is 'tuned 
in' — by dint of analogy with similar tasks encountered in the past. As 
a result, a matrix will emerge, a kind of patterned mental grid or chess- 
board, which provides a preliminary selection of permissible moves, a 
first guidance for the exploratory process. Next comes strategy, 
dependent upon the particulars of the situation. 

Each step involves processes more or less removed from focal 
awareness. The code which guides the focal beam of consciousness 
functions more or less unconsciously. (It could not be otherwise, for if 
the beam were guided by the beam, we would be landed in the 
paradox of a little man inside the brain with a little man inside his 
brain, and so forth.) The codes of grammar and syntax function 
unconsciously; the meaning you wish to express provides the strategy 
for selecting the proper word. The words— just like the towns with 
*M' — were lying in darkness before the beam searched them out and 
lit them up for a fleeting moment; then they sink back into darkness 
again. 

Thus all reasoning, even of a trivial order, is steeped in unconscious 
processes. But when the task is of a more complex order, thinking may 
run into difficulty at each of the steps which I have outlined. A situation 
may share certain features with other situations encountered in the past, 
yet the code of rules which enabled us to cope with them proves 
mysteriously inadequate in the new situation. Bleeding and purging the 
patient proved beneficial in a number of cases, so it came to be regarded 
as an all-cure; why did it not work? We can bisect an angle with 
compass and ruler, so it was assumed that we can trisect angles by the 
same method; but it did not work. Sound waves are propagated in thin 
air, so it was assumed that light waves are propagated in a thin ether; 
but the analogy provided the wrong matrix. Circles turning upon 
circles yielded an adequate description of heavenly morions, until 
Tycho perfected the methods of observation; the new data disrupted 
the pattern, and the matrix was blocked. 

When a situation is blocked, straight thinking must be superseded 
by 'thinking aside* — the search for a new, auxiliary matrix which will 
unblock it, without having ever before been called to perform such a 
task. The essence of discovery is to hit upon such a matrix — as 
Gutenberg hit on the wine-press and Kepler on the sun-force. 



164 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



In the trivial routines of thinking, we are exploring the shallows 
on the twilight periphery of awareness, guided by a more or less 
automatized scanning procedure. In creative thinking we are exploring 
the deeps, without any obvious guidance. Yet some guidance there 
must be — unless all novelty is due to random hits produced by the 
patient monkey on the typewriter. 

The 'Hooked Atoms of Thought* 

Let me return once more to Henri Poincare, who proposed a theory 
concerning the nature of this unconscious guidance. We have heard 
him describe how, on three different occasions, the solution of a 
problem popped up spontaneously and ready-made, as it were, from 
the depths of the unconscious. Further on in that famous lecture from 
which I have quoted (pp. 114-16) he tried to give an explanation of 
this phenomenon. His starting point was that mathematical discovery 
consists in a 'combination of ideas'; and his description of this process 
stresses the characteristic features of what I have called the bisociative 
act: 

Among chosen combinations the most fertile will often be those 
formed of elements drawn from domains which are far apart. . . . 
Most combinations so formed would be entirely sterile; but certain 
among them, very rare, are the most fruitful of all. 

Now these combinations are engineered by the unconscious or, as 
he calls it, the Subliminal self*; but how? There are, he says, two 
possibilities. The first is that the unconscious 'is capable of discernment; 
it has tact, delicacy; it knows how to choose, to divine. What do I say? 
It knows better how to divine than the conscious self since it succeeds 
where that has failed. In a word, is not the subliminal self superior to 
the conscious self? I confess that, for my part, I should hate to accept 
this. . . .* So he rejects this first hypothesis in favour of the second: 
the unconscious is an automaton which mechanically runs through all 
possible combinations: 

Figure the future elements of our combinations as something like 
the hooked atoms of Epicurus. During the complete repose of the 
mind, these atoms are motionless, they are, so to speak, hooked to the 



THINKING ASIDE 



wall. During a period of apparent rest and unconscious work, 
certain of them are detached from the wall and put in motion. They 
flash in every direction through the space ... as would, for example, 
a swarm of gnats, or if you prefer a more learned comparison, like 
the molecules of gas in the kinematic theory of gases. Then their 
mutual impacts may produce new combinations. 

But two objections come to his mind. Firstly, is not the number of 
possible combinations infinite, and the chance of hitting on a favourable 
one infinitesimal? No, he answers, because during the conscious 
preparatory work which preceded the period of unconscious incuba- 
tion, a first selection was already made of those atoms which are to be 
unhooked from the wall; and although no satisfactory combination of 
them was found, 'after this shaking up imposed upon them by our will, 
these atoms do not return to their previous rest. They freely continue 
to dance* — until the one favourable collision in a rnillion occurs. (This 
is rather like saying that the chances of the monkey on the typewriter 
hitting on a Shakespeare sonnet would be considerably improved by 
building a typewriter which uses whole words as keys instead of 
letters.) 

The second objection which occurred to Poincare is as follows: 
although coundess combinations are formed 'in consequence of the 
automatism of the subliminal self, only the interesting ones . . . break 
into the domain of consciousness*. But, if so, what is the nature of the 
mysterious sieve which rejects the useless combinations and allows only 
the lucky hits to pass into consciousness? Poincare's answer is that 
the selection is done by 'the aesthetic sensibility of the real creator. The 
useful combinations are precisely the most beautiful, I mean those best 
able to charm this special sensibility*. 

This is certainly a more attractive answer than Galton's, who sum- 
mons ideas from the ante-chamber 'in a mechanically logical way'; yet 
Poincare himself felt its unsatisfaaoriness. For it combines a mechanistic 
theory about the random collision of atomic ideas in the unconscious, 
with an aesthetic sensibility which resides in the conscious, and plays 
the part of a deus ex machina* We do not doubt that this kind of 
sensibility is present in the creative rnind, and to inquire into its nature 
is precisely what we are after; but Poincare lets the matter rest just 
where the problem starts. 

Particularly fascinating in this lecture, delivered in 1908, is the fact 
that Poincare, after acknowledging his debt to the 'subliminal self' and 



I<5<5 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



singing its praises, confesses that he would 'hate to accept' that it might 
in some respects be superior to the conscious self, and relegates it to the 
role of an automatic mixing machine in the basement. He worked by 
intuition, but for all his modesty and open-mindedness he was unable 
to shake off the rationalist hubris of the nineteenth century.* 

Exploring the Deeps 

All we have gleaned from these excursions into the history of our 
subject, from Plotinus to Poincare, is firsdy, a negative insight into the 
narrow limitations of conscious thinking; and on the positive side, 
affirmations of the superiority of unconscious mentation at certain 
stages of creative work. But regarding the reasons for this superiority, 
and the process by which it manifests itself, we got merely a few vague 
intimations, or else unsatisfactory mechanistic hypotheses such as 
Gallon's and Poincare's. Nor, I may add here, had Freud or Jung much 
to say about the specific problem how unconscious processes lead to 
new discoveries. 

Let us at this stage follow the advice we have so often heard repeated, 
and 'think aside' — by turning, for a moment, from scientists to poets. 
If we were to apply Poincare's hypothesis we would come to the 
conclusion that the poet has a conscious mind endowed with aesthetic 
sensibility, and an unconscious mind equipped with an automatic 
rhyme-computer (built on the principle of rhyming lexicons), and also 
with an image computer (a kind of magic lantern with an automatic 
slide-changer). Out of the hundreds of rhymes and similes produced 
per minute the vast majority would, of course, be, valueless, and the 
aesthetic censor in the conscious mind would have a full-time job 
rejecting them— until he went out of his mind. 

It seems neither an economical nor an inspired procedure. Now let 
us listen to Coleridge's celebrated description of the genesis of Kubla 
Khan. He is speaking of himself in the third person singular: 

In the summer of the year 1797, the Author, then in ill health, had 
retired to a lonely farm-house between Porlock and Linton. ... In 
consequence of a slight indisposition, an anodyne had been 
prescribed, from the effects of which he fell asleep in his chair at the 
moment that he was reading the following sentence, or words of the 
same substance, in Purchases Pilgrimage: 



THINKING ASIDE 



I67 



'Here the Khan Kubla commanded a palace to be built, and a 
stately garden thereunto. And thus ten miles of fertile ground were 
enclosed with a wall/ 

The Author continued for about three hours in a profound sleep, 
at least of the external senses [sic] during which time he has the most 
vivid confidence, that he could not have composed less than from 
two to three hundred lines; if that indeed can be called composition 
in which all the images rose up before him as things with a parallel 
production of the correspondent expressions, without any sensation 
or consciousness of effort. On awakening he appeared to himself to 
have a distinct recollection of the whole, and taking his pen, ink, and 
paper, instantly and eagerly wrote down the lines that are here 
preserved. 

This, of course, is an extreme case of unconscious production — even 
if, in all likelihood, it did not originate in a dream, but in an intense day- 
dream or hypnogogic state. (In another, and probably earlier, statement 
Coleridge gives a different version: 'This fragment with a good deal 
more, not recoverable, composed in a sort of Reverie brought on by 
two grains of Opium, taken to check a dysentery.' The 'reverie* 
version is strengthened by the words 'in a profound sleep, at least of the 
external senses 9 — which point towards some intermediary kind of 
'waking dream'.) 

But whether he was asleep or half asleep is unimportant; the point 
to note is the emphasis he puts on visual images which rose up as 
things'. Unfortunately, no sooner had he started on the actual writing 
down of the poem than he was interrupted 'by a person on business 
from Porlock, and detained by him above an hour, and on his return to 
his room, found, to his no small surprise and mortification . . . that with 
the exception of some eight or ten scattered lines and images, all the 
rest had passed away like the images on the surface of a stream into which a 
stone has been cast*. This incidental metaphor suddenly sets off in its 
author another chain of visual imagery which illustrates how the dream 
version of 'Kubla Khan' was lost, thanks to the gentleman from 
Porlock, but reconstructed later on out of the remaining fragments. 
After the 'stone had been cast*: 

... all the charm 
Is broken— all that phantom-world so fair 
Vanishes, and a thousand circlets spread, 



168 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



And each mis-shape the other. Stay awhile, 
Poor youth! . . . 

The stream will soon renew its smoothness, soon 
The visions will return! And lo, he stays, 
And soon the fragments dim of lovely forms 
Come trembling back, unite, and now once more 
The pool becomes a mirror. 

The whole poem, with its rather striking allegory, grew out of a 
hackneyed metaphor, which was meant to serve only as a visual 
illustration to a verbal narrative. But all at once the servant becomes 
master, the illustration takes over from the text; visual association, the 
logic of the eye are in command, and the words must follow their 
lead. ... 

We further note that the whole sequence of not less than from two 
to three hundred lines' of the Kubk Khan dream itself was triggered off 
by a passage read in Purchases Pilgrimage, as indifferent as the simile of 
the stone cast into the stream: 'Here the Khan Kubla commanded a 
palace to be built', etc. But at that point his imagination caught on, the 
opium took effect, visual thinking took over, and images rose up as 
things'. 

Thinking in pictures dominates the manifestations of the unconscious 
— the dream, the hypnogogic half-dream, the psychotic's hallucina- 
tions, the artist's 'vision'. (The 'visionary' prophet seems to have been 
a visualizer, and not a verbalizer; the highest compliment we pay to 
those who trade in verbal currency is to call them 'visionary thinkers'.) 

But, on the other hand, pictorial thinking is a more primitive form 
of mentation than conceptual thinking, which it precedes in the 
mental evolution of the individual and of the species. The language of 
the primitive (and of the child) is, to borrow Kretschmer's simile, 'like 
the unfolding of a picture-strip: each word expresses a picture, a 
pictorial image, regardless of whether it signifies an object or an 
action'. In Golding's novel The Inheritors the Neanderthal men always 
say 'I had a picture' when they mean 'I thought of something'; and 
anthropologists agree that for once a novelist got the picture right. 

Thus the poet who reverts to the pictorial mode of thought is 
regressing to an older and lower level of the mental hierarchy — as we do 
every night when we dream, as mental patients do when they regress 
to infantile fantasies. But the poet, unlike the dreamer in his sleep, 
alternates between two different levels of the mental hierarchy; the 



THINKING ASIDE 



169 



dreamer s awareness functions on one only. The poet thinks both in 
images and verbal concepts, at the same time or in quick alternation; 
each trouvaille, each original find, bisociates two matrices. The dreamer 
floats among the phantom shapes of the hoary deep; the poet is a skin- 
diver with a breathing tube. 

Similar considerations apply — and will be discussed in Part HI 
— to rhythm, metre, alliteration, assonance, rhyme. The rhythmic beat, 
echoing the shaman's tom-tom, awakens archaic resonances and lulls 
the mind into a waking trance' (Yeats). The rhyme appeals to the 
tendency to vocal repetition in the language of primitives and children 
(kala-kala, ma-ma), and to the equally deep-rooted tendency to 
associate by sound — punning. To conclude this anticipatory excursion: 
the creative activity of the artist involves momentary regressions to 
earlier stages in mental evolution, bringing forms of mentation into 
play which otherwise manifest themselves only in the dream or dream- 
like states. 

The Word and the Vision 

Let us return from poets to scientists, and to the question what 
guidance the latter could possibly derive from the intervention of 
unconscious processes. The answer which, by analogy, now suggests 
itself is that the temporary relinquishing of conscious controls liberates the 
mind from certain constraints which are necessary to maintain the disciplined 
routines of thoughts hut may become an impediment to the creative leap; at 
the same time other types of ideation on more primitive levels of mental 
organization are brought into activity. The first part of this sentence 
indicates an act of abdication, the second an act of promotion. It will 
be useful to remember this dual aspect of the Eureka act; it will be seen, 
later on, to correspond to the destructive-constructive character of all 
great revolution in the history of thought. 

The scientific counterpart of the Coleridge episode is the Kekule" 
episode (p. 118). But the vision of the serpent biting its tail was only the 
last one in a series, which extended over a period of seven or eight years. 
This is how Kekule described one of the early but decisive quasi- 
haHucinations, which led to his theory of molecular constitution— he 
was then living in London: 

'One fine summer evening,' he relates, 'I was returning by the last 
omnibus, "outside" as usual, through the deserted streets of the 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



metropolis, which are at other times so full of life. I fell into a reverie, 
and lo! the atoms were gambolling before my eyes. Whenever, 
hitherto, these diminutive beings had appeared to me, they had 
always been in motion; but up to that time, I had never been able to 
discern the nature of their motion. Now, however, I saw how, 
frequently, two smaller atoms united to form a pair; how a larger one 
embraced two smaller ones; how still larger ones kept hold of three 
or even four of the smaller; whilst the whole kept whirling in a giddy 
dance. I saw how the larger ones formed a chain ... I spent part 
of the night putting on paper at least sketches of these dream 
forms/ 23 

The whirling, giddy vision reminds one of the hallucinations of 
schizophrenics, as painted or described by them. Kekule's case is rather 
exceptional, but nevertheless characteristic in one respect: the sudden 
abdication of conceptual thought in favour of semi-conscious visual 
conceits. 

Another example is Michael Faraday, one of the greatest physicists 
of all time, who also was a Visionary* not only in the metaphorical but 
in the literal sense. He saw the stresses surrounding magnets and 
electric currents as curves in space, for which he coined the name 'lines 
of forces', and which, in his imagination, were as real as if they consisted 
of solid matter. He visualized the universe patterned by these lines — or 
rather by narrow tubes through which all forms of 'ray- vibrations' or 
energy-radiations are propagated. This vision of curved tubes which 
'rose up before him like things' proved of almost incredible fertility: it 
gave birth to the dynamo and the electric motor; it led Faraday to 
discard the ether, and to postulate that light was electro-magnetic 
radiation. Perhaps the most remarkable fact about Faraday is that he 
lacked any mathematical education or gift, and was 'ignorant of all but 
the merest elements of arithmetic'; and mathematics is of course 
regarded as an indispensable tool of the physicist. In his Faraday 
memorial lecture in 1881, von Helmholtz — himself one of the greatest 
mathematical physicists of the century — remarked: 

It is in the highest degree astonishing to see what a large number 
of general theorems, the methodical deduction of which requires the 
highest powers of mathematical analysis, he found by a kind of 
intuition, with the security of instinct, without the help of a single 
mathematical formula. 24 



THINKING ASIDE 



171 



Kekule's visions resemble hallucinatory flights; Faraday's, the stable 
delusional systems of paranoia. Kekule's serpent reminds one of 
paintings by Blake; the curves of force which crowd Faraday's universe 
recall the vortices in Van Gogh's skies. 

Around fifty — like Newton, and at the same age — Faraday had a 
nervous breakdown. He had always hated writing letters and had 
stopped lecturing; now he seemed to have developed an abhorrence of 
language itself: 'This is to declare in the present instance, when I say I 
am not able to bear much talking, it means really, and without any 
mistake, or equivocation or oblique meaning, or implication, or 
subterfuge, or omission, that I am not able, being at present rather weak 
in the head and able to work no more.' 25 Distrust of words is a trait 
often found among those who create with their eyes. 

Let us leave the borderlands of pathology. Nobody could have been 
further removed from it than the mild, sober, and saintly Einstein. Yet 
we find in him the same distrust of conscious conceptual thought, and 
the same reliance on visual imagery. In 1945 an inquiry was organized 
among eminent mathematicians in America to find out their working 
methods. In reply to the questionnaire which was sent to him, Einstein 
wrote: 

The words or the language, as they are written or spoken, do not 
seem to play any role in my mechanism of thought. The physical 
entities which seem to serve as elements in thought are certain signs 
and more or less clear images which can be Voluntarily' reproduced 
and combined. 

. . . Taken from a psychological viewpoint, this combinatory play 
seems to be the essential feature in productive thought — before there 
is any connection with logical construction in words or other kinds 
of signs which can be communicated to others. 

The above-mentioned elements are, in any case, of visual and some 
of muscular type. Conventional words or other signs have to be 
sought for laboriously only in a secondary stage, when the mentioned 
associative play is sufficiently established and can be reproduced at 
will. 

According to what has been said, the play with the mentioned 
elements is aimed to be analogous to certain logical connections one 
is searching for. 

In a stage when words intervene at all, they are, in my case, purely 



172 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



auditive, but they interfere only in a secondary stage as already 
mentioned. 26 

The inquiry was organized by Jacques Hadamard, whom I have 
repeatedly quoted, since he is to my knowledge the only mathematician 
who has made a systematic research into the psychology of mathe- 
matical creation. Of himself he said: 

I distinctly belong to the auditory type; and precisely on that 
account my mental pictures are exclusively visual. The reason for 
that is quite clear to me: such visual pictures are more naturally 
vague, as we have seen it to be necessary in order to lead me without 
misleading me. 

He summed up the results of the inquiry as follows: 

Among the mathematicians born or resident in America . . . 
phenomena are mostly analogous to those which I have noticed in 
my own case. Practically all of them . . . avoid not only the use of 
mental words but also, just as I do, the mental use of algebraic or any 
other precise signs; also as in my case, they use vague images. . . .* 
The mental pictures ... are most frequently visual, but they may 
also be of another kind for instance, kinetic. There can also be 
auditive ones, but even these . . . quite generally keep their vague 
character. 27 

It rather sounds as if mathematical discoveries were born out of the 
airy nothings of A Midsummer Night's Dream: 

... as imagination bodies forth 
The forms of things unknown, the poet's pen 
Turns them to shapes, and gives to airy nothing 
A local habitation and a name. 

The inquiry brought conclusive proof that among mathematicians, 
verbal thinking plays only a subordinate part in the decisive phase of 
the creative act; and there is a mass of evidence to show that this is also 
the rule among original thinkers in other branches of science. 

This is a rather startling discovery in view of the fact that language 
is the proudest possession o£homo sapiens, and the very foundation on 



THINKING ASIDE 



173 



which mental evolution could build. 'Logic' derives from logos, which 
originally meant 'language', 'thought', and 'reason*, all in one. Think- 
ing in concepts emerged out of thinking in images through the slow 
development of the powers of abstraction and symbolization, as the 
phonetic script emerged by similar processes out of pictorial symbols 
and hieroglyphs. Most of us were brought up in the belief that 
'thinking' is synonymous with verbal thinking, and philosophers 
from Athens to Oxford have kept reasserting this belief. The early 
Behaviourists went even further, asserting not only that words are 
indispensable to thought, but also that thinking is nothing more than 
the subliminal movements of the vocal chords, an inaudible whispering 
to oneself. Yet if all thinking were verbal thinking Einstein would not 
qualify as a thinker. In fact, the whole evidence points in the opposite 
direction, summed up in a single sentence in Woodworth's classic 
textbook of experimental psychology: 'Often we have to get away 
from speech in order to think clearly/ And we heard one testimony 
after another from great scientists, which show that in order to create 
they had to regress at times from the word to the picture-strip, from 
verbal symbolism to visual symbolism — some, like Einstein, even to 
the kinesthetic sensation of muscle-motions. The word 'regression is 
appropriate, because the high aesthetic value which we put on visual 
imagery should not obscure the fact that as vehicles of thought, pictorial 
and other non-verbal representations are indeed earlier, both phylo- 
genetically and ontogenetically older forms of ideation, than verbal 
thinking. Kekule's 'Let us dream, gentlemen', is an invitation to regres- 
sion and retreat— -but a regression which prepares the forward leap, a 
reader pour mieux sauter. 



The Snares of Language 

The necessity for this retreat derives from the fact that words are a 
blessing which can turn into a curse. They crystallize thought; they 
give articulation and precision to vague images and hazy intuitions. 
But a crystal is no longer a fluid. 'Language is not only the foundation 
for the whole faculty of thinking, but the central point also from which 
proceed the misunderstandings of reason by herself.' 28 This was written 
by Hamman, a German philosopher of the eighteenth century, who 
had a great influence on Goethe. Roman Jakobson, a contemporary 
linguist — to quote one among many— voices the same ancient doubt: 



174 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Signs are a necessary support of thought. For socialized thought 
(stage of communication) and for the thought which is being socia- 
lized (stage of formulation), the most usual system of signs is 
language properly called; but internal thought especially when 
creative, willingly uses other systems of signs which are more 
flexible, less standardized than language and leave more liberty, 
more dynamism to creative thought. 29 

The vital importance of language as a thought-crystallizer was per- 
fecdy described by little Alice who, on being admonished to think 
carefully before she spoke, indignantly exclaimed: 'How can I know 
what I think till I see what I say?' For it is, of course, undeniable that 
in some forms of intellectual activity language is not only an indis- 
pensable tool, but that the stream of language actually carries the 
thought, so that the processes of ideation and verbal formulation 
become indistinguishable. The same applies to certain phases in the 
poet's and writer's work; but only to certain phases. The counterpart 
to the little girl's predicament is the little boy's who said: 1 see what I 
mean but I don't know how to say it.' 

Not only scientists, painters, and musicians find it often difficult to 
convert their ideas into verbal currency, but writers too. Even H. G. 
Wells lamented: 'The forceps of our minds are clumsy things and 
crush the truth a little in the course of taking hold of it.' The novelist 
suffers — among other things — from the poverty of his vocabulary 
when he tries to describe what his characters feel (as distinct from what 
they think or do). He can write streams of what goes on in the cranial 
cavity, but if it is a pain in the abdominal cavity, all he can say is, 
'it hurts' — or use some equally insipid synonym. Suffering is 'dumb'; 
the glandular and visceral processes which colour emotion do not 
lend themselves to verbal articulation. 

The scientist's trouble with language is of a different nature. He 
suffers not from the poverty of his verbal tools but rather from their 
over-precision, and the hidden snares in them. 

Take, for example, the deceptively simple words 'Space' and 'Time'. 
Before the dawn of the scientific revolution, medieval man lived hi a 
closed universe with firm boundaries in space and time — a few million 
miles in diameter, and a few thousand yean of duration. Space taken 
in itself, as an abstract concept, did not exist; it was merely an attribute 
of material bodies — their length, width, and depth; empty space was 
unthinkable, a contradiction in terms; and infinite space even more so. 



THINKING ASIDE 



175 



Time, similarly, was simply the duradon of an event. Nobody in his 
senses would have said that things move throuoh space or in time — how 
can a thing move in or through an attribute of itself? 

The over-precise meaning which these words carried had ensnared 
scientific thought from Aristotle to the Renaissance. Even Galileo still 
believed that a heavenly body, left to itself, would for ever continue 
to move in a circular path, because a straight line would carry it towards 
infinity — which was unthinkable. And when he noticed that two 
polished marble slabs stuck to each other with astonishing strength, he 
ascribed this to nature's horror of empty space which would be created 
at the moment of their separation — and thus failed to discover the 
phenomenon of surface-adherence. 

The first thaw of these frozen word-crystals occurred in 1277, when 
a council of theologians in Paris condemned the Aristotelian doctrine 
that even God could not create empty or infinite space. Thus both 
empty space and infinite space became at least thinkable — which 
previously they had not been. A few unorthodox thinkers did in fact 
speculate about them; yet it took another four centuries until Space 
and Time acquired a new meaning in the Newtonian universe. 

For the next two hundred years after Newton Space meant the 
rigid three-dimensional frame of the universe, which remained at 
rest; so that the motion of a boat sailing up a river was relative measured 
against the water or coast, but absohite motion measured against the 
frame of Space. Time had an equally absolute nature; and that is what 
to most of us the words Space and Time still mean — except in our 
dreams, when the rigid, Newtonian framework breaks down. 

Einstein could never have transformed man's view of the universe, 
had he accepted those two words as ready-made tools. 'When I asked 
myself', he confided to a friend, 'how it happened that I in particular 
discovered the Relativity Theory, it seemed to lie in the following 
circumstance. The normal adult never bothers his head about space- 
time problems. Everything there is to be thought about, in his opinion, 
has already been done in early childhood. I, on the contrary, developed 
so slowly that I only began to wonder about space and time when I 
was already grown up. In consequence I probed deeper into the 
problem than an ordinary child would have done.' 30 Modesty can 
hardly be carried further; nor insight put into simpler terms. 

'For me [the Relativity Theory] came as a tremendous surprise', 
said Minkovsky, who had been one of Einstein's teachers, 'for in his 
student days Einstein had been a lazy dog. He never bothered about 



176 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



mathematics at all From now on "space in itself" and "time in 

itself" must sink into the shade and only a union of the two will 
preserve independence.* 31 

The spelling of the two words had remained the same, but they now 
signified something quite different from what they had signified 
before. 

Words are essential tools for formulating and communicating 
thoughts, and also for putting them into the storage of memory; but 
words can also become snares, decoys, or strait-jackets. A great 
number of the basic verbal concepts of science have turned out at 
various times to be both tools and traps: for instance, 'time', 'space', 
'mass', 'force', weight', ether', 'corpuscle', 'wave', in the physical 
sciences; 'purpose', 'will', 'sensation, 'consciousness', 'conditioning', 
in psychology; 'limit', 'continuity', 'countability', 'divisibility', in 
mathematics. For these were not simple verbal tags, as names attached 
to particular persons or objects are; they were artificial constructs which 
behind an innocent facade hid the traces of the particular kind of logic 
which went into their making. As Sidney Hook has put it: 'When 
Aristode drew up his table of categories which to him represented the 
grammar of existence, he was really projecting the grammar of the 
Greek language on the cosmos.' 32 That grammar has kept us to this 
day ensnared in its paradoxes: it made the grandeur and misery of two 
millennia of European thought. If Western philosophy, to quote 
Popper, consisted in a series of footnotes to Plato, Western science 
took a full two thousand years to liberate itself from the hypnotic 
effect of Aristode, whose encyclopaedic philosophy penetrated 
the very structure of our language. It determined not only what was 
'science' but also what was 'common sense'. Each of the major 
break-throughs in scientific thought had to be achieved not only in the 
teeth of Aristotelian, Platonic, and Christian dogma, but also in the 
teeth of what appeared to be self-evident and commonsensical — the 
implied rules of the code. Each revolution had to make a hole in the 
established fabric of conceptual thought. Kepler destroyed the 'self- 
evident' doctrine of uniform circular motion; Galileo the equally 
commonsense notion that any moving body must have a 'mover' 
which pulls or pushes it along. Newton, to his horror, had to go against 
the obvious experience that action is only possible by contact; Ruther- 
ford had to commit the contradiction in terms of asserting the divisi- 
bility of the atom, which in Greek means 'indivisible'. Einstein des- 
troyed our belief that clocks move at the same rate anywhere in the 



THINKING ASIDE 



177 



universe; quantum physics has made the traditional meaning of words 
like matter, energy, cause and effect, evaporate into thin air. 

'The awkward fact', said L. L. Whyte, 'that reason, as we know it, 
is never aware of its hidden assumptions — has been too much for some 
philosophers, and even many scientists to admit/ 33 One of the philoso- 
phers who saw this clearly was Wittgenstein: 'Propositions cannot 
represent the logical form: this mirrors itself in the propositions. That 
which mirrors itself in language, language cannot represent. That 
which expresses itself in. language, we cannot represent/ 34 

The prejudices and impurities which have become incorporated 
into the verbal concepts of a given 'universe of discourse* cannot be 
undone by any amount of discourse within the frame of reference of 
that universe. The rules of the game, however absurd, cannot be 
altered by playing that game. Among all forms of mentation, verbal 
thinking is the most articulate, the most complex, and the most 
vulnerable to infectious diseases. It is liable to absorb whispered sug- 
gestions, and to incorporate them as hidden persuaders into the code. 
Language can become a screen which stands between the thinker and 
reality. This is the reason why true creativity often starts where 
language ends. 

NOTES 

Top. 157. Zen philosophy, in the form in which it is taught by its contemporary 
propounders (foremost among them Prof. D. T. Suzuki and his Western 
disciples), is a welter of confusions, derived from the failure to discriminate 
between automatized skills and creative originality — between the 'downward* 
and the 'upward' traffic to and from the unconscious. The former results in 
getting the 'knack' of a skill; the latter in the sudden flash of a new insight (the 
*It'). The practitioner of the various applied Zen arts was trained to act 'spontan- 
eously, unthinkingly* — and this led to the added confusion between the pseudo- 
spontaneity displayed by the responses of a well-oiled automaton, and the. 
genuine spontaneity of original inspiration. (Cf. The "It" and the Knack*, 
pp. 260 seq., in my The Lotus and the Robot, i960). 

To p. 166. Less understandable is the case of Spearman, who wrote a book 
on the Creative Mind (1030) with only passing mention of unconscious processes, 
the main reference being a sneer at Freud's preoccupation with 'subconscious 
bestiality*. This was written when Spearman was Professor of Psychology at the 
University of London. 

To p. 172. The exceptions were G. D. BirkhofF, Norbert "Wiener (who said 
that 'he happens to think with or without words'), and G. Polya. 



1 



VIII 

UNDERGROUND GAMES 

The Importance of Dreaming 

To recapitulate: ordered, disciplined thought is a skill governed 
by set rules of the game, some of which are explicitly stated, 
others implied and hidden in the code. The creative act, in so 
far as it depends on unconscious resources, presupposes a relaxing of 
the controls and a regression to modes of ideation which are indifferent 
to the rules of verbal logic, unperturbed by contradiction, untouched 
by the dogmas and taboos of so-called common sense. At the decisive 
stage of discovery the codes of disciplined reasoning are suspended — 
as they are in the dream, the reverie, the manic flight of thought, when 
the stream of ideation is free to drift, by its dWn emotional gravity, 
as it were, in an apparently 'lawless* fashion. 

The laws of disciplined thinking demand that we should stick to a 
given frame of reference and not shift from one universe of discourse 
to another. When I am arguing about Richard III and somebody 
quotes 'my kingdom for a horse' I am not supposed to shift my 
attention to my chances of drawing a winner in the Grand National, 
however tempting it may be. The strain of concentrating on an 
abstract subject derives mainly from the efibrt to inhibit emotionally 
more tempting associations outside of its field. But when concentration 
flags and primitive motivations take over, thought will shift from 
one matrix to another, like a ball bouncing down a mountain stream, 
each time an idea (like 'horse' in the above example) provides a link 
to a more attractive context. 

We might say that while dreaming we constantly bisociate in a passive 
way — by drift as it were; but we are, of course, unaware of it because 
the coherence of the logical matrices is weakened, and the codes 
which govern them are dormant. Hence, while dreaming, we do not 
realize their incompatability; there is no simultaneous juxtaposition of 
matrices, no awareness of conflict and incongruity; that comes only on 

178 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



179 



awakening. To put it in another way: the dream associates by methods 
which are impermissible in the waking state — such as affinities of 
sound detached from meaning, and similarities of form regardless of 
function. It makes use of 'links' which, while awake we 'would not 
dream' of using — except where dream-logic intrudes into humour, 
discovery, and art. 

It is not surprising, then, that we find all the bisociative patterns that 
I have discussed prominently displayed in the dream: the pun: two 
strings of thought tied together by a purely accoustic knot; the optical 
pun: one visual form bisociated with two functional contexts; the 
phenomenon of displacement or shift of attention to a previously un- 
noticed feature; the concretization of abstract and general ideas in a 
particular image; and vice versa, the use of concrete images as symbols 
for nascent, unverbalized concepts; the condensation in the same link- 
idea of several associative contexts; the unearthing of hidden analogies; 
impersonation and double identity — being oneself and something else 
at the same time, where the 'something else' might belong to the 
animal, vegetable, or mineral kingdom. The ensemble of these and 
related operations constitutes the grammar and logic of dream- 
cognition. To go on with the list would be tedious, the more so as the 
categories overlap; but one more trick ought to be added to the 
repertory: the occasional reversal of causal sequences. This, however, is 
putting the phenomenon into over-concrete terms, since 'causality* 
(together with space, time, matter, identity, etc.) appear in the dream 
in a semi-fluid shape like a half-melted snowman; yet even a snowman 
may be standing on his head. Lastly, I must mention the obvious fact 
of the dreamer's extreme gullibility. Hamlet's cloud merely resembles 
a camel, weasel, or whale; to the dreamer the cloud actually becomes 
a camel, a weasel, or whale — without his turning a hair. 

A child, watching a television thriller with flushed face and palpita- 
ting heart, praying that the hero should realize in time the deadly trap 
set for him, is at the same time aware that the hero is a shadow on the 
screen. A day-dreamer — like Thurber's Walter Mitty — is aware of the 
fantasies which he creates for his own benefit; but also aware, though 
less intensely so, of the fact that he is creating them. He lives, like the 
spectator in front of the screen, on two different levels, simultaneously 
or in quick alternations — by mental quantum-jumps, as it were. If he 
settles for a single level then either the illusion ceases to function — or 
it grows into hallucinatory delusion. 

The dream occupies a privileged position among these ambiguous 



i8o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



mental states; privileged, in that it is included in the normal daily cycle 
in spite of— or because of— its pronounced hallucinatory, 'abnormal* 
character. Dreaming is distinguished from other delusionary states by 
being transitory, easily interrupted, and by being confined to the 
'inner landscape', by a more or less complete shuttering of the senses 
(whereas in pathological states the senses may continue to function, 
but perception may be perverted). On the other hand, dreaming is 
distinguished from day-dreaming in that the dreamer is aware of the 
fantasies which he creates, but unaware of the fact that he is creating 
them. He is the spectator passively watching the sequence of images 
on one level, which he actively produces on another; he is the cinema 
operator who works the projection machine, and the audience at the 
same time. But while the spectacle on the screen is visible, the operator 
is not. He operates in complete darkness, and there is a good reason for 
it: the production is frequently childish, obscene, confusing, an affront 
to logic and common sense. 

There is no need to emphasize, in this century of Freud and Jung, 
that the logic of the dream is not the logic of Aristotle; that it derives 
from the magic type of causation found in primitive societies and the 
fantasies of childhood; that it is indifferent to the laws of identity and 
contradiction; that the dream's reasoning is guided by emotion, its 
morality blush-making, its symbolism pre-verbal and archaic. If these 
ancient codes which govern the games of the dreamer were allowed 
to operate in the waking state they would play havoc with civilized 
adult behaviour; they must be kept underground. 

But these underground, in normal states subconscious, levels or 
planes in the hierarchy of mental functions must not be confused with 
the linear scale of awareness (pp. 154-7). The latter forms a con- 
tinuous gradient from focal awareness, through peripheral awareness 
to unawareness of a given event; whereas the levels of the mental 
hierarchy form quasi-parallel (or concentric) layers, which are dis- 
continuous, and are under normal conditions kept separate, as waking 
is from learning. The codes which govern organic activities, auto- 
matized habits, and routine skills, function unawares because they are 
either inborn or have been mastered by practice; the 'underground' 
codes function underground because they have been superseded by 
the codes of rational thinking. In the first case we see the working of 
mental economy ; in the second, of mental evolution. Automatized 
codes serve the maintenance of normal functioning; underground 
codes disrupt routine in a creative or destructive sense. We are con- 



UNDERGROUND GAMES l8l 

cerned with the creative aspect only; but I should mention in passing 
that the underground layers of the mental hierarchy must not be con- 
fused with repressed complexes'. The latter form a special category 
within the much broader realm of subconscious phenomena. Com- 
plexes originate in traumatic experiences; the underground games of 
the mind reflect the facts of mental evolution. 

The levels of mental organization have been compared to the 
archaeological strata of ancient and prehistoric civilizations, buried, 
but not irretrievably, under our contemporary towns. The analogy is 
Freud's 1 but I would like to carry it one step further. Imagine for a 
moment that all important written records and monuments pre-dating 
the Industrial Revolution have been destroyed by some catastrophe 
like the burning down of the library in Alexandria; and that know- 
ledge of the past could be obtained only by archaeological excavations. 
Without digging into the undergound strata, modern society, ig- 
norant of the culture of the Renaissance, of Antiquity, Prehistory, and 
the Age of the Dinosaurs, would be reduced to an unimaginably super- 
ficial, two-dimensional existence: a species without a past and probably 
— for lack of comparative values — without much future. An individual 
deprived of his dreams, of irrational impulses, of any form of ideation 
except articulate verbal thought, would be in much the same position. 
Dreaming, in the literal and metaphorical sense, seems to be an essen- 
tial part of psychic metabolism — as essential as its counterpart, the 
formation and automatization of habits. Without this daily dip into 
the ancient sources of mental life we would probably all become 
desiccated automata. "And without the more spectacular exploratory 
dives of the creative individual, there would be no science and no art. 

To sum up, there is a two-way traffic between conscious and un- 
conscious. One traffic stream continually moves in a downward 
direction: we concentrate on new experiences, arrange them 
into patterns, develop new observational skills, muscular dexterities, 
verbal aptitudes; and when these have been mastered by continued 
practice, the controls are handed over to a kind of automation, and 
the whole assembly is dispatched, along the gradients of awareness, 
out of sight. The upward traffic stream moves in the small fluctuating 
pulses from the unconscious which sustain the dynamic balance of the 
mind — and in the rare, sudden surges of creativity, which may lead 
to a re-stracturing of the whole mental landscape. 

I have illustrated this upward traffic by a number of examples. Irt 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



each case the creative act consisted in a new synthesis of previously un- 
connected matrices of thought; a synthesis arrived at by 'thinking 
aside', a temporary relinquishing of the rational controls in favour of 
the codes which govern the underground games of the mind. We 
have seen that the dream operates with a type of logic which is in- 
admissible in the waking state, and which, for precisely that reason, 
proved useful in critical situations where the matrices of conscious 
thought are blocked. Thus the illogicality and apparent naivete of 
visual associations, or the indifference of the dreaming mind to con- 
vention and common sense, turned out to be of great value in forging 
new combinations out of seemingly incompatible contexts. All the 
bisociative mechanisms of the comic we found in the dream free- 
wheeling as it were, without being harnessed to any obvious rational 
purpose. But when the whole personality, on all its levels, becomes 
saturated with the problem in hand during the period of incubation, 
then the freewheeling machinery too is 'engaged* in its service and 
goes into action — not necessarily in the dream, but mosdy on some 
intermediary, part-conscious level. 

The examples in previous chapters had been meant to illustrate 
various aspects of unconscious discovery. In the sections which follow 
I shall try to show, a little more systematically, how the peculiarities of 
subconscious ideation, reflected in the dream, facilitate the bisociative 
click. 

Concretization and Symbolization 

The sleeper producing a Freudian dream, in which a broomstick 
represents a phallus, has made an optical pun: he has connected a single 
visual form with two different functional contexts. The same technique 
is employed by the caricaturist who equates a nose with a cucumber, 
the discoverer who sees a molecule as a snake, the poet who compares 
a lip to a coral. When Jean Cocteau underwent a drug-withdrawal 
cure, he drew human figures constructed out of the long, thin stalks 
of opium pipes. William Harvey, watching the exposed heart-valve at 
work in a living fish, suddenly visualized it as a pump — but the analogy 
between the gory mess he actually saw and the neat metallic gadget 
existed in his mind's eye only. 

These, however, are rather dramatic examples. As a rule, visual 
imagery does not work in such precise fashion. The visualizer rather 
feels his way around a problem and strokes it with his eye, as it were, 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



I8 3 



trying to fit it into some convincing or elegant shape; he plays around 
with his vague forms like the couturier with his fabrics, draping and 
undraping them on the model. Let me call on Einstein once more. We 
remember that he described the 'physcical entities which seem to serve 
as elements in thoughts' in terms of 'signs and more or less clear images 
of visual, and some of muscular type'. On another occasion, he des- 
cribed how the basic insight into the relativity of Time, to wit, 'the 
knowledge that the events which are simultaneous for one observer 
are not necessarily simultaneous for another', came to him early one 
morning just as he got out of bed. But that sudden moment of truth 
had been preceded 'by ten years of contemplation, of considering a 
paradox which had struck me at the age of sixteen: if I pursue a ray of 
light with the speed c — the speed of light in a vacuum — I must accept 
such a ray of light as a stationary, spatially oscillating electro-magnetic 
field'. 2 In other words, if you travel with the speed of light, you will 
see no light — you will be, roughly speaking, in the position of the 
surf-rider in whose eyes the waves around him form a stationary pattern. 
Yet — 'intuitively it seemed clear to me that, judged by such an ob- 
server, everything should follow the same laws as for a stationary 
observer'. 3 hi other words, the traveller ought to see the world just 
as the person sees it who remained at home on earth. 

It is of course, not enough to visualize oneself as a passenger riding 
on a ray of light; and the ride lasted ten years, even for Einstein. But 
visual thinking enabled him to escape the snares of verbal thought, and 
to brave the apparent logical contradiction that 'at the same time' for 
A may mean 'at different times' for B. This apparent contradiction 
derived from the axiom of absolute time, which had been built into 
the codes of 'rational* — meaning post-Newtonian — thinking about 
the physical world. In the pre-rational codes of the dream time is dis- 
continuous, and the sequence of events can be reversed — as in a film. 
Needless to say, the relativity of psychological time has nothing to do 
with the relativity of time in physics. I merely wished to point out 
that to the visual thinker 'tune* loses the awesome, cast-iron character 
which it automatically assumes in verbal thought. The Theory of 
Relativity was an affront to conceptualized thinking, but not to 
visualized thinking. 

Let me take a more trivial example: a famous brain-teaser: 

One morning, exacdy at sunrise, a Buddhist monk began to 
climb a tall mountain. The narrow path, no more than a foot or 



184 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



two wide, spiralled around the mountain to a glittering temple at 
the summit. 

The monk ascended the path at varying rates of speed, stopping 
many times along the way to rest and to eat the dried fruit he 
carried with him. He reached the temple shortly before sunset. After 
several days of fasting and meditation he began his journey back 
along the same path, starting at sunrise and again walking at variable 
speeds with many pauses along the way. His average speed des- 
cending was, of course, greater than his average climbing speed. 

Prove that there is a spot along the path that the monk will 
occupy on both trips at precisely the same time of day. 4 

I used to amuse myself putting this to various friends — scientists and 
others. Some chose a mathematical approach; others tried to 'reason it 
out* — and came to the conclusion that it would be a most unlikely 
coincidence for the monk to find himself at the same time of day, on 
the same spot on the two different occasions. But others — who evi- 
dently belonged to the category of visualizers — saw the solution in a 
manner for which the following description of a young woman with- 
out any scientific training is typical: 

I tried this and that, until I got fed up with the whole thing, but 
the image of that monk in his saffron robe walking up the hill kept 
persisting in my mind. Then a moment came when, super-imposed 
on this image, I saw another, more transparent one, of the monk 
walking down the hill, and I realized in a flash that the two figures 
must meet at some point some time — regardless at what speed they 
walk and how often each of them stops. Then I reasoned out what I 
already knew: whether the monk descends two days or three days 
later comes to the same; so I was quite justified in letting him 
descend on the same day, in duplicate so to speak. 

Now it is, of course, quite impossible for the monk to duplicate 
himself, and to be walking up the mountain and down the mountain 
at one and the same time. But in the visual image he does; and it is 
precisely this ^difference to logical contradiction, the irrational, 
dream-ike telescoping of the two images into one, which leads to the 
solution. 

^ We could call the double image of the monk, or Einstein's traveller 
riding on a ray of light, a concretization of abstract problems as it 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



sometimes occurs in dreams; and we could equally well call Kekule's 
serpent which seizes its own tail 'to whirl mockingly before his eyes*, 
the symbolization of a nascent, unformulated theory; these categories 
overlap. The following example illustrates both; it refers to an incident 
which has recently come to my knowledge: 

Dr. X, a biologist, dreamed that as he was walking home from his 
laboratory he was joined by the wife and two children of his colleague 
Dr. Y — , one a boy, the other an enchanting little girl. The little 
girl seemed to take an immediate liking to X; she insisted on his 
picking her up, and gave him a kiss, or rather a peck, on the cheek. 
They all walked on with a feeling of friendly elation, but on arriving 
at the house where X lived — it had, unaccountably, become a big 
railway-station hotel — the girl declared peremptorily that she would 
be staying with him; and as he looked at her he discovered that she was 
no longer a child but an adolescent, 'almost fully developed', with a 
provocative glint in her eye. Dr. Y's wife gave him a glance which 
showed irony but no surprise; and the girl said to him mockingly: 
'Don't worry, I am all brains' He felt both tempted and terribly em- 
barrassed; at which he woke up. 

The first thought that flashed through his mind was: 'She is Y's 
brain-child'; and immediately the message of the dream was clear to 
him. Some time earlier on Y had, in conversation, thrown out an 
idea, which had taken root in X's mind, and had eventually set him 
off on a line of research. The peck on his cheek had been 'the kiss of the 
muse'; but by now the idea was 'almost fully developed* — in fact, the 
day before the dream, he had started drafting a paper on the pre- 
liminary results of his research. But he had postponed telling Y about 
it until he had something positive to show; and now he could neither 
face owning up to Y that he had taken up his brain-child, nor could he 
face stealing it (by omitting to give Y due credit in the paper). The 
conversion of X's house into a railway hotel indicated that this state 
of mind could not be a lasting one. 

The dream solved his dilemma by producing a biological analogy 
for the growth of a 'bram-child* from infancy to 'full development*. 
The seminal idea had been Y's; but it was X who had done the work 
and brought it to maturation; every scientist knows that it is quite a 
different matter to throw out a casual suggestion which might or 
might not lead somewhere — and to follow it up by months of hard 
work in the laboratory. The dream made him see the situation 
in its proper perspective;, now all he had to do was to tell Y the 



i86 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



simple facts of the matter, and to give due credit in his paper to Y's 
paternity. 

On one level of his mind X had, of course, known all this; discovery 
in this case, as in many others, consisted in uncovering what had always 
been there. But his knowledge had been buried under the rigid crust 
of a conventional matrix, which made his conscious thoughts turn in a 
vicious circle. 

Punning for Profit 

Charles Lamb once remarked in a letter that he wished 'to draw his 
last breath through a pipe and exhale it in a pun. 

The benefits which the humorist and the poet derive from two 
meanings linked together by one sound are evident^ in the natural 
sciences they are non-existent, for the simple reason that verbal formula- 
tion, the choice of the particular words in which a theory is expressed, 
is to a large extent irrelevant to its content. But in the sciences con- 
cerned with language and meaning, the relations between sense and 
sound play an important part. Homonyms and homophones, sound 
affinities and transformations, are essential pointers in etymology and 
comparative philology, in the study of the structure and development 
of language. I have mentioned the 'divine pun' by which adam, man, 
was created out ofadamah, earth. Eve's Hebrew name is Havvah, life; 
while ahavvah is love; esh, a synonym for man, has the same root as 
isk, fire; and milkhamah, war, is derived from lekhem, bread; so is the 
village of Beth-lehem: the House of Bread. 

Affinities of sound provide the threads which lead from contem- 
porary words and concepts back to the Greek and Sanskrit womb.The 
deciphering of the scripts of ancient languages is often aided by clues 
such as the frequency with which a certain sign occurs, and other 
'links' between sign, symbol, sound, and sense. Thus the links which, 
in 1 821, enabled Champollion to break into the secret of hieroglyphics, 
were the proper names Ptolemy, Cleopatra, and Alexander, which 
appeared on the Rosetta Stone (and on various other documents) 
bearing parallel inscriptions in Greek and in two different Egyptian 
scripts. The three names, inscribed in conspicuous cartouches, pro- 
vided Champollion with altogether fourteen alphabetic signs of as- 
certained value — certainly the greatest service which any Cleopatra 
has rendered to history. 

In the infantile and primitive imagination, the ties between sound 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



187 



and meaning are still very intimate; name and object form an almost 
indivisible unity, shown in the universal practices of word magic, 
incantations, and verbal spells. Related to this is the belief that the 
letters contained in a word form secret connections according to cer- 
tain hermeneutical rules — a belief, shared by Judaism, several other 
Oriental religions, and adopted by the Christian Fathers. It was thought, 
for instance, that to extract their hidden meaning, certain texts in 
Hebrew Scriptures should be arranged in vertical columns and read 
downwards; or that the first and last letter in each word should be used 
to form new words; or that the letters should be reduced to their 
numerical value, and the sums so obtained should then be manipu- 
lated according to the rules of mystic numberlore. Here we have the 
archaic origins of the pun, the crossword puzzle, the acrostic, anagram, 
and cryptogram, which have always exerted such a curious fascina- 
tion in the most varied cultures — from Pythagoras and Lao-Tse to 
Champollion and Freud. The humorist's joke, the linguist's dis- 
covery, the poet's euphony, all derive from that source. 



The Benefits of Impersonation 

*As far as my observations go', wrote C. G. Jung, 'I have not dis- 
covered in the unconscious anything like a personality comparable to 
the conscious ego. But . . . there are at least traces of personalities in the 
manifestations of the unconscious. A simple example is the dream, 
in which a variety of real and imaginery people enact the dream 
thoughts The unconscious personates. 95 

The boundaries of the self are fluid or blurred in the dream. I may 
watch an execution, and the next moment become the person to be 
executed. The actors on the stage are interchangeable; their cards of 
identity are often reshuffled. 

To be oneself and somebody else at the same time is an experience 
shared by the dreamer, the Shaman impersonating the rain-god, the 
patient possessed by demons. The same projective faculty is made use 
of by the actor, to create the illusion in the audience that he is both 
himself and Prince Hamlet; by the priest offering the eucharist in Holy 
Communion; by the healer, who projects himself into the patient's 
place, and at the same time acts as a father-figure. 

The fluid boundaries of the self as represented in the unconscious 
mind, confer on it the gift of empathy— Hw/«e/*/wttg--of entering into 



i88 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



a kind of mental symbiosis with other selves. Empathy is a nicely sober, 
noncommittal term for designating the rather mysterious processes 
which enable one to transcend his boundaries, to step out of his skin 
as it were, and put himself into the place of another. One reads the 
mood of the other from such scant and crude pointers as the lifting or 
lowering of the corners of the Hps, or almost imperceptible changes in 
the muscles which control the eyes; but the interpretation of these 
signs is not a conscious act. It belongs to the repertory of underground 
games. 

Empathy is at the source of our understanding how others think and 
feel; it is the starting point of the art of medical diagnosis and of the 
science of psychology. The medicine man, ancient and modern, has a 
twofold relationship with the patient: he is trying to feel what the 
patient feels, and he is, at the same time, acting a part: the exorcizer of 
evil spirits himself endowed with divine powers; magician, witch, 
saint, sage, hypnotist, faith-healer, confessor, father. The roles have 
changed, but the principle has remained the same: to induce the patient 
to an act of faith, to submission, worship, transference, catharsis. 
Psychotherapy in its modern form expresses in explicit terms the 
principle of ab-reaction, of the mental purge, which has always been 
implied in the ancient cathartic techniques from the Dionysian and 
Orphic mystery-cults to the rites of baptism and the confessional. The 
psycho-analyst induces his patients to relive their conflicts in an illu- 
sionary drama, where he himself impersonates the central figure — half- 
way between comedian and tragedian. The tragedian creates illusion, 
the comedian debunks illusion; the therapist does both, in the dreams 
of patients under Jungian therapy, supposed aspects of their under- 
ground-personality — anima, animus and 'shadow* — keep appearing 
under various disguises, like actors on a stage. Finally, the technique of 
impersonation is used deliberately and explicidy in the form of group- 
therapy known as 'psycho-drama'. 

Some eminent psychiatrists — among them Charcot, Freud, Jung, 
and Theodor Reik— -have expressed, or hinted at their belief that not 
only empathy, but something akin to telepathy operates between 
doctor and patient in the hothouse atmosphere of the analytical ses- 
sion. But there is no need to go that far in order to realize that some of 
the basic insights of medicine and psychology are derived from the 
underground games which permit us to transcend the limits of per- 
sonal identity while we dream — or stare into the footlights of the 
stage. 



Displacement 



We have seen that the sudden shift of attention to a seemingly irrele- 
vant aspect of a phenomenon — which was previously ignored or taken 
for granted — plays a vital part in humour, art, and discovery. In the 
comic story, the abrupt displacement of emphasis ('What am I sup- 
posed to do at 4 a.m. in Grimsby f) has the same effect as the matador's 
nonchalant side-stepping while the bull charges at his muleta. In dis- 
covery, it makes a familiar thing or idea appear under a new angle, in 
an unexpected light. In the art of photography a shift in the direction 
and focus of the lens may turn a trivial object into a thing of wonder. 

In the waking state 'side-stepping', 'shift of emphasis', and related 
expressions signify a change-over from one frame of reference to 
another. But while we dream, the coherence of these frames is so 
much loosened that the change is not experienced as such, and side- 
stepping becomes almost the normal way of the dream's progress. 
It is by virtue of its freedom from restraint that the 'dreamy' way 
of thinking can benefit the creative person — whether he is Archimedes 
relaxing in his bath, or the chimpanzee gazing absent-mindedly at a 
tree. 

In one of his experiments, Carl Duncker — the psychologist who 
fathered the Buddhist monk problem — set his experimental subjects 
the task of making a pendulum. The subject was led to a table on which 
had been placed, among some miscellaneous objects, a cord with a 
pendulum-weight attached to its end, and a nail. All he had to do was 
to drive the nail into the wall and hang the cord with the pendulum- 
weight on the nail. But there was no hammer. Only fifty per cent of 
the experimental subjects (all students) found the solution: to use the 
pendulum-weight as a hammer. 

Next, another series of students, of the same average age and in- 
telligence, were given the same task under slightly altered conditions. 
In the first series the weight on the table was attached to the cord, and 
was expressly described to the students as a pendulum-weight'. In 
the second series, weight and cord were lying separately on the table, 
and the word pendulum-weight' was not used. Result: all students in 
die second group found the solution without difficulty. They took in 
the situation with an unprejudiced mind, saw a nail and a weight, and 
hammered the nail in, then tied the cord to the nail and the weight 
to the cord. But in the minds of the first group the weight was firmly 
'embedded* into its role as a 'pendulum-weight' and nothing else, 

189 



190 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



because it had been verbally described as such and because visually it 
formed a unit with the cord to which it was attached. Thus only half 
of the subjects were able to wrench it out of that context — to perform 
the shift of emphasis which transformed a 'pendulum-weight' into a 
'hammer — as Sultan transformed a 'branch' into a 'stick.' 

I have quoted only one among many experiments on similar lines. 
The fact that fifty per cent of Duncker's presumably bright students 
failed at this simple task is an illustration of the stubborn coherence 
of the perceptual frames and matrices of thought in our minds. The 
visual gestalt of weight-attached-to-cord, plus the verbal suggestion 
of their venerated teacher, made that pendulum-weight stick to its 
matrix like an insect caught in amber. 

To undo wrong connections, faulty integrations, is half the game. To 
acquire a new habit is easy, because one main function of the nervous 
system is to act as a habit-forming machine; to break out of a habit is 
an almost heroic feat of mind or character. The prerequisite of origin- 
ality is the art of forgetting, at the proper moment, what we know. 
Hence, once more, the importance of the Unconscious — as an anaes- 
thetist, who puts reason to sleep, and restores, for a transient moment, 
the innocence of vision. Without the art of forgetting, the mind re- 
mains cluttered up with ready-made answers, and never finds occa- 
sion to ask the proper questions. 

If forgetting can be an art, ignorance can be bliss—in the limited 
sense, of course, of procuring for a certain type of mind freedom from 
certain types of constraint. To Faraday, his ignorance of mathematics 
was an asset; Edison benefited from his shocking ignorance of science. 
As a child, 'his demands for explanations of what seemed obvious to his 
elders created the belief that he was less than normally intelligent. As 
his head was abnormally large, it was thought that he might have a 
brain disease'. 0 At a time when his inventions were transforming the 
pattern of our civilization, 'his ignorance of scientific theory raised 
criticism and opposition, especially among highly trained scientists 
and engineers without inventive talent'. 7 He was said to have carried 
the art of forgetting to such extremes, that on one occasion, when he 
had to queue at New York City Hall to pay his taxes, and an official 
suddenly asked him his name, Edison could not at the moment 
remember it, and lost his place in the queue. 

Let me return from the laboratory of the Sorcerer at Menlo Park 
to that blacksmith's workshop in Samos which, according to tradition, 
was the birthplace of the first quantitative law in physics. One would 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



191 



expect that Pythagoras, as an acute and scientifically minded observer, 
would concentrate on the techniques the men employed in the exercise 
of their craft. Instead of this, his attention shifted to a phenomenon that 
was totally irrelevant and adventitious to that craft— the fact that 
under the strokes of the hammer, iron bars of different size gave out 
different sounds. The ear-splitting crashes and bangs in the workshop, 
which, since the Bronze Age had yielded to the Iron Age, had been 
regarded by ordinary mortals as a mere nuisance, were suddenly lifted 
out of their habitual context: the 'bangs' became 'clangs' of music. In 
the technical language of the communication engineer, Pythagoras had 
turned 'noise' into 'information . 

'The great field for new discoveries', wrote William James, 'is 
always the unclassified residuum. Round about the accredited and 
orderly facts of every science there ever flows a sort of dust-cloud of 
exceptional observations, of occurrences minute and irregular and 
seldom met with, which it always proves more easy to ignore than to 
attend to/ 8 The genius of Sherlock Holmes manifested itself in shifting 
his attention to minute clues which poor Watson found too obvious to 
be relevant, and so easy to ignore. The psychiatrist obtains his clues 
from the casual remark, the seemingly irrelevant drift of associations; 
and he has learned to shift the emphasis from the patient's meaningful 
statements to his meaningless slips of the tongue, from his rational 
experiences to his irrational dreams. The Lord Almighty seems to be 
fond of the trick which Poe's character employed when he let the 
secret document he open on his desk — where it was too obvious to be 
seen. 

Standing on Ones Head 

A drastic form of displacement is the sudden shift of emphasis from one 
aspect of a situation to its opposite, accompanied by a kind of 'reversal 
of logic (p. 65). 

'The dream', wrote Freud, 'neglects in a most conspicuous manner 
the logical category of opposition and contradiction. The concept 
"No" does not seem to exist in the dream. It likes to compress opposites 
into a unity, or to represent them as one. It takes the further liberty of 
representing any given entity by its emotional opposite, so that a 
priori one never knows whether a reversible entity is thought of in the 
dream with a plus or a minus sign/ 9 When a patient says to the doctor: 
'You think that I am now going to say something offensive, but I 



192 THE ACT OB CREATION 

really have no intention of doing so,' then, says Freud, *y ou c* 11 take it 
for granted that he did have that intention. Or, the patient will say: 
"You are asking me who that person in my dream could be. It is not 
my mother." We then correct him: "In other words, it's your mother." 
... At times one can obtain information about unconscious repressed 
processes by a very easy method. One asks: "What do you consider 
to be the most unlikely aspect of that situation? What was it that you 
least intended to do?" If the patient swallows the bait, and tells one 
what he can believe least, then he has almost invariably conceded the 
true answer/ 10 

Freud seemed to believe (following Bain and others) that the reason 
for the unconscious tendency to unify opposites is the relativity of 
all scales by which attributes are measured: a 'hot' summer-day in 
London is 'cold' to the visitor from the Sudan, and Gulliver is a 
'giant' or a 'dwarf* according to the country he visits. He further 
refers to the fact that in some ancient languages pairs of opposites are 
designated by the same word: thus altus means both 'high' and 'deep', 
and sacer both 'holy* and 'accursed'. 

For once, however, Freud did not seem to have probed deep enough; 
he did not mention the rites of the Saturnalia and other ancient festi- 
vals, in which the roles of slaves and masters are reversed; nor the 
constant afErmation of the unity' of opposites in most Oriental religions 
and philosophies. It seems indeed that the tendency to stand things, 
from time to time, on their head, has its deep, unconscious roots, 
which probably reach down into the physiological peculiarities of the 
nervous system.* One of its striking manifestations is the reversi- 
bility of 'figure* and 'background' in visual perception— about which 
below. 

I am not at all sure how far these considerations are relevant to a 
certain pattern of discovery which recurs with curious insistence in the 
biological sciences: we find, over and again, mishaps and minor 
laboratory disasters which turn out to be blessings in disguise, and 
spoilt experiments which perversely yield the solution— by brutally 
shifting die experimenter's attention from a 'plus' to a 'minus' aspect 
of the problem, as it were. One might call this pattern 'discovery by 
misadventure'. A classic case is that of the Abbe* Haiiy (1743-1822), a 
humble teacher at the college at Lemoine, whose leisure hours were 
devoted to collecting specimens of plants and minerals — until a small, 
embarrassing accident suddenly changed the direction of his interests 
and his whole life: 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



193 



One day, when examining some minerals at the house of a 
friend, he was clumsy enough to allow a beautiful cluster of prismatic 
crystals of calcareous spar to fall on the ground. One of the prisms 
broke in such a way as to show at the fracture faces which were no 
less smooth than those elsewhere, but presented the appearance of a 
new crystal altogether different in form from the prism. Haiiy picked 
up this fragment and examined the faces with their inclinations and 
angles. To his great surprise, he discovered that they are the same in 
rhomboidal spar as in Iceland spar. 

He wished to be able to generalize: he broke his own little collec- 
tion into pieces; crystals lent by his friends were broken; everywhere 
he found a structure which depended upon the same laws. u 

The result was Haiiy's Traite de Mineralogie which made him a 
member of the French Academy and a pioneer of the science of 
crystallography. 

Haiiy had a favourite pupil, Delafosse, who later became Pasteur s 
teacher at the ficole Normale in Paris. Under his influence Pasteur 
took up the study of crystallography; it was in this field that he made 
his first important discoveries, which contained the germs of all his 
later achievements. The decisive incident was again a laboratory 
mishap. 

Pasteur was studying his favourite mineral, Para-Tartrate, derived 
from the red Tartar deposit in the vats of fermented wine. One day 
one of his Tartrate solutions became affected by a mould, and spoiled. 
This kind of thing frequendy happens in warm weather; the normal 
reaction of chemists is to pour, with a gende oath, the turbid liquid 
down the drain. Pasteur reversed the logic of the situation: he shifted 
his attention to the accidental and irrelevant mould, and turned 
'accident' into 'experiment' by studying the mould's action on the 
Tartrate. The result was 'the first link in the chain of arguments which 
led him into the study of fermentation, to the recognition that micro- 
organisms play an essential role in the economy of nature, and even- 
tually to his epoch-making discoveries in the field of infectious 
diseases'. 

In his later life Pasteur performed the same kind of mental head-stand 
on at least two more momentous occasions. One I have already men- 
tioned: the discovery of immunization by vaccines, which grew out of 
a spoilt culture of chicken cholera. The other was the 'domestication' of 
micro-organizms, their transformation from enemies into allies of man, 



194 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



which led to industrial micro-biology and, eventually, to the anti- 
biotics: microbes destroying microbes. 'In the inferior organisms,' he 
wrote, 'still more than in the big animal and vegetable species, life 
hinders life.' It sounds simple. But what a long way it was from the 
enunciation of the principle to the discovery of penicillin ! It took more 
than half a century; and it was again due to an almost ludicrous series 
of misadventures. They started in 1922, when Alexander Fleming 
caught a cold. A drip from his nose fell into a dish in his laboratory at 
St. Mary's Hospital; the nasal slime killed off the bacilli in the culture; 
Fleming isolated the active agent in the mucus, which was also present 
in tears, and called it lyso2yme. That was the first step; but lysozyme 
was not powerful enough as a germ-killer, and another seven years 
had to pass until a gust of wind blew through the lab window a spore 
of the mould penicillium notatum, which happened to setde in a culture 
dish of staphylococci. But Fleming had been waiting for that stroke of 
luck for fifteen years; and when it came, he was ready for it. As Lenin 
has said somewhere: 'If you think of Revolution, dream of Revolution, 
sleep with Revolution for thirty years, you are bound to achieve a 
Revolution one day.' 

I shall have to return to Fleming in a different context. The examples 
of 'discovery by misadventure', which I have just given, were taken 
from biology; but the same kind of perverse- or reverse-logic can also 
be found operating in other branches of science and art. 

Li 1 821 Faraday invented the electric motor, and constructed a crude 
model of it. For more than fifty years no attention was paid to his 
invention. In 183 1 he also invented (independently from, and roughly 
simultaneously with Joseph Henry) the electrical dynamo. A motor 
converts electric current into mechanical motion; a dynamo converts 
mechanical motion into electricity. But, curiously, the" reciprocal 
nature of the two machines was not realized until 1873. By that time 
huge dynamo machines, driven by steam power, were in use to gener- 
ate electrical current; but Faraday's earlier invention had been for- 
gotten, and electric motors did not exist. 

In 1873, at an exhibition in Vienna, several dynamo machines of an 
improved type were displayed. In the happy-go-lucky manner of the 
Austrians, one of the technicians mistakenly connected a dynamo, 
driven by a steam-engine, with a second dynamo which was at rest. 
The current fed into the resting dynamo promptly set it into motion — 
and thus the electrical motor came into existence. Electric trains, the 
electrical transmission of power, one of the foundations of modern 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



195 



technology, originates in the accidental reversal of the function of a 
single machine. 

The history of photography and the early history of radiography 
seem to hinge on fluorescent screens and photographic plates which 
showed effects they were not supposed to show, and vice versa. Dagu- 
erre put an exposed plate into an untidy cupboard full of various 
bottles of chemicals — ^including some mercury. The next morning he 
found to his surprise that a perfect image had developed on the plate. 
He repeated the experiment, systematically eliminating one chemical 
after another in the cupboard— until he knew that it was mercury 
vapour which had done the trick. Prior to the discovery of mercury as 
an ideal developer of latent images, Daguerre had written: 'The time 
required to procure a photographic copy of a landscape is from seven 
to eight hours; but single monuments, when strongly lighted by the 
sun, or which are themselves very bright, can be taken in about three 
hours/ 12 After the discovery the time of exposure was shortened to 
between three and thirty minutes. 

In 1895 Wilhelm Konrad Rontgen, Professor of Physics at the 
University of Wtirzburg, noticed by accident that a paper-screen 
covered with barium platinocyanide became fluorescent without any 
apparent cause. He had at the time a cathode-ray tube going — an 
apparatus used to study the conduction of electricity through gases — 
which was enclosed in a box of black cardboard. But in those days 
there was no radiation known hard enough to penetrate black card- 
board, and such a thing was in fact considered to be impossible. 
Rontgen immediately accepted the impossible as true: the fluorescent 
glow which he saw on the screen must be caused by rays of an unknown 
kind, emitted by the tube, and capable of traversing the bhck card- 
board. Within a few weeks he had demonstrated that the rays were 
equally capable of traversing human flesh and showing the outline of 
the bones as shadows cast upon the luminous screen. He called them 
X-rays. 

Some few weeks later, Henri Becquerel saw a demonstration of 
Rontgen s X-rays at a meeting of the French Academy of Sciences. 
Becquerel's father and grandfather had also been professors of physics 
and members of the Academy; they had taken a special interest in the 
fluorescent glow which certain substances — among .them uranium 
compounds — emit, when exposed to light. He therefore immediately 
formed the— wrong — theory that X-rays were a normal accompani- 
ment of the fluorescent glow, and he set out to prove this theory by 



196 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



experiment. He wrapped a photographic plate into heavy black paper 
to screen it from ordinary light. On top of the paper-wrapping he kid 
some crystals of the uranium compound; between the crystals and the 
wrapping he placed a bit of metal with holes in it. Then he placed this 
whole arrangement outside his window so that the sun's rays should set 
the uranium aglow with fluorescence, and thereby set the X-rays going 
across the wrapper. This worked admirably: when he developed his 
plates the rays had penetrated the wrapping and produced a photograph 
of the holes in the metal. It was a wonderful example of an experiment 
confinning a prediction based on a false hypothesis. 

No sooner had he communicated his results to the Academy, when 
the sky clouded over, and Becquerel put his plates and the uranium 
into a dark drawer. Here the crystals were shut off from the sunlight; 
hence there was no fluorescent glow; hence there could be no X-rays to 
blacken the photographic plate. But when he took them out of the 
drawer, the plates were blackened nevertheless. Once more the im- 
possible had happened; and once more a reversal of logic brought the 
solution. The fluorescent glow had been caused by the X-rays — and not 
the other way round. Becquerel now tried non-fluorescent uranium 
compounds and found that they, too, produced rays. He tried other 
fluorescent materials which did not contain uranium, and found 
that they did not produce the rays. That clinched the matter: the source 
of the rays, 'the radio-active agent, was the uranium itself. It was from 
here that the Curies took over. 

Perhaps the prettiest example of reasoning in reverse gear is the 
invention of the phonograph. 

As a young man Edison worked as a telegraphist. His main job was 
the taking of messages from the Morse-ticker by ear; if the line was bad, 
the ticking became blurred, and he had to rely on guessing. This 
annoyed him all the more as, owing to an earlier accident, Edison was 
partially deaf. So the young telegraphist invented a simple Morse- 
signal-recording apparatus. It consisted mainly of a paper disc, which 
was made to rotate like the gramophone disc of the future; on the disc 
the incoming dots and dashes were recorded as indentations. But from 
the telegraph company's point of view transcribing from the record 
instead of doing it directly by ear from the ticker was a sheer waste of 
time; Edison, then seventeen, lost his job. 

Eleven years later, in the first laboratory of his own, he was working 
on about fifty inventions simultaneously — among them the typewriter 
and an improved telegraph-recorder, on which the mcoming dots and 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



197 



dashes were embossed by a needle. When the message was to be sent on 
to another station, the paper disc was placed on a transmitting machine 
with a contact lever which moved up and down according to the 
indentations on the disc. It was a gadget with the sole purpose of 
recording and transmitting electrical impulses, and had nothing what- 
soever to do with the production of sounds. Yet it did produce purely- 
accidental sounds — because the lever, while tracing the embossed dots 
and dashes, was apt to rattle; and when the disc was rotated very quickly 
this ratde became a hum, then something like a musical sound. A 
sudden reversal of logic and the phonograph was born. 

The rest was a matter of elaboration. Instead of a paper disc, Edison 
proposed to use a cylinder covered with soft tin-foil; instead of attach- 
ing the needle to a Morse-telegraph, he attached it to a membrane set 
into vibration by the waves of sound. He made a sketch of the machine, 
and gave it to one of his workmen, a certain John Kruesi. It cost 
altogether eighteen dollars to build it, but Kruesi had no idea what the 
contraption was for. When it was finished Edison shouted at it: 'Mary 
had a Httle lamb.' Then he turned the handle of the recording cylinder: 

'The rnachine reproduced perfectly. Everybody was astonished * 

And that was that. To quote once more the jargon of communication 
engineering: the background noise' of the vibrating lever had been 
turned into 'information. 

We have met the same kind of logical mirror-writing in humour — a 
sadist is a person who is kind to a masochist , , 'operation successful, 
patient dead*. All jokes based on a tmning-the-tables technique show 
the same pattern (for instance, the Prince and the Retainer story on 
p. 84). 

In the classical tragedy, on the other hand, it is the gods, or the stars, 
who turn the tables on the mortal hero, or lure him into appointments 
in Samara. They particularly like to use seemingly harmless coinci- 
dences — the blind gaps in the meaningful order of events — as levers of 
destiny. In later forms of literature, it is characters which are made to 
stand on their heads, or are turned inside out like a glove. Prince 
Mishkin, the 'Idiot', is revealed as a sage in reverse; saints are sinners, 
sinners are saints, heroes are cowards, adults are children, and every 
JekyH has something to Hyde. 

In visual perception we find a parallel phenomenon in the reversible 
figure-background relation. If one stares at the mosaic on the bathroom 
floor, unconscious and often uncontrollable shifts in perception make 
the pattern of black tiles stand out at one moment, and the pattern of 



I98 THE ACT OF CREATION 

white tiles at the next. A more dramatic illustration is the following, 
found in many psychological textbooks: 



Figure 9 

Urn or profiles — whichever is master for a while, will become slave 
in turn, 'figure' will change into 'ground', 'noise' into 'information', in 
a kind of visual saturnalia. The two perceptual matrices are reciprocal, 
and their alternation seems to be determined by unconscious physio- 
logical processes. 

Some of the great revolutions in the history of painting entailed 
almost equally brutal reversals of vision. Up to the late Venetians, the 
landscape on the canvas was primarily perceived as a conventional 
background against which human figures were displayed; roughly 
from Giorgione onward it became possible to paint landscapes in which 
the human figure played an accidental part. At different stages one fw.6s 
similar reversals in the logic of the eye: from ornate drapery to personal 
expression, from contours to surfaces, from naturalism to other isms of 
perception. At each of these upheavals the cat without a grin was 
superseded by the grin without a cat. 

In the realm of music the relativity and reversibility of 'figure' and 
'background* (accompaniment, counterpoint, fugue) is self-evident. It 
is less obvious in modern theoretical physics, although it is implied in 
one of its basic postulates: according to Niels Bohr's Principle of Com- 
plementarity the dtimate constituents of the universe—electrons, 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



199 



protons, photons, etc. — behave on some occasions as if they were 
particles, that is, hard lumps of matter, on other occasions as if they 
were ripples of energy without definite location. Although the two 
descriptions are mutually exclusive in terms of traditional physics and 
philosophy, the theory works remarkably well. As a matter of fact, 
most physicists are not much bothered by the inherent contradiction, 
and are quite content to believe that the wavicles', the actual stuff the 
world is made of, are at one moment like the solid urn, and the next 
like the empty space between the two profiles. 

That the most brilliant scientists of this century should be capable of 
accepting this paradox is a rather striking indication of the susceptibility 
of the human mind for reversals of logic, and the unification of 
opposites. The complementarity of energy and matter in quantum- 
physics is not so far removed as it would seem from the dualism of 
Yang and Yin, the feminine and masculine principles in Taoist philo- 
sophy. I do not mean that Lao-Tse, in the sixth century B.C., foresaw 
the behaviour of alpha-particles in a Wilson chamber; I mean that it is 
a timeless characteristic of the unconscious mind to work in that way. 

Analogy and Intuition 

The great biologist Elie MechnikofF felt rather lonely one afternoon 
in 1890 'when the whole family had gone to the circus to see some 
extraordinary performing apes, and I remained alone with my micro- 
scope'. 13 The microscope was in a laboratory of the £cole Normale 
which Pasteur had given him; MechnikofF was observing the life of the 
mobile cells in the transparent larvae of starfish, and idly threw a few 
rose-thorns among them. The thorns were prompdy surrounded by 
the larvae and dissolved inside their transparent bodies — they had been 
gobbled up and digested. This reminded him of what happens when a 
human finger is infected by a splinter: it will be surrounded by pus 
which, like the starfish larvae, will attack and try to digest the intruder. 
By this analogy MechnikofF discovered the organisms* main defence 
mechanism against invading microbes: the 'phagocytes', cell-eaters, a 
population of mobile cells among the white blood corpuscles. 

The starting point of Kepler's discoveries was a supposed analogy 
between the role of the Father in the Trinity and the role of the Sun in 
the Universe. Lord Kelvin hit on the idea of the mirror galvanometer 
when he noticed a reflection of light on his monocle. Sultan saw that a 



200 



THE ACT OF CRBATION 



branch was like a stick; Newton saw that the moon behaved like an 
apple. Pasteur saw the analogy between a spoilt culture and a cow-pox 
vaccine; Fleming saw the analogy between the action of a mould and 
the action of a drip from his nose. Freud, on his own account, conceived 
the idea of the sublimation of instincts by looking at a funny cartoon in 
the Fliegende Blatter— the one-time German equivalent of Punch. In the 
first picture a little girl was herding a flock of goslings with a stick. In 
the second she had grown into a governess herding a flock of young 
ladies with a parasol. 14 

Some writers identify the creative act in its entirety with the unearth- 
ing of hidden analogies. 'The discoveries of science, the works of art 
are explorations — more, are explosions, of a hidden likeness', Bronow- 
ski wrote. 15 But where does the hidden likeness hide, and how is it 
found? Sultan's branch could literally be seen as a stick — though even in 
this case, a change of the perceptual frame was required to discover the 
likeness. But in most truly original acts of discovery the 'seeing' is in 
fact imagining; it is done in the mind's, and mostly the unconscious 
mind's eye. The analogy between the life of one kind of microbe inside 
a cow and another kind of microbe in a forgotten culture tube was not 
'hidden' anywhere; it was 'created* by the imagination; and once an 
analogy has been created, it is of course there for all to see— just as a 
poetic metaphor, once created, soon fades into a cliche. 

Analogy, in logic, means a process of 'reasoning from parallel causes'; 
in common parlance it means that two situations or events are similar 
in some respects, but not in all respects. The rub is in the words 'parallel' 
and 'similar'; the latter, in particular, has bedevilled psychology ever 
since the term 'association by similarity* was invented (by Bain, I 
believe) as an explanation of how the mind works. A Chinaman who 
collects stamps is 'similar* to a Negro in that both are males; he is 
similar to a Chinese girl in that both are Chinese; and he is similar to 
other stamp-coUeaors of any nationality. Mathematics began, wrote 
Bertrand Russell, when it was discovered that a brace of pheasants and 
a couple of days have something in common: the number two. 
'Similarity* is not a thing offered on a plate (or hidden in a cupboard); 
it is a relation established in the mind by a process of selective emphasis 
on those features which overlap in a certain respect— along one dimen- 
sional gradient— and ignoring other features. Even such a seemingly 
simple process as recognizing the similarity between two letters V 
written by different hands, involves processes of abstraction and 
generalization in the nervous system which are largely unexplained. 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



201 



Thus the real achievement in discoveries of the type mentioned, in 
this section is 'seeing an analogy where no one saw one before'. The 
scientist who sets out to solve a problem looks at it from various angles, 
through glasses of different colours, as it were — in the jargon of the 
present theory, he experiments with various matrices, hoping that one 
will fit If it is a routine problem of a familiar type, he will soon discover 
some aspect of it which is similar in some respect to other problems 
encountered in the past, and thus allows him to come to grips with it. 
Some of the mental operations involved in such routine cases we have 
already encountered in discussing the solving of witty riddles (pp. 
84-6): extrapolation, interpolation, transposition. These are 'rules of 
the game' which enter as sub-codes into any complex mental skill. To 
put it in a different way: solving a problem means bridging a gap; and 
for routine problems there usually exist matrices— various types of 
prefabricated bridges — which will do the job; though it may require a 
certain amount of sweat to adjust them to the terrain. 

But in original discoveries, no single pre-fabricated matrix is adequate 
to bridge the gap. There may be some similarities with past situations, 
but these may be more misleading than helpful, and lure the victim into 
fruitless experimentation based on traditional rules of the game. Here 
the only salvation lies in hitting on an auxiliary matrix in a previously 
unrelated field — the larvae of starfish or the Holy Ghost. One may call 
the process which follows after the hit 'reasoning from a parallel case' — 
but the real achievement was to 'appoint', as it were, the larva as a 
parallel case to the pus, and the action of the Holy Ghost as 'similar* to 
the action of gravity. It is an achievement much closer to the birth of a 
poetic simile than to a logical production. After all, the Walrus too was 
arguing by analogy when he talked 'Of shoes — and ships — and sealing 
wax/Of cabbages — and kings/ 

The essence of discovery is that unlikely marriage of cabbages and 
kings — of previously unrelated frames of reference or universes of dis- 
course — whose union will solve the previously unsoluble problem. The 
search for the improbable partner involves long and arduous striving — 
but the ultimate matchmaker is the unconscious. I have discussed 
several tricks which qualify it for that role: the greater fluency and 
freedom of unconscious ideation; its 'intellectual Hbertinage' — as one 
might call the dream's indifference towards logical niceties and mental 
prejudices consecrated by tradition; its non-verbal, 'visionary' powers. 
To these must be added, in our present context, the dream's tendency 
towards creating unusual analogies. These may be verbal puns, or 



202 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



'optic puns' or visual symbols; but there is another type of vague and 
cloudy analogy generated in the dream and half-dream, which dis- 
integrates on awakening and cannot be put into words — except by 
muttering 'something rerninded me of something, but I don't know 
what reminded me of what, and why'. Some dreams have a way of 
dissolving in the wakening mind like solid crystals melting in a liquid*, 
and if we reverse the process we get at least a speculative pointer to the 
manner in which those 'somethings' vaguely reminding me of other 
'somethings' condense into a nascent analogy. This may be a hazy, 
tentative affair — the dance of Poincare's unhooked atoms; and its shape 
may be changing from camel to weasel, as Hamlet's cloud. The un- 
conscious regions of fertile minds must be pullulating with such nascent 
analogies, hidden likenesses, and the cloudy forms of things unknown. 
But most clouds form and dissolve again; only a few intuitions reach 
the stage of 'seeding the cloud' which results in the formation of verbal 
drops; and cloud-bursts are a rarity. 

Two final examples may serve to illustrate the actual process of 
discovering hidden analogies. The first is related to clouds in a literal 
sense — Franklin's invention of the Hghtning conductor. 

Benjamin Franklin became interested in electricity in 1746 when he 
was forty, and began playing about with Leyden jars — a kind of 
electrified bottle which gave one fearful shocks. Within the next three 
years he rediscovered by himself virtually everything that was known 
about electricity to that date, and added several fundamental discoveries 
of his own. 

In 1749 he noted in his diary that he thought Hghtning and thunder 
to be electrical phenomena.* He also found that when brought near to' 
an electrified body, a pointed object, like a finger, will draw a much 
stronger spark than a blunt one. 'To know this power of points', he 
musingly wrote, 'may possibly be of some use to mankind, though we 
should never be able to explain it.' He then drew an analogy between a 
cloud and an electrified body, and concluded that Hghtning was an 
electrical discharge phenomenon. But if that was the case, mankind 
could protect itself against this cosmic scourge: 

I say, if these things are so, may not the knowledge of this power of 
points be of use to mankind, in preserving houses, churches, ships & 
cont. from the stroke of Hghtning, by directing us to fix on the 
highest parts of those edifices, upright rods of iron made sharp as a 
needle, and gilt to prevent rusting, and from the foot of those rods a 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



203 



-wire down one of the shrouds of a ship, and down her side till it 
reaches the water? Would not these pointed rods probably draw 
the electrical fire silently out of a cloud before it came nigh enough to 
strike, and thereby secure us from that most sudden and terrible 
mischief? 16 

However, before he could convince mankind to put 'Franklin rods* 
on their houses he had to prove his fantastically sounding notion that 
thunderclouds were in fact giant Leyden jars floating in the air. He 
waited for some time hopefully for the erection of a tall spire at 
Philadelphia, intending to fix a pointed rod on top of it, and so to 
bring down the electricity from a passing thundercloud. But the 
difficulties of the project proved insurmountable; it was during this 
period of impatient waiting and restless searching for a simpler method 
to prove his theory that he hit on the fantastic yet at the same time 
astonishingly simple idea of the kite. 

How did it happen? Franklin was an expert swimmer. On his first 
sojourn in London, at the age of nineteen, he swam from Chelsea to 
BlackfHars, a distance of three miles, performing on the way many 
feats of activity both upon and under the water — and was advised by 
some English gendemen, who watched him, to open a swiniming 
school. He did not do that, but he devised a new method of learning to 
swim: 'Choosing a place where the water deepens gradually, walk 
coolly into it till it is up to your breast, then turn around, your face to 
the shore, and throw an egg into the water between you and the 
shore.' The learner then must 'boldly retrieve the egg* — and in the act 
of retrieving acquires the art of swimming. 

Even earlier on he had devised another aquatic sport: as a boy he used 
to drift for hours on a lake, floating on his back, and towed by the 
string of a kite. He suggested that this method might be utilized by 
swimmers to cross the Channel from Dover to Calais — with the 
judicious addendum: 'The packet-boat, however, is still preferable.' 

It is easy to imagine how, in a moment of weariness and 'thinking 
aside' from that wretched spire in Philadelphia, a pleasant childhood 
memory rose like a bubble to the surface of his consciousness: drifting 
on the lake attached to the kite in the sky. Eureka! With the enthusi- 
astic assistance of his young son, Franklin fabricated a kite out of a cross 
of cedar wood and a silk handkerchief. All he needed now were a few 
good thunderclouds — which conveniently appeared in June 1752. 
Father and son sent up the kite and, with due precaution, drained the 



204 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



clouds' electric charge into a Leyden jar; 'by the electric fire thus 
obtained spirits were inflamed and other experiments performed'. 

Such was the excitement caused all over the world that one of 
Franklin's imitators, a certain Monsieur Riehmann, was killed in St. 
Petersburg by the lightning discharge he drew from a cloud. He was 
worshipped as a hero and found many would-be imitators; among 
them the German inventor Herr Boze. Even Joseph Priestley, one of 
the great British scientists of the century, rhapsodized about 'the 
sentiments of the magnanimous Mr. Boze, who with a truly philo- 
sophic heroism, worthy of the renowned Empedocles, said he wished he 
might die by the electric shock, that the account of his death might 
furnish an article for the memoirs of the French Academy of Sciences. 
But it is not given to every electrician to die the death of the justly 
envied Riehmann.' 17 

There are two successive Eureka processes involved in this story. In 
the first, the bisociative link was what Franklin called 'the power of 
points'; it gave rise to the analogy: pointed ringer discharges Leyden 
jar, pointed rod discharges cloud. It may have been attained by ideation 
on a relatively conscious level, probably with the aid of visual imagina- 
tion. The second stroke of genius was the use of the kite to reach the 
thunderbolt. It illustrates the argument I have put forward earlier in this 
chapter: one can hardly say that a hidden analogy was pre-existent in the 
universe between a kite used as a sail by a boy floating on a lake, and a 
lightrtirtg conductor. What actually happened was that Franklin was 
desperately searching for a means to make contact with a thundercloud, 
thinking in habitual terms of tall spires, long iron rods, and perhaps the 
Tower of Babel. But all these approaches proved impracticable, and the 
matrix was blocked — until in a moment of lassitude and day-dreaming 
the previously unrelated memory-train of swimming, egg-retrieving, 
and kite-sailing was brought to bear on it. 

The last example that I shall quote in this section is a particularly 
impressive illustration of the unconscious in the role of rnatchmaker. I 
am referring to the discovery, in 1920, of the chemical transmission of 
nerve-impulses by Otto Loewi. Since the matter is somewhat technical, 
I shall give a simplified account of it. 

Before Loewi's discovery it was generally believed that nervous 
control of bodily functions was exercised by a direct transmission of 
electrical impulses from nerve-terminal to muscle or gland. But this 
theory failed to account for the fact that the same type of electric 
impulse travelling down a nerve had an excitatory eflect on some 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



205 



organs, an inhibitory effect on others. Now certain drugs were known 
to have precisely the same effect. In a discussion with a friend in 1903, 
it occurred to Loewi that the chemical agents which were contained in 
these drugs may also be present at the nerve-terminals; the electric 
impulse would initiate chemical action, which in its turn would act on 
the muscle or gland. But Loewi could not think of an experimental 
method to test the idea — and forgot it for the next seventeen years. 

Fifteen years later, for quite different purposes, he designed an 
experiment. He made preparations of two frogs' hearts which were kept 
beating in salt solutions to see whether their activities gave out any 
chemical substance. In the sequel he forgot all about the experiment. 

Another two years passed until the critical event: 

The night before Easter Sunday of that year [1920] I awoke, 
turned on the light, and jotted down a few notes on a tiny slip of thin 
paper. Then I fell asleep again. It occurred to me at six o'clock in the 
morning that during the night I had written down something most 
important, but I was unable to decipher the scrawl. The next night, 
at three o'clock, the idea returned. It was the design of an experiment 
to determine whether or not the hypothesis of chemical trans- 
mission that I had uttered seventeen years ago was correct. I got up 
immediately, went to the laboratory, and performed a simple 
experiment on a frog heart according to the nocturnal design. . . . 

No lesser person that Walter B. Cannon, the discoverer of adrenalin, 
has described this noctural design as 'one of the neatest, simplest, and 
most definite experiments in the history of biology'. Loewi again 
isolated two frog hearts, the first with its nerves, the second without. 
He stimulated the vagus nerve of the first heart for a few minutes. The 
vagus has an inhibitory effect on the heart, and its beats slowed down. 
Loewi now removed the salt solution from the first heart and applied 
it to the second. It slowed down just as if its own (no longer existent) 

vagus had been stimulated He repeated the experiment, this time 

stimulating the accelerator nerve of the first heart. When the liquid was 
transferred to the second heart it accelerated He concludes: 

These results unequivocally proved that the nerves do not 
influence the heart directly but liberate from their terminals specific 
chemical substances which, in their turn, cause the well-known 
modifications of the function of the heart characteristic of the 
stimulation of its nerves. 



206 



THE ACT Of CREATION 



The story of this discovery shows that an idea may sleep for 
decades in the unconscious mind and then suddenly return. Further, 
it indicates that we should sometimes trust a sudden intuition without 
too much scepticism. If carefully considered in the daytime, I would 
undoubtedly have rejected the kind of experiment I performed. It 
would have seemed likely that any transmitting agent released by a 
nervous impulse would be in an amount just sufficient to influence 
the effector organ. It would seem improbable that an excess that could 
be detected would escape into the fluid which filled the heart. It 
was good fortune that at that moment of the hunch I did not think 
but acted immediately. 

For many years this nocturnal emergence of the design of the 
crucial experiment to check the validity of a hypothesis uttered 
seventeen years earlier was a complete mystery. 18 

In 1955— twenty-five years after the discovery, which earned him 
the Nobel Prize— Loewi had to compile a bibliography: 

I glanced over all the papers published from my laboratory. I 
came across two studies made about two years before the arrival of 
the nocturnal design in which, also in search of a substance given off 
from the heart, I had applied the technique used in 1920. This 
experience, in my opinion, was an essential preparation for the idea 
of the finished design. In fact, the nocturnal concept represented a 
sudden association of the hypothesis of 1903 with the method tested 
not long before in other experiments. Most so-called 'intuitive' 
discoveries are such associations suddenly made in the unconscious 
mind. 1 * 

Let me briefly recapitulate the three stages of this drama. The first is 
the sudden emergence, during a conversation in 1903, of the hunch that 
his problem could be solved by switching from a 'spark theory' to a 
'soup theory* (in neurological jargon, 'spark' refers to electrical, 'soup' 
to chemical transmission of nerve impulses). But a hunch of this kind 
as often as not turns out to be a fallacious over-simplification; so the 
idea went into the incubator for the next seventeen years, till 1920. 

Act Two. In 1918, fifteen years after the hunch, Loewi performs 
certain experiments for which purpose he has to design a technique 
for the detection of fluids secreted by the frog's heart. He then forgets 
all about it. 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



207 



On the night before Easter Sunday the two previously unrelated 
memories meet; but their meeting place is so deep underground that 
the next morning he can remember nothing, and cannot even decipher 
his own scribbled note. He has to wait until the next night for another 
underground excursion — which takes place at 3 a.m., followed by the 
rush to the laboratory. 

After the event one wonders, of course, why one idea had to wait for 
seventeen years, the second for two years, and then choose such a secret 
place for their final rendezvous that the identity of the second was only 
revealed another twenty-five years later. The first was a theory of the 
transmission of nerve impulses to organs by a fluid; the second was a 
technique for tracing fluids in an organ; what could be more logical 
than that the twain should meet? Yet they did not meet through all 
those years because mortal minds, even those of genius, are not 
governed by logic but by habit, and the two ideas were embedded 
each in its own habitual context. Wallace, too, had been thinking of 
evolution for two years, and had read Malthus many years before the 
two fused— during an attack of tropical fever. It seems that encounters 
of this kind can occur only when the normal rules of the game are 
suspended and the unconscious match-maker enters into action. Loewi's 
inability to read his own note, and other cases of 'snowblindness* 
which I shall mention, indicate the stubborn resistance of habit against 
such breaches of the rules and illicit liaisons. 

"We are somewhat more than ourselves in sleep and the Slumber of 
the Body seems to be but the Waking of the Soul', Sir Thomas Browne 
wrote three centuries ago. Yet it is difficult and frustrating to write 
consciously on the unconscious, rationally on the irrational. It is rather 
like praising the beauties and expounding the grammar of the Sanskrit 
language — but a Sanskrit which you speak only in your sleep and the 
command of which you lose when awake. Only fragments of it emerge 
to the surface — disjointed memories and the testimonies of creative 
minds. When these fragments are pieced together, as best we can, they 
do not form a coherent pattern — but they do provide evidence that 
such a pattern exists. 

Sumtnary 

The interlocking of two previously unrelated skills or matrices of 
thought was again seen to constitute the basic pattern of discovery in 
the illustrative cases of Gutenberg, Kepler, and Darwin-Wallace 



208 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



(Chapter VI). Gutenberg combined the techniques of the wine-press 
and the seal; Kepler married physics to astronomy; Darwin connected 
biological evolution with the struggle for survival. 

On the question how the new synthesis comes into being, the evi- 
dence indicates that verbal thinking, and conscious thinking in general, 
plays only a subordinate part in the decisive phase of the creative act. 
Hadamard's inquiry among leading mathematicians in America re- 
vealed that 'practically all of them . . . avoid not only the use of mental 
words but also ... the mental use of algebraic or any other signs'. On 
the testimony of those original thinkers who have taken the trouble to 
record their methods of work, this also seems to be the rule in other 
branches of science. Their virtually unanimous emphasis on spontane- 
ous intuitions, unconscious guidance, and sudden leaps of imagination 
which they are at a loss to explain, suggests that the role of stricdy 
rational thought-processes in scientific discovery has been vasdy over- 
estimated since the Age of Enlightenment; and that, contrary to the 
Cartesian bias in our beliefs, 'full consciousness', in the words of 
Einstein, 'is a limit case*. 

'Full consciousness' must indeed be regarded as the upper limit of a 
continuous gradient from focal awareness through peripheral aware- 
ness to total unawareness of an event. Awareness is a matter of degrees; 
and only a fraction of our multi-levelled activities at any moment 
enters the beam of focal consciousness. But this realisation in itself 
provides no answer to the question how unconscious guidance works. 

We have approached that question in several cautious steps. First, I 
have tried to show that unconscious automatisms must not be con- 
fused, as they often ate, with unconscious intuitions. To be able to 
recite the lines of Kubla Khan 'in one's sleep* is not the same thing as 
conceiving them in a dream; it is, in fact, the result of the opposite 
process. The formation and gradual automatization of habits of all 
kinds, of muscular, perceptual, tmnking skills, follows the principle of 
economy. Once a new skill has been mastered, the controls begin to 
function automatically and can be dispatched underground, out of 
sight; and under stable conditions strategy too will tend to become 
stereotyped. I called this the 'downward' stream of mental traffic. 

The next step led us to inquire how in ordinary, routine thinking we 
explore the 'shallows' of our minds— operating on the twilight peri- 
pheries of awareness, as it were. Galtons oft-quoted metaphor of the 
ante-chamber, from which the 'most closely allied' idea is summoned 
to the presence-chamber of the mind in a 'mechanically logical way', 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



209 



proved to be inadequate, because the order of precedence was seen to 
depend firstly, on the specific rules of the game in which the mind is 
engaged at the time, and secondly, on strategic considerations depen- 
dent on the he of the land. Purposive thinking, then, may be compared 
to the scanning of a landscape with the narrow beam of focal vision — 
whether it is a panorama, a chessboard, or an 'inner landscape*. Those 
features which are relevant to the purpose of the operation will stand 
out as 'members' of the matrix, while the rest sinks into the background. 
Thus the first act in skilled routine-thinking and problem-solving is the 
'turdng-in of the code appropriate to the task, guided by some obvious 
similarity with situations encountered in the past. This leads to the 
emergence of a matrix which provides a preliminary selection of 
possible moves; the actual moves depend on strategy, guided by feed- 
back, and distorted by emotional interferences. 

However, the problems which lead to original discoveries are 
precisely those which cannot be solved by any familiar rule of the game, 
because the matrices applied in the past to problems of similar nature 
have been rendered inadequte by new features or complexities in the 
situation, by new observational data, or a new type of question. The 
search for a clue, for Poincare's 'good combination which will 
unlock the blocked problem, proceeds on several planes, involving 
unconscious processes at various levels of depth. 

In a general way this simultaneous activity on various levels, during 
the period of incubatioii, in itself creates a state of receptivity, a readi- 
ness of the 'prepared mind' to pounce on favourable chance-constella- 
tions, and to profit from any casual hint (Gutenberg and the wine- 
press, Archimedes, Pasteur, Darwin, Fleming). In discoveries of this 
type, where both rational thinking and the trigger-action of chance 
play a noticeable part, the function of the unconscious seems to be 
mainly to keep the problem constantly on the agenda, even while 
conscious attention is occupied elsewhere. In this context the word 
'unconscious* refers primarily to processes (such as perceptions and 
memories) which occur fairly low down on the gradient of awareness. 

But in other types of discovery the unconscious plays a more 
specific, guiding role by bringing forms of ideation into play which 
otherwise manifest themselves only in dreaming and related states. 
Their codes function more or less permanently 'underground', because 
they govern the type of thinking prevalent in childhood and in primi- 
tive societies, which has been superseded in the norm al adult by techni- 
ques of thought which are more rational and realistic— or are considered 



210 



THE. ACT OF CREATION 



as such. These ancient, quasi-archaeological layers in the mental hier- 
archy form a world apart, as it were, glimpses of which we get in the 
dream; their existence is a kind of historic record, which testifies to the 
facts of mental evolution; and they must not he confused with auto- 
matized skills which, once mastered, function unawares, for reasons of 
mental economy. (It would perhaps be preferable to call these 'archeo- 
logicaT strata of the mind the swfc-conscious', to distinguish them from 
processes of which we are merely wfl-consrious because they happen 
to rank low on the linear scale of awareness. But the Freudian connota- 
tions of the word subconscious would probably lead to confusion of a 
different kind.) 

The period of incubation represents a reculerpour mieux sauter. Just as 
in the dream the codes of logical reasoning are suspended, so 'thinking 
aside' is a temporary liberation from the tyranny of over-precise verbal 
concepts, of the axioms and prejudices engrained in the very texture of 
specialized ways of thought. It allows the rnind to discard the strait- 
jacket of habit, to shrug off apparent contradictions, to un-learn and 
forget—and to acquire, in exchange, a greater fluidity, versatility, and 
gullibility. This rebellion against constraints which are necessary to 
maintain the order and discipline of conventional thought, but an 
impediment to the creative leap, is symptomatic both of the genius and 
the crank; what distinguishes them is the intuitive guidance which only 
the former enjoys. 

Though Poincare was doubtless one of its beneficiaries, I have quoted 
his hypothesis regarding the nature of that guidance— the automatic 
mixing machine in the basement— as an example of a mechanistic 
explanation. In fact, however, the underground games of the mind were 
seen to be of a highly sophisticated, visionary and witty nature, al- 
though its rules are not those of formal logic. The dreamer constandy 
bisociates— innocently as it were— frames of reference which are 
regarded as incompatible in the waking state; he drifts effortlessly from 
matrix to matrix, without being aware of it; in his inner landscape, the 
bisociative techniques of humour and discovery are reflected upside 
down, like trees in a pond. The most fertile region seems to be the 
marshy shore, the borderland between sleep and full awakening — 
where the matrices of disciplined thought are already operating but 
have not yet sufficiently hardened to obstruct the dreamlike fluidity of 
imagination.* 

I have discussed various bisociative devices in which the matchmaking 
activities of the unconscious manifest themselves: the substitution of 



UNDERGROUND GAMES 



vague visual images for precise verbal formulations; symbolization, 
conaetization, and impersonation; mergers of sound and sense, of form 
and function; shifts of emphasis, and reasoning in reverse gear; guidance 
by nascent analogies. In day-dream ing, and in most dreams of ordinary 
mortals, these activities are free-wheeling or serving intimately per- 
sonal ends; in the inspired moments of artists and scientists they are 
harnessed to the creative purpose. 

The moment of truth, the sudden emergence of a new insight, is an 
act of intuition. Such intuitions give the appearance of miraculous 
flashes, or short-circuits of reasoning. In fact they may be likened to an 
immersed chain, of which only the beginning and the end are visible 
above the surface of consciousness. The diver vanishes at one end of the 
chain and comes up at the other end, guided by invisible links. 

Habit and originality, then, point in opposite directions in the two- 
way traffic between conscious and unconscious processes. The conden- 
sation of learning into habit, and the automatization of skills constitute 
the downward stream; while the upward traffic consists in the minor, 
vitalizing pulses from the underground, and the rare major surges of 
creation. 

NOTES 

To p, 192. Jung's emphasis on the mandala as the symbol of the coincidencia 
oppositorum concerns the reconciliation of opposites in the fully integrated person — 
which is an altogether different question. 

To p. 202. Half a century earlier, the cracklings and sparks produced by 
rubbing a piece of amber had been compared to lightning and thunder by Wall, 
a friend of Boyle's; but as the context shows, the comparison was meant in a 
purely metaphorical way. 

To p. 210. \ . . Einstein has reported that his profound generalization con- 
necting space and time occurred to him while he was sick in bed. Descartes is 
said to have made his discoveries while lying in bed in the morning and both 
Cannon and Poincare report having got bright ideas when lying in bed unable to 
sleep — the only good thing to be said for insomnia! It is said that James Brindley, 
the great engineer, when up against a difficult problem, would go to bed for 
several days till it was solved. Walter Scott wrote to a friend: 

4 "The half-hour between waking and rising has all my life proved propitious 
to any task which was exercising my invention. ... It was always when I first 
opened my eyes that the desired ideas thronged upon me." ' (Beveridge, W. I. B., 
1950, pp. 73-4). 



IX 

THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 

False Inspirations 

I have discussed the genesis of the Eureka act — the sudden shaking 
together of two previously unconnected matrices; let us now turn 
to the aftermath of it. 
If all goes well that single, explosive contact will lead to a lasting 
fusion of the two matrices — a new synthesis will emerge, a further 
advance in mental evolution will have been achieved. On the other 
hand, the inspiration may have been a mirage; or premature; or not 
sumciendy impressive to be believed in. 

A stimulating inquiry by the American chemists Piatt and Barker 
showed that among those scientists who answered their questionnaire 
eighty-three per cent claimed frequent or occasional assistance from 
unconscious intuitions. But at the same time only seven pe* cent among 
them asserted that their intuitions were always correct; the remainder 
estimated the percentage of their 'false intuitions' variously at ten to 
ninety per cent. 

A false inspiration is not an ordinary error committed in the course 
of a routine operation, such as making a mistake in counting. It is a kind 
of inspired blunder which presents itself in the guise of an original 
synthesis, and carries the same subjective conviction as Archimedes' s 
cry did. Let me quote Poincare once more: 

I have spoken of the feeling of absolute certitude accompanying 
the inspiration; often this feeling deceives us without it being any 

the less vivid When a sudden iHumriiiation seizes upon the mind 

of the mathematician, it usually happens that it does not deceive him, 
but it also sometimes happens, mat it does not stand the test of 
verification; well, we almost always notice that this false idea, had it 
been true, would have gratified our natural feeling for mathematical 
elegance. 1 

2X2 



THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 213 

The previous chapters may have given the mistaken impression that 
the genius need only listen to his Socratian demon and all will be well. 
But the demon is a great hoaxer— precisely because he is not bound by 
the codes of disciplined thought; and every original thinker who relies, 
as he must, on his unconscious hunches, incurs much greater risks to his 
career and sanity than his more pedestrian colleagues. 'The world little 
knows', wrote Faraday, 'how many of the thoughts and theories which 
have passed through the mind of a scientific investigator have been 
crushed in silence and secrecy; that in the most successful instances not 
a tenth of the suggestions, the hopes, the wishes, the preliminary 
conclusions have been realized.' 2 Darwin, Huxley, and Planck, among 
many others, made similar confessions; Einstein lost 'two years of hard 
work' owing to a false inspiration. 'The imagination, wrote Beveridge, 
'merely enables us to wander into the darkness of the unknown where, 
by the dim light of the knowledge that we carry, we may glimpse 
something that seems of interest. But when we bring it out and 
examine it more closely it usually proves to be only trash whose 
glitter had caught our attention. Imagination is at once the source of 
all hope and inspiration but also of frustration. To forget this is to court 
despair/ 3 

All through his life Kepler hoped to prove that the motions of the 
planets round the sun obeyed certain musical laws, the harmonies of the 
spheres. When he was approaching fifty, he thought he had succeeded 
The following is one of the rare instances on record of a genius des- 
cribing the heady effect of a false inspiration — Kepler never discovered 
that he was the victim of a delusion: 

The thing which dawned on me twenty-five years ago before I had 
yet discovered the five perfect bodies between the heavenly orbits; 
which sixteen years ago I proclaimed as the ultimate aim of all 
research; which caused me to devote the best years of my life to 
astronomical studies, to join Tycho Brahe and to choose Prague as 
my residence — that I have, with the aid of God, who set my en- 
thusiasm on fire and stirred in me an irrepressible desire, who kept 
my life and intelligence alert — that I have now at long last brought 
to light. Having perceived the first glimmer of dawn eighteen 
months ago, the light of day three months ago, but only a few days 
ago the plain sun of a most wonderful vision-— nothing shall now 
hold me back. Yes, I give myself up to holy raving. If you forgive 
me, I shall rejoice. If you are angry, I shall bear it. Behold, I have 



214 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



cast the dice, and I am writing a book either for my contemporaries, 
or for posterity. It is all the same to me. It may wait a hundred 
years for a reader, since God has also waited six thousand years for a 
witness. 4 

T. H. Huxley has said that the tragedies, of science are the slayings of 
beautiful hypotheses by ugly facts. Against this tragedy, at least, the 
artist seems to be immune. On the other hand, it is generally believed 
that the scientist can at least rely on the verification of his intuitions by 
experiment, whereas the artist has no such objective tests to decide 
whether or not he should burn his manuscript, or slash his canvas to 
pieces. 

In fact, however, Verification by experiment' can never yield 
absoulte certainty, and when it comes to controversial issues the data 
can usually be interpreted in more than one way. The history of 
medicine is full of obvious and distressing examples of this. In physics 
and chemistry too, the best we can do by so-called 'crucial experiments' 
is to confirm a prediction — but not the theory on which the prediction 
is based (see below, pp 270-6); and scientific controversies about the 
interpretation of experimental results have been just as passionate and 
subjective as controversies between theologians or art critics. If a hunch 
is drastically contradicted by experiment, it will of course be aban- 
doned. But, by and large, scientists are inclined to trust their intuitions; 
and if confronted with experiments which give ambiguous or diver- 
gent results, either to declare— as Einstein once did-— that 'the facts are 
wrong*; or—as Hobbes did — that 'the instance is so particular and 
singular, that 'tis scarce worth our observing' ; or to resort to the standard 
phrase that the unfavourable experimental result is due 'to unknown 
sources of error'— hoping that some day, somehow, it will all work out. 
Modern theoretical physics lives to a large extent on that hope. Thus 
veriflability is a matter of degrees, and neither the artist, nor the 
scientist who tries to break new ground, can hope ever to achieve 
absolute certainty. 

Premature Linkages 

I have mentioned discoveries which were the happy outcome of a 
comedy of errors. No less frequent are those tragedies in the history of 
thought, where the right kind of intuition begets wrong results-— faulty 
integrations, premature births. 



THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 



215 



The first attempt to describe physical reality by mathematical relations 
was made in the sixth century B.C. by the Pythagorean Brotherhood — 
a religious, scientific, and political Order which wielded great power in 
the south of Italy. They succeeded in explaining musical quality by 
quantitative laws, and believed that ultimately 'all things are numbers'. 

But they translated this prophetic intuition into a premature synthesis 
between 'things' and 'numbers', based on the assumption that a line 
consisted of a definable number of tiny dots, a plane of a definable 
number of these lines, and so on. They soon discovered, however, that 
the length of a line such as the diagonal of a square cannot be defined 
by any countable number of dots; one can draw the diagonal in a jiffy, 
but to write down the number defining its length one would have to 
use an infinite series of decimals. To make the scandal worse, numbers 
of this kind could be shown to be neither even nor odd — or both. 
Pythagoreans called these numbers arrketos, unspeakable (we call them, 
more politely, irrational numbers), and tried to keep their existence 
secret, because they were convinced that their assertion of a harmonious 
mathematical order behind the untidy world of appearances was true 
and correct; when a member of the Brotherhood, Hippasos, let the 
secret leak out, he was reportedly put to death. The failure of this 
premature attempt at a synthesis brought the quantitative approach to 
nature into discredit. The physics of Aristotle, which ruled Europe for 
two thousand years, paid no attention to quantity or measurement; 
physics remained divorced from mathematics until the scientific 
revolution in the seventeenth century a.d. brought them together 
again. 

Another premature synthesis, which I have already mentioned, was 
the Keplerian cosmology, in which the sun sweeps the lazy planets 
round their orbits with invisible heavenly brooms. But, in this case, the 
error was a fertile one: physics and astronomy, once 'shaken together' 
even though in the wrong way, could never again be separated. 
Equally fertile was the alchemists' right intuition, supported by wrong 
arguments, of the transmutability of chemical elements. On the other 
hand, the phrenology of Franz Josef Gall had the opposite effect. Gall 
thought that every mental faculty is seated in a definite region on the 
surface of the brain, and that a person's abilities and character could be 
assessed by the bumps on his skull. It was the first, premature, and naive 
attempt to correlate psychology with brain-physiology. Though 
phrenology was highly fashionable around a.d. 1800, it brought such 
discredit in its wake that for a century or more psychologists would 



216 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



have nothing to do with, speculations ahout the structure and function 
of the brain. 

Thus the premature integration of matrices which are not yet suffici- 
ently consolidated has in some cases a wholesome effect, by stimulating 
more mature attempts in the same direction; while in other cases it acts 
as a deterrent and carries the stigma of superstition or 'un-scientific 
thinking*. Taken in a wider sense, the category of premature intuitions 
accommodates the whole body of folk-wisdom— -herbal knowledge, 
weather-lore, psychosomatic healing by hypnosis, suggestion, shock, 
and abreaction — down to Jenner's diarymaid who 'would not take the 
pox\ We have learned to recognize in these intuitive insights and 
techniques the forerunners of our more mature discoveries and re- 
discoveries; and we thus arrive at a progression in several stages. In the 
first stage the two matrices which will participate in the ultimate 
synthesis are tentatively and inadequately joined together by the logic 
of the unconscious. In the second the haphazard connection is severed 
again, and a reaction may set in which keeps them apart for a consider- 
able time. In the final stage, after the definite merger, the previously 
separate matrices become mentally inseparable, and we marvel at our 
former blindness. 

Sncwblindness 

*The mind', wrote 'Wilfred Trotter, 'likes a strange idea as little as 
the body likes a strange protein and resists it with similar energy. It 
would not perhaps be too fanciful to say that a new idea is the most 
quickly acting antigen known to science. If we watch ourselves honestly 
we shall often find that we have begun to argue against a new idea even 
before it has been completely stated/ 5 

I shall not dwell on the martyrology of genius; the title of this section 
refers to that remarkable form of blindness which often prevents the 
original thinker from perceiving the meaning and significance of his 
own discovery. Jealousy apart, the anti-body reaction directed against 
new ideas seems to be much the same whether the idea was let loose 
by others — or oneself. The defence mechanisms which protect habits 
against the instrusion of novelty accounts both for our mental inertia — 
and mental stability. 

Copernicus was an orthodox believer in the physics of Aristode, and 
stubbornly clung to the dogma that all heavenly bodies must move in 
perfect circles at uniform velocities. In the fourth chapter of the Third 



THE SPAM AND TH2 FLAME 



217 



Book of the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, the original manuscript 
of the book contains the following lines: 

It should be noticed, by the way, that if the two circles have 
different diameters, other conditions remaining unchanged, then the 
resulting movement will not be a straight line but . . . what mathe- 
maticians call an ellipse, (my italics) 

This is actually not true, for the resulting curve will be a cycloid 
resembling an ellipse — but the odd fact is that Copernicus had hit on the 
ellipse which is the form of all planetary orbits — had arrived at it for the 
wrong reasons and by faulty deduction — and having done so, promptly 
dropped it: the passage is crossed out in the manuscript, and is not 
contained in the printed edition of the Revolutions. The history of human 
thought is full of triumphant eurekas; but only rarely do we hear of the 
anti-climaxes, the missed opportunities, which leave no trace. 

Kepler, too, nearly threw away the elliptic orbits; for almost three 
years he held the solution in his hands — without seeing it His conscious 
mind refused to accept the 'cartload of dung' which the underground 
had cast up. When the battle was over, he confessed: 'Why should I 
mince my words? The truth of Nature, which I had rejected and 
chased away, returned by stealth through the backdoor, disguising 
itself to be accepted. Ah, what a foolish bird I have been!* 6 

Poor Kepler, he was even more foolish than he thought: he actually 
discovered universal gravity—then rejected it. In the Preface to the 
New Astronomy he explains that the tides are due to the attraction of the 
moon, and describes the working of gravity — even that the attracting 
force is proportionate to mass; but in the text of that book, and of all 
subsequent works, he has—incredible as it sounds — completely for- 
gotten all about it. I have given elsewhere a detailed account of this 
remarkable case of snowblindness. 7 

Galileo revolutionized astronomy by the use of the telescope; but he 
refused to believe in the reality of comets and declared them to be 
optical illusions. For he too believed that heavenly bodies must move 
in perfect circles; and since comets moved in very elongated elliptical 
orbits, they could not be heavenly bodies. 

Freud's revered master, Professor Brucke at the Vienna Medicine 
Faculty, discovered, in 1849, a technique to illuminate the retina of the 
eye; but the idea of observing the muminated retina through a lens did 
not occur to him! It was his friend Helmholtz who hit on the idea — 



2l8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



while preparing a lecture on Brucke's work— and thus became the 
inventor of the ophthalmoscope. 

Freud himself had two narrow escapes, as it were, from achieving 
world fame in his twenties. In the course of his physiological researches 
at Brucke's Institute 'he was trembling on the very brink of the 
important neurone theory, the basis of modern neurology'; but, as 
Ernest Jones said, 'in the endeavour to acquire "discipline" he had not 
yet perceived that in original scientific work there is an equally 
important place for imagination. 8 It is strange indeed to hear the 
founder of psychoanalysis being accused by his pupil and biographer of 
having in his early years suffered from lack of imagination; but there it 
is — and worse to come. 

The fantastic character of the 'Cocaine Episode' in Freud's life can be 
appreciated only by comparing the silences in Freud's autobiography 
with the revelations in Jones's biography. In the spring of 1884 Freud 
— then twenty-eight — read in a German medical paper that an Army 
doctor had been experimenting 'with cocaine, the essential constituent 
of coca leaves which some Indian tribes chew to enable them to resist 
privations and hardships*. He ordered a small quantity of the stuff from 
a pharmaceutical firm, tried it on himself, his sisters, fiancee, and 
patients, decided that cocaine was a 'magical drug', which procured 
*the most gorgeous excitement', left no harmful after-effect, and was not 
habit-forming! In several publications he unreservedly recommended 
the use of cocaine against depression, indigestion, 'in those functional 
states comprised under the name of neurasthenia', and during the with- 
drawal-therapy of morphine addicts; he even tried to cure diabetes 
with it. 'I am busy', he wrote to his future wife, 'collecting the literature 
for a song of praise to this magical substance.' One is irresistibly 
reminded of Aldous Huxley's songs of praise to mescaline; but Huxley 
was neither a member of the medical profession nor the founder of a 
new school in psychotherapy. 

Two years after the publication of his first paper on the wonder-drug 
Knapp, the great American ophthalmologist, greeted Freud 'as the man 
who had introduced cocaine to the world, and congratulated him on 
the achievement. In the same year, 1886, however, cases of cocaine 
addiction and intoxication were being reported from all over the world, 
and in Germany there was a general alarm — 9 The man who had tried 
to benefit humanity or at all events to create a reputation by curing 
"neurasthenia" was now accused of unleashing evil on the world.' 
Among Ireud's personal patients one died as a result of a large dose of 



THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 



219 



the drug; another — his close friend Fleischl — whom he tried to cure from 
morphine addiction, became cocaine-addicted instead, and developed 
*a delirium tremens with white snakes creeping over his skin'. 10 A 
leading neurologist, Erlenmeyer, described cocaine as 'the third scourge 
of humanity ' — the other two being alcohol and morphine. 11 

I have said enough about the disasters of this episode. And yet Freud's 
dabbling with cocaine became a blessing to humanity — but not in the 
way in which he had thought of it. Two of his colleagues at the 
Medical Faculty, Koller and Koenigstein, both ophthalmologists, both 
of incomparably smaller stature than Freud, read his 1884 paper, 
experimented with cocaine, and saw almost at once what Freud's 
snowblindness prevented him from seeing. Freud was not interested in 
surgery; it did not enter into his habits of thought. He was fascinated 
by the possible internal uses of cocaine, and, above all, its effects on 
nervous disorders. Only in the final paragraph of his paper did he 
casually mention some possible additional uses* of cocaine as a pain- 
deadener in local infections; its uses as an anaesthetic in minor surgery 
never occurred to him. He and Koller both noticed that after swallow- 
ing cocaine their mouths and lips went numb — the familiar sensation 
after the dentist's injection. Koller took the hint—Freud did not. Freud 
suggested to Koenigstein that cocaine could be used to alleviate the pain 
in certain eye-diseases; but it was Koenigstein who thought of using it 
as an anaesthetic in eye-operations. Among the first of these, incident- 
ally, was an operation on Freud's father for glaucoma— carried out 
by Koenigstein, with Koller administering the cocaine, and Freud 
assisting. . . . 

But even at that stage Freud still considered the tremendous benefits 
of local anaesthetics as merely 'one more of the outlying applications of 
which his beloved drug was capable. It took a long time before he 
could assimilate the bitter truth that Roller's use of it was to prove 
practically the only one of value and all the rest dust and ashes/ 12 

Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, Freud— I have quoted only a few out- 
standing examples of mental eye-cataract. How often did Archimedes 
get into his bath and watch the rising water-level which gave a perfect 
measure of the volume of his gnarled body? We must resign ourselves 
to the fact that snowblindness is inherent in the human condition; if it 
were not so, then everything we know today about the theory of 
numbers, or analytical geometry, would have been discovered within 
a few generations after Euclid. 



Gradual Integrations 



In some of the discoveries which I discussed earlier on a sudden 
intuition sparked off the instant fusion of previously unrelated matrices. 
In the cases described in the previous section the spark failed to ignite, 
m yet other cases it initiates the fusion without completing it. Loewi 
could not decipher the note relating^ to his dream, and had to dream, a 
second time before he accepted its message. Kepler rejected the 'truth 
of Nature', and only admitted it when it returned 'by the backdoor'. 
Some of K6hler*s less gifted chimpanzees discovered, unaided, various 
new techniques for making and using tools — then seemed to forget 
them again; but on the next test they rediscovered them after a much 
shorter period of trying than the first time (See Book Two, XIII). 
The human equivalent of this situation is a cry of distress: 'Blast it, I had 
the solution, but now I have forgotten it again/ 

Cases of this kind make one think of a lighter whose wick has started 
to glow, without properly burning. The struggle will have to go on, and 
more sparks will have to be produced, before it bursts into flame. In 
other words, intuition has established some tentative link between the 
two distant frames of reference, but that link is insufficient to overcome 
resistances and effect their fusion. It will have to be strengthened by 
repetition (as in the case of Loewi) or else additional links will have to 
be discovered to precipitate the integration. 

The Dawn of Language 

The most common example for this type of gradual process is the 
way in which the child discovers that 'all things have names'. During 
the first year of its life, the average baby progresses from spontaneous 
babbling to the imitative repetition of syllables and words spoken by 
adults— with some vague intimations that these words are somehow 
connected with the situation in which they are regularly used. It seems 
that eager parents frequently teach their offspring its first words by a 
process of repetitive 'stamping in', at an age when the baby is not yet 
ripe to grasp the principles involved. Thus Watson conditioned an infant 
to say 'da* whenever it was given the bottle, starting at five months, 
twenty days — that is, six months earlier than the first words normally 
appear. The process took more than three weeks, at the end of 
which the word 'da' became the first, mechanically established 1™k 

220 



THE SPARS AND THE FLAME 



221 



between the two otherwise still unrelated matrices of 'sounds* and 
'things'. 

"With each month that passes, the acquisition of new word-links 
becomes quicker and easier; the child is 'learning to learn'; until, usually 
in the second half of the second year, it 'makes the most important 
discovery of its whole life — that everything has a name 9 . 23 As far as one 
can generalize from the scant statistics, the vocabulary of the average 
child at the close of the first year is three words; at eighteen months 
twenty-two words. This seems to be the approximate age when the 
'naming discovery* is made, for three months later the average vocabu- 
lary has jumped to a hundred and eighteen: 





Smith's Test 1 * 






Average size of vocabularies 




Age 


Number of cases reported Number 


of words 


—8 


13 


0 


— 10 


17 


i 


I — 0 


52 


3 


i— 3 


19 


19 


1—6 


14 


22 


i—9 


14 


118 


2 — 0 


25 


272 


2—6 


14 


446 


3—o 


20 


896 


3-6 


26 


1222 


4—o 


26 


1540 


4-6 


32 


187O 


5—0 


20 


2072 


5-6 


27 


2289 


6—0 


9 


2562 



The integration of the matrices is indicated not only by the steep rise 
of the learning curve after the eighteenth month, but by the fact that 
from now on the child, of its own initiative, will point at a thing and 
ask to be told its name. Delighted with its discovery, it sometimes 
develops a veritable 'naming mania': it indicates an object, calls out its 
name, or, if it has forgotten it, invents a name of its own; for henceforth 
a person or thing is felt to be incomplete if it has no name attached to it. 

Thus the dawn of symbol-consciousness is a gradual, cumulative 



222 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



event; a kind of diluted Eureka process, spread out in time, because the 
final integration can take place only when the child's mental organiza- 
tion has attained sufficient maturity. But the same process may occur in 
a telescoped, highly dramatized form in rare cases such as Helen Keller's. 
The blind, deaf, and mute litde girl was nearly seven when Miss 
Sullivan took charge of her and taught her the first few words, c-a-k-e, 
d-o-1-1, etc., by means of the manual alphabet, a kind of morse spelt by 
finger-play. Since Helen was 'overripe' for learning a language, she 
covered, within less than a month, the same ground which takes a 
normal child about two years, from the imitative acquisition of the 
first word ( e I did not know that I was spelling a word or even that 
words existed; I was simply making my fingers go in monkey-like 
imitation.') — to the final discovery: 

We walked down the path to the well-house, attracted by the 
fragrance of the honeysuckle with which it was covered. Some one 
was drawing water and my teacher placed my hand under the spout. 
As the cool stream gushed over one hand she spelled into the other 
the word water, first slowly, then rapidly. I stood still, my whole 
attention fixed upon the motions of her fingers. Suddenly I felt a 
misty consciousness as of something forgotten — a thrill of returning 
thought; and somehow the mystery of language was revealed to 
me. I knew then that 'w-a-t-e-r' meant the wonderful cool some- 
thing that was flowing over my hand. That living word awakened 
my soul, gave it light, joy, set it free! . . . 

I left the well-house eager to learn. Everything had a name, and 
each name gave birth to a new thought. As we returned to the house 
each object that I touched seemed to quiver with life. That was 
because I saw everything with the strange new sight that had come 
to me. 15 

Here we have the undiluted bisociative act, the sudden synthesis of 
the universe of signs and the universe of things. In its sequel each 
matrix imparts a new significance, a new dimension to the other: the 
words begin to *Iive\ to 'give birth to new thoughts*; and the objects 
begin to 'quiver* under the touch of the magic wand of language. 

Helen Keller's dramatic moment of truth is quite unlike the gradual 
dawn of the name-relation in normal children, and much closer to the 
sudden insight in discoveries of the type of Pasteur's. The normal child's 
n a m in g discovery could be likened to the process known in logic as 



THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 



223 



empirical induction: 'some things have names ergo I assume that all things 
have names'. (Needless to say, I do not mean to impute any conscious 
reasoning of this kind to the babe in its cradle.) The chick episode, on the 
other hand, which made Pasteur jump to his conclusion and establish 
the general principle of immunization, could be called 'induction from 
a single case' — a procedure usually illustrated in primers on logic by the 
example 'all French waiters have red hair'. For a detailed discussion of 
the relations of gradual learning to sudden discovery I must refer the 
reader to Book Two. 

Summary 

New integrations arise by various processes which can be arranged in 
a series. It ranges from faulty or premature integrations, through partial 
blindness towards the meaning and significance of one's own dis- 
coveries, to the gradual blending of matrices by dint of repetitive 
experiences, which increase the number of links between them. 
Finally, there is the sudden iUumination of 'spontaneous' discoveries, 
sparked off by an unconscious intuition, or a chance observation, or a 
combination of both. 



X 

THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 

There is a theory, put forward by George Sarton, and held to be 
self-evident by many scientists, which says, broadly speaking, 
that the history of science is the only history which displays a 
cumulative progress of knowledge; that, accordingly, the progress of 
science is the only yardstick by which we can measure the progress of 
mankind; and moreover, that the word 'progress* itself has no clearly 
defined meaning in any field of activity — except the field of science. 

This is the kind of pronouncement where it is advisable to hold one's 
breath and count to ten before expressing indignant protest or smug 
agreement, according to one's allegiance to eggheads or engineers. 
Personally I believe that there is a grain of truth in Sarton's proposition 
— but no more than that. 

Separations and Reintegrations 

There are certain analogies between the characteristic stages in the 
history of an individual discovery, and the historical development of a 
branch of science as a whole. Thus a 'blocked matrix* in the individual 
mind reflects some kind of impasse into which a science has manoeuvred 
itself. The 'period of incubation , with its frustrations, tensions, random 
tries, and false inspirations, corresponds to the critical periods of 'fertile 
anarchy* which recur, from time to time, in the history of every science. 
These crises have, as we saw, a destructive and a constructive aspect. 
In the case of the individual scientist, they involve a temporary retreat 
to some more primitive form of ideation — innocence regained through 
the sacrifice of hard-won intellectual positions and established beliefs; 
in the case of a branch of science taken as a whole, the crisis manifests 
itself in a relaxation of the rigid rules of the game, a thawing of the 

224 



THE EVOLUTION OP IDEAS 



225 



collective matrix, the breakdown of mental Habits and absolute 
frontiers — a process of reader pour mieux sauter on an historic scale. The 
Eureka act proper, the moment of truth experienced by the creative 
individual, is paralleled on the collective plane by the emergence, out 
of the scattered fragments, of a new synthesis, brought about by a 
quick succession of individual discoveries — where, characteristically, 
the same discovery is often made by several individuals at the same 
time (cf. p. 110 f). 

The last stage — verification, elaboration, consolidation — is by far the 
least spectacular, the most exacting, and occupies the longest periods of 
time both in the life of the individual and in the historical evolution of 
science. Copernicus picked up the ancient Pythagorean teaching of the 
sun as the centre of all planetary motions when he was a student in 
Renaissance Italy (where the idea was much discussed at the time), and 
spent the rest of his life elaborating it into a system. Darwin hit on the 
idea of evolution by natural selection at the age of twenty-nine; the 
remaining forty-four years of his life were devoted to its corroboration 
and exposition. Pasteur's life reads like a story divided into several 
chapters. Each chapter represents a period which he devoted to one field 
of research; at the beginning of each period stands the publication of a 
short preliminary note which contained the basic discovery in a nut- 
shell; then followed ten or fifteen years of elaboration, consolidation, 
clarification. 

The collective advances of science as a whole, and of each of its 
specialized branches, show the same alternation between relatively 
brief eruptions which lead to the conquest of new frontiers, and long 
periods of consolidation. In the case of the individual, this protracted 
chore has its natural limits at three score years and ten, or thereabouts; 
but on the historical stage, the assimilation, consolidation, interpreta- 
tion, and elaboration of a once revolutionary discovery may go on for 
generations, and even centuries. The new territory opened up by the 
impetuous advance of a few geniuses, acting as a spearhead, is subse- 
quently occupied by the solid phalanxes of mediocrity; and soon the 
revolution turns into a new orthodoxy, with its unavoidable symp- 
toms of one-sidedness, over-specialization, loss of contact with other 
provinces of knowledge, and ultimately, estrangement "from reality. 
We see this happening — unavoidably, it seems — at various times in the 
history of various sciences. The emergent orthodoxy hardens into a 
'closed system' of thought, unwilling or unable to assimilate new 
empirical data or to adjust itself to significant changes in other fields of 



226 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



knowledge; sooner or later the matrix is blocked, a new crisis arises, 
leading to a new synthesis, and the cycle starts again. 

This does not mean, of course, that science does not advance; only 
that it advances in a jerky, unpredictable, ^ unscientific , way. Although 
'in the year 1500 Europe knew less than Archimedes who died in the 
year 212 B.C.', 1 it would nevertheless be foolish to deny that today we 
know considerably more than Archimedes. And I mean by that not 
only the fantastic and threatening achievements of applied science 
which have transformed this planet to a point where it is becoming 
increasingly uninhabitable; but that we also know more than Archi- 
medes in other, more worthwhile ways, by having gained deeper 
insights into the structure of the universe, from the spiral nebulae to the 
acid molecules which govern heredity. 

But these insights were not gained by the steady advance of science 
along a straight line. Mental evolution is a continuation of biological 
evolution, and in various respects resembles its crooked ways. 'Evolu- 
tion is known to be a wasteful, fumbling process characterized by 
sudden mutations of unknown cause, by the slow grinding of selection, 
and by the dead-ends of over-specialization and loss of adaptability. 
"Progress'* can by definition never go wrong; evolution constantly does; 
and so does the evolution of ideas, including those of "exact science". 
New ideas are thrown up spontaneously like mutations; the vast 
majority of them are useless, the equivalent of biological freaks without 
survival-value. There is a constant struggle for survival between 
competing theories in every branch of the history of thought. When we 
call ideas "fertile" or "sterile", we are unconsciously guided by 
biological analogy. . . 

'Moreover, there occur in biological evolution periods of crisis and 
transition when there is a rapid, almost explosive, branching out 
in all directions, often resulting in a radical change in the dorninant 
trend of development. After these stages of "adaptative radiations", 
when the species is plastic and malleable, there usually follow periods 
of stabilization and specialization along the new lines—which again 
often lead into dead ends of rigid over-specialization/ 2 

But there the analogy ends. The br^ching of the evolutionist's tree 
of life is a one-way process; giraffes and whales do not bisociate to give 
rise to a new synthesis. The evolution of ideas, on the other hand, is a 
tale of ever-repeated differentiation, specialization and reintegrations on 
a higher level; a progression from primordial unity through variety to 
more complex patterns of unity-in-variety. 



Twenty-six Centuries of Science 



If we could takes kind of grandstand view of the history of scientific 
thought we would at once be struck by its discontinuity, its abrupt 
changes of tempo and rhythm. The record starts in the sixth century 
B.C. when we find suddenly, as if sprung from nowhere, a galaxy of 
Philosophers of Nature in Miletus and Elea and Samos, discussing the 
origins and evolution of the universe, its form and substance, its 
structure and laws, in terms which have become forever incorporated 
into our vocabulary and our matrices of thought. They were searching 
for some simple, ultimate principles and primeval substances under- 
lying all diversity: four elements, four humours, atoms of a single kind, 
moving according to fixed laws. The Pythagoreans attempted the first 
grand synthesis: they tried to weave the separate threads of religion, 
medicine, astronomy, and music into a single carpet with an austere 
geometrical design. That carpet is still in the making, but its basic 
pattern was laid down in the three centuries of the heroic age of Greek 
science between Thales and Aristotle. 

After the Macedonian conquest of Greece there followed a period 
of consolidation, orthodoxy, and decline. Aristode's categories 
became the grammar of existence, his animal spirits ruled the 
world of physics, everything worth knowing was already known, and 
everything inventable already invented. The Heroic Age was guided 
by the example of Prometheus stealing the fire of the gods; the 
philosophers of the Hellenistic period dwelt in Plato's cave, drawing 
epicycles on the wall, their backs turned to the daylight of reality. 

After that there came a period of hibernation lasting for fifteen 
centuries. During that time the march of science was not only halted, 
but its direction reversed. M* Pyke, a contemporary philosopher of 
science, wrote about 'the inability of science to go backwards — once the 
neutron has been discovered it remains discovered'. 3 Does it? In the 
fifth century B.C. the educated classes knew that the earth was a 
spherical body floating in space and spinning round its axis; a thousand 
years later they thought that it was a flat disc, or a rectangle perhaps. 
Similar, though less drastic examples of forgetfulness can also be shown 
to have occurred in modern science. 

In the twelfth century A..D. we observe the first signs of a thaw, and 
during the next hundred years there are hopeful stirrings: it is the 
century of Roger Bacon and Peter Peregrine, of the budding univer- 
sities at Oxford and Cambridge, Salerno, Bologna, and Paris. But it is 

327 



228 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



also the century of the fatal mesalliance between Aristotelian physics and 
the theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Within a few generations this 
'faulty synthesis' was to create a new orthodoxy, which led to another 
three centuries of sterility and stagnation. 

Then comes a.d. 1600— a landmark second in importance only to 
600 B.C. — which inaugurates the second heroic age of science: the 
century of Dr. Gilbert, Kepler, Galileo, Pascal, Descartes, Leibniz, 
Huyghens, Harvey, and Newton. In the next century, the eighteenth, 
the speed of the advance is considerably reduced: it is a period of 
assimilation, consolidation, and stock-taking, the age of the popular- 
izes, classifiers, and systematizers; of Fontanelle, Linnaeus, and Buffon, 
of the Philosophes and Encyclopidistes. As Pledge has remarked: 'An 
observer born early in the century, and making the Grand Tour, 
would have been an old man before he came across, in the Paris of 
Lavoisier, anyone worthy of Newton/ 4 

Finally, in the nineteenth century and in the first half of the twentieth, 
we have an explosive development of ever-increasing momentum. The 
nineteenth century was the age of the most spectacular syntheses in the 
history of thought— of royal marriages between previously unrelated 
and often hostile dynasties. The science of electricity merged with that 
of magnetism.* Then electro-magnetic radiations were discovered to 
account for light, colour, radiant heat, Hertzian waves. Chemistry was 
swallowed up by atomic physics. The control of the body by nerves and 
glands was seen to rely on electro-chemical processes. The previously 
independent effluvia' or powers of nature' which had been known as 
'heat', 'light', 'electric fire', mechanical motion', 'magnetic flux' were 
recognized to be all convertible one into another, and to be merely 
different forms of 'energy', whose total amount contained in the 
universe always remained the same. Soon afterwards, the various 
forms of matter, the 'elements' of chemistry, suffered the same fate, 
as they were all found to be constructed out of the same building blocks 
in different combinations. And lastly, these building blocks themselves 
seemed to be nothing but parcels of compressed energy, packed and 
patterned according to certain mathematical formulae. 

The Pythagorean aspiration, to reduce 'all things to numbers', 
seemed to be at last on the point of fulfilment. The advance of science 
in the last century offers the panorama of a majestic river-delta, where 
the various branches first separate and diverge, then follow more or less 
parallel courses, in a complex pattern of cross-connections and re- 
unifications, as they approach their ultimate confluence in the sea. 



Creative Anarchy 



Even this short and breathless gallop through the twenty-six centuries 
since the dawn of scientific thought, ought to be sufficient to show that 
the progress of science is neither gradual nor continuous. Each basic 
advance was effected by a more or less abrupt and dramatic change: 
the breaking down of frontiers between related territories, the amal- 
gamation of previously separate frames of reference or experimental 
techniques; the sudden falling into pattern of previously disjointed 
data. Let me illustrate this process by a few further examples — no 
longer of individual discoveries, but of episodes in the evolution of 
the collective matrices of science. 

In the recurrent cycle described in the previous section I mentioned 
periods of crisis and creative anarchy (corresponding to the individual's 
'period of incubation'), which precede the new synthesis. The first such 
crisis occurred at the very beginning of our story when the ritualized 
worship of the Olympian gods and demi-gods could no longer provide 
answers to the ultimate questions after the meaning of existence. 
Mythology had become a 'blocked matrix , ; from the whims of Vulcan 
and Poseidon man's interest turned to the nature of fire and water; 
from the chariot of Helios to the motions of the sun along the ecliptic; 
from the antics of Zeus and Athena to the natural causes of physical 
events. The result was mtoxicating. To quote Burnet: *No sooner did 
an Ionian philosopher learn half a dozen geometrical propositions and 
hear that the phenomena of the heavens recur in cycles man he set to 
work to look for law everywhere in nature and with an audacity 
amounting to hubris to construct a system of the universe.' 5 

The same audacity and hubris characterized the early seventeenth cen- 
tury, when the stranglehold of the Aristotelian Schoolmen was broken, 
and the solid, walled-in universe of the Middle Ages lay in shambles, 
exposed to the speculative depradations of hosts of Paracelsians, Gilbert- 
ians, Copernicans, and Galileans. * 'Tis all in pieces, all coherence gone*, 
lamented John Donne; it must have been an intoxicating age to live in. 

Lastly, since the discoveries of the 1920s, theoretical physics, and with 
it our picture of sub-atomic and extra-galactic reality, of substance and 
causality, have again reverted to a state of creative anarchy. And so the 
cycle keeps repeating itself: 

Nature and Nature's laws lay hid in night: 
God said let Newton be, and all was light . . . 
229 



230 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



But alas: 

It did not last: the Devil howling 'Ho! 
Let Einstein be!' restored the status quo?* 

1 Connect, Always Connect 

Out of the creative anarchy emerges the new synthesis. 

I have given in previous chapters a series of examples to show how 
new syntheses arise in the brains of original thinkers through the bi- 
sociation of previously unconnected matrices. The parallel process on 
the collective plane— on the map of history — is the confluence of two 
branches of science which had developed independently, and did not 
seem to have anything in common. 'Theprogress of science', Bronowski 
wrote, 'is the discovery at each step of a new order which gives unity 
to what had long seemed unlike/* 

The new synthesis in the mind of the thinker may emerge suddenly, 
triggered by a single 'link'; or gradually, by an accumulation of 
linkages. On the map of history the 'links' are the discoveries of 
individuals; and here again the process of integration may be sudden, 
or the result of a series of discoveries by several people. The unification 
of arithmetic and geometry — analytical geometry — was a one-man 
show, accomplished by the formidable Descartes. The unification of 
electricity and magnetism, on the other hand, took a hundred years — 
from 1820, when Hans Christian Oersted discovered by chance that an 
electric current flowing through a wire deflected a compass needle 
which happened to lie on the table, to io2r, when O. W. Richardson 
explained ferro-magnetism in terms of electron-spin; and it needed a 
whole series of original discoveries by Ampere, Faraday, Maxwell, and 
others to act as links and bring the crowning synthesis about (see 
Appendix I). 

All decisive advances in the history of scientific thought can be 
described in terms of mental cross-fertilization between different 
disciplines. Some of these historic bisociations appear, even in retro- 
spect, as surprising and far-fetched as the combination of cabbages and 
kings. What lesson, for instance, could one expect neurophysiology to 
derive from astronomy? And yet, here it is. In 1796 a minor scandal 
occurred at the Greenwich Observatory: Maskelyne, the Astronomer 
Royal, dismissed one of his assistants because the latter's observations 
differed from his own by half a second to a whole second. Ten years 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



231 



later the German astronomer Bessel read about this incident in a 
history of the Greenwich Observatory. Bessel, who combined a 
highly original mind with meticulous precision in his observations, 
was puzzled by the frequent occurrence of similar timing mistakes 
by astronomers. It was a typical case of a 'shift of attention* from 
the nuisance aspect of a trivial phenomenon to the investigation of its 
causes. 

After ten years of comparing his own records with those of several 
other astronomers, Bessel was able to prove that there existed systematic 
and consistent differences between the speed with which each of them 
reacted to observed events; and he also succeeded in establishing the 
characteristic reaction-time — called 'the personal equation — of several 
of his colleagues. 

These studies were continued by other astronomers over the next 
thirty years, in the course of which the development of more precise, 
automatic recording instruments made it possible to arrive at 'absolute 
personal equations'. Finally, fifty years after Bessel's discovery, von 
Helmholtz published a paper showing that the rate of conduction of 
impulses in nerves was of a definite, measurable order — and not, as had 
previously been assumed, practically instantaneous. Helmholtz was well 
acquainted with the work that astronomers had done on personal 
equations, and his experiments on the propagation of impulses in motor 
and sensory nerves followed their procedure and techniques. Helm- 
holtz's discovery inaugurated the era of 'mental chronometry', and was 
a decisive step in the progress of neurophysiology and experimental 
psychology. 

In a similar manner the basic advances in our knowledge of infectious 
diseases were mostly due to the importation of experimental techniques 
which had been developed for quite different purposes — such as the use 
of filtering procedures, microscopic techniques, tissue-cultures and the 
statistical methods employed in genetics. 

Bartlett, in Thinking — An Experimental and Social Study (1958), gave 
a series of similar illustrations. The conclusions at which he arrived 
seem to paraphrase the thesis of the present theory that bisociation is 
the essence of creative activity: 

As experimental science has gained wider and wider fields, and 
won increasing recognition, it has often happened that critical stages 
for advance are reached when what has been called one body of 
knowledge can be brought into close and en^ctive relationship with 



232 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



what has been treated as a different, and a largely or wholly inde- 
pendent, scientific discipline. 

, . . The alert experimenter is always on the lookout for points and 
areas of overlap, between things and processes which natural and 
unaided observations has tended to treat merely, or chiefly, as 
different. . . . 

One of the most important features of these turning points in 
experimental development is that they very often introduce methods 
and instrumentation new to the field of research involved, but 
already developed in some other region of investigation. . . . 

The winding progress of any branch of experimental science is 
made up essentially by a relatively small number of original inquiries, 
which may be widely separated, followed, as a rule, by a very large 
number of routine inquiries. The most important feature of original 
experimental thinking is the discovery of overlap and agreement 
where formerly only isolation and difference were recognized. This 
usually means that when any experimental science is ripe for marked 
advance, a mass of routine thinking belonging to an immediately 
preceding phase has come near to wearing itself out by exploiting 
a limited range of techniques to establish more and more minute and 
specialized derail. A stage has been reached in which finding out 
further details adds litde or nothing to what is known already. . . . 

However, at the same time, perhaps in some other branch of 
science, and perhaps in some hitherto disconnected part of what is 
treated as the same branch, there are other techniques generating 
their own problems, opening up their own gaps. An original mind, 
never wholly contained in any one conventionally enclosed field of 
interest, now seizes upon the possibility that there may be some 
unsuspected overlap, takes the risk whether there is or not, and gives 
the old subject-matter a new look. Routine starts again. . . . 

The conditions for original thinking are when two or more 
streams of research begin to offer evidence that they may converge 
and so in some manner be combined. It is the combination which 
can generate new directions of research, and through these it may 
be found that basic units and activities may have properties not 
before suspected which open up a lot of new questions for experi- 
mental study. 6 

But I must add to this a word of warning. Except when it is merely a 
matter of borrowing, so to speak, an existing technique or laboratory 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 233 

equipment from a neighbouring science (as in most of Bartlett's 
examples), the integration of matrices is not a simple operation of 
adding together. It is a process of mutual interference and cross- 
fertilization, in the course of which both matrices are transformed in 
various ways and degrees. Hidden axioms, implied in the old codes, 
suddenly stand revealed and are subsequently dropped; the rules of the 
game are revised before they enter as sub-rules into the composite 
game. When Einstein bisociated energy and matter, both acquired a 
new look in the process. 

The Thinking Cap 

I have repeatedly mentioned 'shifts of attention' to previously 
neglected aspects of experience which make familiar phenomena appear 
in a new, revealing light, seen through spectacles of a different colour. 
At the decisive turning points in the history of science, all the data in 
the field, unchanged in themselves, may fall into a new pattern, and be 
given a new interpretation, a new theoretical frame. 

By stressing the importance of the interpretation (or reinterpretation) 
of facts, I may have given the impression of underestimating the 
importance of collecting facts, of having emphasized the value of theory- 
making at the expense of the empirical aspect of science — an unfor- 
givable heresy in the eyes of Positivists, Behaviourists, and other 
theorists of the anti-theory school. Needless to say, only a fool could 
belittle the importance of observation and experiment — or wish to 
revert to Aristotelian physics which was all speculation and no experi- 
ment. But the collecting of data is a discriminating activity, like the 
picking of flowers, and unlike the action of a lawn-mower; and the 
selection of flowers considered worth picking, as well as their arrange- 
ment into a bouquet, are ultimately matters of personal taste. As T. H. 
Huxley has said in an oft-quoted passage: 

Those who refuse to go beyond fact rarely get as far as fact; and 
anyone who has studied the history of science knows that almost 
every step therein has been made by . . . the invention of a hypothesis 
which, though verifiable, often had little foundation to start with 

Sir Lawrence Bragg is the only physicist who shared a Nobel Prize 
with his own father—for their joint work on analysing crystal 



234 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



structures by means of X-rays, doubtless an eminently factual pre- 
occupation, which took two lifetimes. Yet in his book on The History of 
Science he too concluded that the essence of science 'lies not in dis- 
covering facts, but in discovering new ways of diinking about them'. 7 
New facts do emerge constantly; but they are found as the result of a 
search in a definite direction, based on theoretical considerations — as 
Galle discovered the planet Neptune, which nobody had seen before, by 
directing his telescope at the celestial region which Leverrier's calcula- 
tions had indicated.* This is admittedly an extreme case of observation 
guided by theory; but it remains nevertheless true that it is not enough 
for the scientist to keep his eyes open unless he has an idea of what he is 
looking for. 

The telescope is, of course, the supreme eye-opener and fact-finder 
in astronomy; but it is rarely appreciated that the Copernican revolu- 
tion came before the invention of the telescope — and so did Kepler's 
New Astronomy. The instruments which Copernicus used for observing 
the stars were less precise than those of the Alexandrian astronomers 
Hipparchus and Ptolemy, on whose data Copernicus built his theory; 
and he knew no more about the actual motions of stars and planets 
than they had known: 

Insofar as actual knowledge is concerned, Copernicus was no 
better off, and in some respects worse off, than the Greek astronomers 
of Alexandria who lived in the time of Jesus Christ. They had the 
same data, the same instruments, the same know-how in geometry, 
as he did. They were giants of *exact science'; yet they failed to see 
what Copernicus saw after, and Aristarchus had. seen before them: 
that the planets' motions were obviously governed by the sun. 8 

Similarly, Harvey's revolutionary discoveries were made before the 
microscope was developed into a serviceable tool; and Einstein 
formulated his 'Special Theory of Relativity' in 1905 based on data 
which, as I have already said, were by no means new. Poincare*, for 
instance, Einstein's senior by twenty-five years, had held all the loose 
threads in his hands, and the reasons for his failure to tie them together 
are still a matter of speculation among scientists. To quote Taton: 

Poincare, who had so much wider a mathematical background 
than Einstein, then a young assistant in the Federal Patents Office of 
Berne, knew all the elements required for such a synthesis, of which 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



he had felt the urgent need and for which he had laid the first 
foundations. Nevertheless, he did not dare to explain his thoughts, 
and to derive all the consequences, thus missing the decisive step 
separating him from the real discovery of the principle of relativity. 9 

Without the hard Htde bits of marble which are called 'facts' or 
'data' one cannot compose a mosaic; what matters, however, are not 
so much the individual bits, but the successive patterns into which you 
arrange them, then break them up and rearrange them. 'We shall 
find', wrote Butterfield on the opening page of his history of the 
Scientific Revolution, 'that in both celestial and terrestrial physics — 
which hold the strategic place in the whole movement — change is 
brought about, not by new observations or additional evidence in the 
first instance, but by transpositions that were taking place inside the 
minds of the scientists themselves. ... Of all forms of mental activity, 
the most difficult to induce even in the minds of the young, who may 
be presumed not to have lost their flexibility, is the art of handling the 
same bundle of data as before, but placing them in a new system of 
relations with one another by giving them a different framework, all 
of which virtually means putting on a different kind of thinking-cap 
for the moment. It is easy to teach anybody a new fact about Richelieu, 
but it needs light from heaven to enable a teacher to break the old 
framework in which the student has been accustomed to seeing his 
Richelieu/ 10 

Once more we are facing the stubborn powers of habit, and the anti- 
thesis of habit and originality. New facts alone do not make a new 
theory; and new facts alone do not destroy an outlived theory. In both 
cases it requires creative originality to achieve the task. The facts which 
proved that the planetary motions depended on the sun have been 
staring into the face of astronomers throughout the ages — but they 
preferred to look away. 

The Pathology of Thought 

I have discussed 'snowblindness' and faulty integrations on the 
individual level. In the evolution of the collective matrices of science, 
similar aberrations occur on an historic scale, and are transmitted from 
one generation to the next — sometimes over a number of centuries. 
Indeed, some of the most important discoveries consisted in the 



236 THE ACT OF CREATION 

elimination of psychological road-blocks— in uncovering what had 
always been there. 

The classic example of a mental road-block, extending over two 
millennia, is one to which I have repeatedly alluded before. If one had 
to sum up the history of scientific ideas about the universe in a single 
sentence, one could only say that up to the seventeenth century our 
vision was Aristotelian, after that Newtonian. It would, of course, be 
naive to blame the giant figure of the Stagyrite for crystallizing trends 
in Greek thought which were originated by others, and reflected the 
intellectual mood of Greece at the disastrous period before and im- 
mediately after the Macedonian conquest. The reasons why his absurd 
theory of physics acquired such a firm hold over medieval Europe I 
have discussed elsewhere; 10 " they do not enter into our present 
context. 

The central postulate of the theory was that a moving body will 
immediately revert to immobility when it ceases to be pushed or pulled 
along by a second body, its 'mover'. Now an ox-cart on a muddy road 
will indeed come to a halt when its movers, the oxen, are unyoked. But 
an arrow will fly through the air once the initial impulse has been 
imparted to it— whereas, according to Aristotelian physics, it should 
have dropped to earth the very instant it parted from the bow, its 
mover. The answer to this objection was that the initial motion of the 
arrow, while still on the bow, created a disturbance in the air, a kind of 
vortex, which now became the arrow's 'mover', and pulled it along its 
course. Not before the fourteenth century was the further objection 
raised that if the arrow (or spear, or catapulted stone) was pulled by an 
air-current, it could never fly against the wind. 

This inability to perceive that a moving body tends to persist in its 
course was the psychological road-block which prevented the emer- 
gence of a true science of physics from the fourth century B.C. to the 
seventeenth century A,D. Yet every soldier who threw a spear felt that 
the thing had a momentum of its own — and so, of course, did the 
victim whom it hit; and every traveller in a post-coach which came to 
an abrupt halt, had experienced to his sorrow that his motion con- 
tinued after the mover's had stopped. The experience, the bodily 'feel' 
of inertial momentum is as old as mankind— but it was prevented from 
becoming conscious and explicit knowledge by the mental block built 
into the collective matrix. Even Galileo saw only part of the truth: he 
thought that a moving body, left to itself in empty space, would persist 
not in straight, but in circular motion. Such are the difficulties of 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



237 



clearing away the man-made heaps of rubble under which some simple 
truth lies buried. 

The necessity for every moving body to be constantly accompanied 
and pushed along by a 'mover' also applied to the stars; it created a 
'universe in which unseen hands had to be in constant operation. 11 The 
planets had to be rolled along their orbits, like beer-barrels, by a host of 
angels; even Kepler needed a heavenly broomstick, wielded by the sun, 
to sweep them round their path. Yet here again, the knowledge of 
centrifugal force has always existed, ever since children swung stones 
round at the end of a string; and this knowledge had even been 
explicitly formulated in antiquity. In his treatise On the Face in the Disc 
of the Moon Plutarch, who took a great interest in science and particu- 
larly in astronomy, wrote that the moon was of solid stuff, like the 
earth; and that the reason why it did not fall down on the earth, in 
spite of its weight, was as follows: 

. . . The moon has a security against falling in her very motion and 
the swing of her revolutions, just as objects put in slings are prevented 
from falling by the circular whirl; for everything is carried along by the 
motion natural to it if it is not deflected by anything else. Thus the moon 
is not carried down by her weight because her natural tendency is 
frustrated by her revolution. 12 (my italics) 

The translation is by Heath, who remarks: 'This is practically 
Newton's first Law of Motion.' It is curious that this passage has 
aroused so little comment. 

Perhaps the most disastrous feature of the Aristotelian system was its 
denial that the whole universe was made out of the same basic stuff (as 
Parmenides and the Atomists had asserted before him) and to split the 
world into two parts, divided by a kind of metaphysical iron curtain. 
The 'sublunary' region (the earth and its vicinity) was made of four 
unstable elements, the sides of a fifth, permanent ether; the sublunary 
region was infected with the vice of change — an abominable slum where 
generation, corruption, and decay never stopped, whereas on the other 
side of the curtain fifty-five celestial intelligences were spinning round 
as many pure, crystalline spheres, carrying the planets and stars in their 
unchanging circular orbits. 

It was the most dramatic splitting operation the world had seen since 
Lucifer was expelled from heaven; and it was unavoidably followed by 
a series of divorces and remarriages between incompatible partners. 



2j8 THE ACT OF CREATION 

Celestial mechanics became dissociated from sublunary physics and 
married to theology when Aristotle's 'first mover' became identified 
with God, and his star-spinning spirits with the hierarchy of angels. 
Terrestrial physics, in its turn, was divorced from mathematics, and 
married to animism. The most striking fact about pre-Renaissance 
science is indeed its complete indifference to quantitative measurements 
and numerical relations — not to mention experiment and observation; 
and its obsession with ascribing animate powers to inanimate objects. 
Stones fell to earth because it was their natural home, as flames rose 
upward because their home was in the sky; and the stone accelerated its 
fall because it was hurrying home as horses hurry to their stable. All 
motion, all change, was due to a purposeful striving of objects to realize 
what was potentially inherent in their nature, to move 'from potency to 
act' — a principle derived by specious analogy from embryonic develop- 
ment. It took about three centuries (from Occam to Newton) to undo 
the tangled mess which these divorces and mesalliances had brought 
about. 

In the healthy evolution of a science, we observe a branching out of 
specialized, relatively autonomous lines of research; and a parallel 
process of confluences and integrations mediated by the discovery of 
universal principles underlying variety. But we also find pathological 
developments of a rather drastic and persistent kind in the history of 
scientific thought — collective mental blockages which keep apart what 
belongs together, and lead to the segregation of 'closed systems'. The 
healthy periods in the growth of a science remind one of the differentia- 
tion of structure and integration of function in organic development. 
In the unhealthy periods, on the other hand, we find dissociation instead 
of differentiation, and faulty integrations. 

Some of the latter were the result of shotgun-marriages, as it were — 
imposed from outside, by religious or political pressures. Medieval 
astronomy had to embrace theology, Soviet biology was wedded to a 
crude form of Lamarckism. The development of science cannot be 
isolated from its historic context, from the climate of a given age or 
civilization; it influences and is influenced by its philosophy, religion, 
art, social organization, economic needs. But scientific thinking 
nevertheless enjoys a considerable amount of autonomy; its tortuous 
progress is unpredictable, its victories and defeats are of its own making. 
The reason why Copernicus postponed the publication of his theory 
till the end of his life was not fear of the Catholic Church (which 
encouraged and protected him) but the fear of ridicule from his fellow 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



239 



astronomers. Galileos conflict with the Church could have probably 
been avoided if he had been endowed with less passion and more 
diplomacy; but long before that conflict started, he had incurred the 
implacable hostility of the orthodox Aristotelians who held key- 
positions at the Italian universities. Religious and political oppression 
play only an incidental part in the history of science; its erratic course 
and recurrent crises are caused by internal factors. 13 

One of the conspicuous handicaps is the conservatism of the scientific 
mind in its corporate aspect. The collective matrix of a science at a 
given time is determined by a kind of establishment, which includes 
universities, learned societies, and, more recendy, the editorial offices 
of technical journals. Like other establishments, they are consciously or 
unconsciously bent on preserving the status quo — partly because un- 
orthodox innovations are a threat to their authority, but also because 
of the deeper fear that their laboriously erected intellectual edifice 
might collapse under the impact. Corporate orthodoxy has been the 
curse of genius from Aristarchus to Galileo, to Harvey, Darwin, and 
Freud; throughout the centuries its phalanxes have sturdily defended 
habit against originality. The uses of hypnotism in dental surgery, 
child-birth, etc., are regarded as a modern discovery. In fact, Esdaile, 
who lived from 1808 to 1859, carried out three hundred major opera- 
tions under 'Mesmeric trance'; but since Mesmer had been declared an 
impostor, medical journals refused to print Esdaile's papers. In 1842 
Ward amputated a leg painlessly under hypnotic trance and made a 
Report to the Royal Medical and Chirurgical Society. The Society 
refused to believe him. One of its most eminent members argued that 
the patient had merely pretended not to feel the pain, and the note of 
the paper having been read was struck from the minutes of the 
Society. 

The martyrology of science mentions only a few conspicuous cases 
which ended in public tragedies. Robert Mayer, co-discoverer of the 
Principle of the Conservation of Energy, went insane because of lack 
of recognition for his work. So did Ignaz Semmelweiss, who dis- 
covered, in 1847, that the cause of childbed fever was infection of the 
patient with the 'cadaveric materiar which surgeons and students 
carried on their hands. As an assistant at the General Hospital in Vienna, 
Semmelweiss introduced the strict rule of washing hands in chlorinated 
lime water before entering the ward. Before this innovation, one out of 
every eight women in the ward had died of puerperal fever; immedi- 
ately afterwards mortality fell to one in thirty, and the next year to one 



240 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



in a hundred. Semmelweiss's reward was to be hounded out of Vienna 
by the medical profession—which was moved, apart from stupidity, by 
resentment of the suggestion that they might be carrying death on their 
hands. He went to Budapest, but made little headway with his doctrine, 
denounced his opponents as murderers, became raving mad, was put 
into a restraining jacket, and died in a mental hospital. 

Apart from a few lurid cases of this kind we have no record of the 
coundess lesser tragedies, no statistics on the numbers of lives wasted in 
frustration and despair, of discoveries which passed unnoticed. The 
history of science has its Pantheon of celebrated revolutionaries — and 
its catacombs, where the unsuccessful rebels lie, anonymous and 
forgotten. 

Limits of Confirmation 

From the days of Greece to the present that history echoes with the 
sound and fury of passionate controversies. This fact in itself is sufficient 
proof that the same 'bundle of data*, and even the same 'crucial experi- 
ment', can be interpreted in more than one way. 

To mention only a few of the more recent among these historic 
controversies: the cosmology of Tycho de Brahe explained the facts, as 
they were known at the time, just as well as the system of Copernicus. 
In the dispute between Galileo and the Jesuit Father Sarsi on the nature 
of comets we now know that both were wrong, and that Galileo was 
more wrong than his forgotten opponent. Newton upheld a corpus- 
culary, Huyghens a wave-theory of light. La certain types of experiment 
the evidence favoured Newton, in other types Huyghens; at present 
we tend to believe that both are true. Leibniz derided gravity and 
accused Newton of introducting 'occult qualities and rniracles' into 
science. The theories of Kekule and Van t HofF on the structure of 
organic molecules were denounced by leading authorities of the period 
as a 'tissue of fancies/ 14 Liebig and Wohler— who had synthesized 
urea from anorganic materials—were among the greatest chemists of 
the nineteenth century; but they poured scorn on those of their 
colleagues who maintained that the yeast which caused alcoholic 
fermentation consisted of living cellular organisms. They even went so 
far as to publish, in 1839, an elaborate skit in the Annalen der Chemie, in 
which yeast was described 'with a considerable degree of anatomical 
realism, as consisting of eggs which developed into minute atiimaU 



THE EVOLUTION OB IDEAS 



shaped like distilling apparatus. These creatures took in sugar as food 
and digested it into carbonic acid and alcohol, which were separately 
excreted.' 15 The great controversy on fermentation lasted nearly forty 
years, and overlapped with the even more passionate dispute on 
'spontaneous generation — the question whether living organisms 
could be created out of dead matter. In both Pasteur figured promin- 
endy; and in both controversies the philosophical preconceptions of 
'vitalists' opposed to 'mechanists* played a decisive part in designing 
and interpreting the experiments — most of which wre inconclusive 
and could be interpreted either way. 

I have compared the nineteenth century to a majestic river-delta, the 
great confluence o£ previously separate branches of knowledge. This 
was the reason for its optimism — and its hubris; the general convergence 
of the various sciences created the conviction that within the foreseeable 
future the whole world, including the mind of man, would be 'redu- 
cible" to a few basic mechanical laws. Yet as we enter our present 
century, we find that in spite of this great process of unification, 
virtually every main province of science is torn by even deeper 
controversies than before. 

Thus, for instance, the most exact of the exact sciences has been split, 
for the last twenty years, into two camps: those who assert (with Bohr, 
Heisenberg, von Neumann) that strict physical causality must be 
replaced by statistical probability because subatomic events are in- 
determinate and unpredictable; and those who assert (with Einstein, 
Planck, Bohm, and Vigier) that there is order hidden beneath the 
apparent disorder, governed by as yet undiscovered laws, because they 
'cannot believe that God plays with dice'. Another controversy 
opposes the upholders of the *big-bang theory', according to which the 
universe originated in the explosion of a single, densely packed mass 
some thirty thousand million years ago and has been expanding ever 
since — and the upholders of the 'steady-state theory*, according to 
which matter is continually being created in a stable cosmos. In genetics, 
the neo-Darwinian orthodoxy maintains that evolution is the result of 
chance mutations, against the neo-Lamarckian heretics, who maintain 
that evolution is not a dice-game either — that some of the improve- 
ments due to adaptive effort can be transmitted by heredity to succes- 
sive generations. In neuro-physiology, one school maintains that there 
is rigid localization of functions in the brain, another, that the brain 
works in a more flexible manner. In mathematics, 'mtrationists* are 
aligned against 'formalists'; in the medical profession, opinions are 



242 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



divided regarding the psychological or somatological origin of a great 
number of diseases; therapeutic methods vary accordingly, and each 
school is subdivided into factions. 

Some of these controversies were decided by cumulative evidence in 
favour of one of the competing theories. In other cases the contradiction 
between thesis and antithesis was resolved in a synthesis of a higher 
order. But what we call 'scientific evidence' can never confirm that a 
theory is true; it can only confirm that it is more true than another. 

I have repeatedly emphasized this point — not in order to run down 
science, but to run down the imaginary barrier which separates 'science' 
from 'art' in the contemporary mind. The main obstacle which 
prevents us from seeing that the two domains form a single continuum 
is the belief that the scientist, unlike the artist, is in a position to attain 
to 'objective truth* by submitting theories to experimental tests. In 
fact, as I have said before, experimental evidence can confirm certain 
expectations based on a theory, but it cannot confirm the theory itself. 
The astronomers of Babylon were able to make astonishingly precise 
predictions: they calculated the length of the year with a deviation of 
only o-ooi per cent from the correct value; their figures relating to 
the motions of sun and moon, which form a continuous record starting 
with the reign of Nabonasser 747 B.C., were the foundation on which 
the Ptolemaic, and later the Copernican, systems were built. Theirs 
was certainly an exact science, and it 'worked'; but that does not prove 
the truth of their theories, which asserted that the planets were gods 
whose motions had a direct influence on the health of men and the 
fortunes of states. Columbus put his theories to a rather remarkable 
experimental test; what did the evidence prove? He and his con- 
temporaries navigated with the aid of planetary tables, computed by 
astronomers who thought the planets ran on circles, knew nothing of 
gravity and elliptic orbits, yet the theory worked— though they had 
the wrong idea why it worked. Time and again new drugs against 
various diseases were tried in hospital wards, and improvement in the 
patients' condition was considered experimental evidence for the 
efikacity of the drug; until the use of dummy pills indicated that other 
explanations were equally valid. Eysenck has questioned the value of 
psychotherapy in general, by suggesting that the statistical evidence for 
successful cures should be reinterpreted in the light of the corresponding 
numbers of spontaneous recoveries of untreated patients. His conclu- 
sions may be quite wrong; but his method of argument has many 
honourable precedents in the history of science. To quote Polanyi: 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



243 



For many prehistoric centuries the theories embodied in magic and 
witchcraft appeared to be strikingly confirmed by events in the eyes 
of those who believed in magic and witchcraft. . . . The destruction 
of belief in witchcraft during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries 
was achieved in the face of an overwhelming, and still rapidly 
growing body of evidence for its reality. Those who denied that 
witches existed did not attempt to explain this evidence at all, but 
successfully urged that it be disregarded. Glanvill, who was one of 
the founders of the Royal Society, not unreasonably denounced 
this proposal as unscientific, on the ground of the professed empiri- 
cism of contemporary science. Some of the unexplained evidence for 
witchcraft was indeed buried for good, and only struggled painfully 
to light two centuries later when it was eventually recognized as the 
manifestation of hypnotic powers. 16 

It is generally thought that physical theories are less ambiguous than 
medical and psychological theories, and can be confirmed or refuted by 
harder and cleaner experimental tests. Speaking in relative terms, this 
is, of course, true; physics is much closer to the 'ultra-violet' than to the 
'infra-red' end of the continuous spectrum of the sciences and arts. But 
a last example will show on what shaky empirical evidence* a generally 
accepted theory can rest; and in this case I am talking of the cornerstone 
of modern physics, Einstein's Theory of Relativity. 

According to the story told in the textbooks, the initial impulse 
which set Einstein's mind working was a famous experiment carried 
out by Michelson and Morley in 1887. They measured the speed oflight 
and found, so we are told, that it was the same whether the light 
travelled in the direction of the earth or in the opposite direction; 
although in the first case it ought to have appeared slower, in the 
second faster, because in the first case the earth was 'catching up* with 
the light-ray, in the second was racing away from it. This unexpected 
result, so the story goes, convinced Einstein that it was nonsense to talk 
of the earth moving through space which was at rest, as a body moves 
through a stationary liquid (the ether); the 1 constancy of the speed of 
light proved that Newton's concept of an absolute frame of space, which 
allowed us to distinguish between 'motion and 'rest*, had to he dropped. 

Now this official account of the genesis of Relativity is not fact but 
fiction. In the first place, on Einstein's own testimony the Michelson- 
Morley experiment 'had no role in the foundation of the theory*. That 
foundation was laid on theoretical, indeed speculative, considerations. 



244 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



And in the second place, the famous experiment did not in fact confirm, 
but contradicted Einstein's theory. The speed of light was not at all the 
same in all directions. Light-signals sent 'ahead* along the earth's orbit 
travelled slower than signals 'left behind'. It is true that the difference 
amounted to only about one-fourth of the magnitude to be expected 
on the assumption that the earth was drifting through a stationary 
ether. But the 'ether-drift' still amounted to the respectable velocity of 
about five miles per second. The same results were obtained by D. C. 
Miller and his collaborators, who repeated the Michelson-Morley 
experiments, with more precise instruments, in a series of experiments 
extending over twenty-five years (1902 to 1926). The rest of the story 
is best told by quoting Polanyi again: 

The layman, taught to revere scientists for their absolute respect 
for the observed facts, and for the judiciously detached and purely 
provisional manner in which they hold scientific theories (always 
ready to abandon a theory at the sight of any contradictory evidence) 
might well have thought that, at Miller's announcement of this 
overwhelming evidence of a positive effect' in his presidential 
address to the American Physical Society on December 29th, 1925, 
his audience would have instandy abandoned the theory of relativity. 
Or, at the very least, that scientists — wont to look down from the 
pinnacle of their intellectual humility upon the rest of dogmatic 
mankind — might suspend judgement in this matter until Miller's 
results could be accounted for without impairing the theory of 
relativity. But no: by that time they had so well closed their minds 
to any suggestion which threatened the new rationality achieved by 
Einstein's world-picture, that it was almost impossible for them to 
think again in different terms. Little attention was paid to the 
experiments, the evidence being set aside in the hope that it would 
one day turn out to be wrong. 17 

So it may. Or it may not. Miller devoted his life to disproving 
Relativity— -and on face value, so far as experimental data are concerned, 
he succeeded.* A whole generation later, W. Kantor of the U.S. Navy 
Electronics Laboratory repeated once more the 'crucial experiment'. 
Again his instruments were far more accurate than Miller's, and again 
they seemed to confirm that the speed of light was not independent from 
the motion of the observer—as Einstein's theory demands. And yet the 
vast majority of physicists are convinced— and I think rightly so — that 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



24s 



Einstein's universe is superior to Newton's. Partly this trust is based on 
evidence less controversial than the 'crucial' experiments that I have 
mentioned; but mainly on the intuitive feeling that the whole picture 
'looks right', regardless of some ugly spots that will, with God's help, 
vanish some day. One of the most prominent among them, Max Born, 
who inclines to a positivistic philosophy, betrayed his true feelings, 
when he hailed the advent of Relativity because it made the universe of 
science 'more beautiful and grander'. 

Paul Dirac, undoubtedly the greatest living British physicist, was 
even more outspoken on the subject. He and my late friend Erwin 
Schrodinger shared the Nobel Prize in 1933 as founding fathers of 
quantum mechanics. In an article 17 * on the development of modern 
physics, Dirac related how Schrodinger discovered his famous wave 
equation of the electron. 'Schrodinger got his equation by pure thought, 
looking for some beautiful generalization . . . and not by keeping close 
to the experimental developments of the subject', Dirac remarks 
approvingly. He then continues to describe how Schrodinger, when he 
tried to apply his equation, 'got results that did not agree with experi- 
ment. The disagreement arose because at that time it was not known 
that the electron has a spin.' This was a great disappointment to 
Schrodinger, and induced him to publish, instead of his original 
formula, an imperfect (non-relativistic) approximation. Only later on, 
by taking the electron's spin into account, did he revert to his original 
equation. Dirac concludes: 

I think there is a moral to this story, namely that it is more 
important to have beauty in one's equations than to have them fit 
experiment. If Schrodinger had been more confident of his work, he 
could have published it some months earlier, and he could have 
published a more accurate equation ... It seems that if one is working 
from the point of view of getting beauty in one's equations, and if 
one has really a sound insight, one is on a sure line of progress. If 
there is not complete agreement between the results of one's work 
and experiment, one should not allow oneself to be too discouraged, 
because the discrepancy may well be due to minor features that are 
not properly taken into account and that will get cleared up with 
further developments of the theory . . . 



In other words, a physicist should not allow his subjective conviction 
that he is on the right track to be shaken by contrary experimental 



246 THE ACT OF CREATION 

data. And vice versa, its apparent confirmation by experimental data 
does not necessarily prove a theory to be right. There is a rather 
hideous trick used in modern quantum mechanics called the 'renorma- 
lization method*. Diracs comment on it is: 

I am inclined to suspect that the renormalization theory is some- 
thing that will not survive in the future, and that the remarkable 
agreement between its results and experiment should be looked on 
as a fluke . . . 

I think I have said enough to show that 'scientific evidence' is a rather 
elastic term, and that Verification' is always a relative affair. The criteria 
of truth differ from the criteria of beauty in that the former refer to 
cognitive, the latter to emotive processes; but neither of them are 
absolute. 'The evidence proves' is a statement which is supposed to 
confer on Science a privileged intimacy with truth which art can never 
hope to attain. But 'the evidence proves' that the statement in quotes is 
always based on an act of faith. To quote K. R. Popper: 

The old scientific ideal of episteme— -of absolutely certain, demon- 
strable knowledge — has proved to be an idol. The demand for 
scientific objectivity makes it inevitable that every scientific state- 
ment must remain tentative for ever. It may indeed be corroborated, 
but every corroboration is relative to other statements which, again, 
are tentative. Only in our subjective experiences of conviction, in 
our subjective faith, can we be 'absolutely certain'. 18 

Fashions in Science 

Controversy is the yeast which keeps science in lively fermentation. 
But its progress is also beset with pseudo-controversies which appear 
to reflect differences of opinion, whereas in reality they only reflect 
differences of emphasis on single aspects of a complex process at the 
expense of others. Nature and nurture are evidently complementary 
factors in shaping an individual's appearance and character; yet a whole 
library could be filled with the disputes between proponents of 'here- 
dity is all' and 'environment is all'. Quantitative measurements were 
virtually ignored in pre-Newtonian physics; today even psychology is 
obsessed with quantity, and presumes to measure human minds by 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



247 



LQ. ratings and character-parameters. Often a branch of science 
assumes a new look* because its pundits have put on, not a new type 
of thinking cap but a fashionable hat. We find in the history of science 
as many fashions, crazes, and 'schools' as in the history of literature or 
interior decoration. The Ionians loved discussing whether the basic 
stuff of the universe was water, air, or fire; the alchemists were hypno- 
tized by the properties of sulphur, salt, and mercury; the invention of 
the Ley den jar threw scientists all over the world into such excitement 
that to die by electric stroke appeared an enviable fate. In medicine, 
fads, fashions, and fancies chase one another tirelessly, from the barber's 
horror-shop to the serene citadels in Harley Street. They have always 
been an easy target 'for satire; the difficulty in this disturbed border- 
province is to distinguish between the quack who consciously deludes 
the patient, and the sincere fanatic who deludes himself into believing 
that one particular aspect, organ, or function represents the whole, and 
that a partial remedy is an all-cure. 

A more positive aspect of the changes of fashion is that its pendular 
motions from one extreme to another occasionally result in establishing 
a more balanced view. One of the remarkable achievements of Pasteur 
was that, having established against considerable opposition the germ- 
theory of disease and made the medical profession 'microbe-conscious', 
he changed the emphasis in his writings from 'figure* to 'background 9 , 
from the microbe itself to the environment in which the microbe 
operates. As Dubos puts it: 

Far from being hypnotized with the idea that micro-organisms are 
the only factors of importance in medicine, Pasteur knew that men 
as well as animals, in health or in disease, must always be considered 
as a whole and in relation to their environment hi all his public- 
cations ... he repeatedly stated the thesis — almost as an obsession — 
that the activities of micro-organisms can be controlled, not only by 
acting on them direcdy, but also by modifying the environment in 
which they operate. 19 

'Environment' to Pasteur meant the whole range of conditions from 
proper sanitation, through aseptic surgery, to the patient's bodily and 
mental state. Much of this has become a fashionable truism today, but 
it was not in the days of Victorian medicine; and even today the lesson 
has not sunk in sufficiently, otherwise the mass-production of 
'super-hygienic* food in sterilized wrappings would be recognized as 



24$ 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



detrimental to man's internal environment—by depriving it of the 
imm unizing effect of ingesting a healthy amount of muck and bugs. 

I have talked more about physics than the other sciences, because it is 
regarded—both by its practitioners and the awe-stricken lay public, as 
the paragon of objectivity. In the sciences of life the subjective, and 
indeed emotive factor, is of course much more in evidence. When it 
comes to psychology, fashion seems to be almost the dominant factor 
which determines into which channels the research efforts of thousands 
of hopeful graduates in the universities of the world will be directed. It 
seems doubtful whether the doctrines of the hostile schools of analytical 
psychotherapy differ as fundamentally as their practitioners believe, or 
mainly by accent and emphasis; and it is becoming increasingly obvious 
that the therapist's personality is a more decisive factor than the school 
to which he belongs. But even on the apparently firmer ground of 
Experimental Psychology and learning Theory, the history of the last 
fifty years shows a bewildering succession of changing fashions in 
experimental design, technical jargon, and field of interest. English 
associanism; the Wurzburg school with its emphasis on introspection; 
Watsonian Behaviourism which declared introspection a heresy; 
Gestalt-theory stressing holism and insight; Neo-Behaviourism in its 
more sophisticated guise — none of them can claim to represent a com- 
prehensive theory of the phenomenon Man — or the phenomenon Rat, 
Cat, Ape, for that matter. Rather it looks as if each school had focussed 
its gaze, or collective squint, on a single aspect or slice of human 
nature, designed its experiments and formulated its questions in such a 
way that other aspects never had a chance to enter the picture. If one 
goes on sowing cabbage seeds, one cannot expect them to grow into 
mimosas—but that hardly gives one a right to denounce belief in the 
existence of mimosas as a superstition; and if one puts a creature into a 
Skinner Box, it will behave as one expects a creature in a Skinner Box 
to behave — with certain quantitative variations which are gratdfyingly 
measurable, but still refer to behaviour in a Skinner Box. 



Boundaries of Science 

I have emphasized, at the risk of repetitiveness, the irrational factors 
in scientific thought, first in their positive aspect: the intuitive leap, the 
reader pour mtettx sauter, then in their negative aspects: snowblindness, 
closed systems, faulty integrations. 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



249 



These features are reflected, on a magnified scale, in the evolution of 
every science as a corporate body. Their histories refute the naive belief 
that progress in science is an orderly, rational affair, represented by a 
continuous curve which approaches the ultimate truth by ever closer 
approximations; or — as we are often told — that our wisdom increases 
in a cumulative manner, like the steady rise of the water-level in a 
reservoir. 

In reality progress is neither continuous nor cumulative in the strict 
sense. If it were continuous, there would be no 'revolutionary' dis- 
coveries, no discarding of discredited theories and sudden changes of 
direction — a continuous curve has no abrupt brakes, it is not a zig-zag 
line. 

Nor is progress cumulative in a simple and direct way. The walls of 
the reservoir — the frame of reference into which new data are poured — 
are periodically changing their shape: narrowing, expanding, curving 
this way or that; pipes are built to connect with other reservoirs of 
knowledge, while rusty connections are sealed off. Moreover, the 
reservoir is leaky and wasteful: gallons of knowledge are forgotten, 
discoveries 'stillborn or smothered at birth'.* 

It is also asserted that science moves in progressively closer approxi- 
mations to truth, like a curve approaching its asymptote, even though 
it will reach it only in infinity. But this statement is rather ambiguous 
and leads to the frequent confusion between progress in exactitude of 
observations and measurements, with progress in the explanatory power 
of theories— which is an altogether different affair. Tycho de Brahe's 
observations of the motions of the planets represent a definite advance 
in so far as precision is concerned. Yet his theory of the solar system 
was not an advance, but a retreat from Copernicus. Einstein's formula 
of gravity looks like a small adjustment to Newton's approximation, 
but it implies a radically different conception of the universe. 

The bubble chamber is a kind of aquarium window into the sub- 
atomic world. It provides us with photographs of the condensation 
trails, like jet trails in the sky, of what we take to be the elementary 
particles of matter: electrons, neutrons, mesons, muons, etc., of some 
forty different varieties. But the particles themselves can of course 
never be seen, their inferred lifespan often amounts to no more than 
a millionth of a millionth second, they ceaselessly transform them- 
selves into different kinds of particles, and the physicists ask us to re- 
nounce thinking of them in terms of identity, causality, tangibility, 
or shape — in a word, to renounce thinking hi intelligible terms, and 



250 



THE ACT OF CHEATION 



to confine it to mathematical symbols. The rapid, continuous increase 
in the precision and power of our methods for exploring and ex- 
ploiting nature is so impressive that we are apt to forget the discon- 
tinuity and periodic upheavals in the formation of explanatory 
theories. 

No doubt the modern scientist knows more than Archimedes; and 
no doubt the modern novelist has a wider range of experience than 
Homer, and more precise tools to analyse human thoughts and emo- 
tions. But neither of them arrived at their present station by the 
shortest way; and though both of them have solved many riddles and 
attained to important part-truths, neither of them is sure whether the 
present direction of lis zig-zag course leads him towards a 'closer 
approximation. Nor is the scientist in a much better position to as- 
certain the correctness of his course. He, too, must ultimately rely on 
his intuitions, and the interpretation which he puts on his bundle of 
data will remain open to controversy. 

In the symbolic year 1899 the foremost German biologist Ernst 
Haeckel published a best-selling book The Riddles of the Universe, 
which became the bible of my youth. Haeckel was die first propa- 
gandist of Darwin in Germany, and the first to draw up a geneological 
tree of the various orders of animals. Like Spencer and Huxley in 
England, he was a typical representative of the buoyant and arrogant 
optimism of the nineteenth century. His book enumerated seven 
Great Riddles of the Universe, of which six were 'definitely solved* — 
including the Structure of Matter and the Origin of Life; the seventh 
was man's experience of freedom of choice. However, this was not 
really a riddle but 'a pure dogma, based on an illusion and having no 
real existence , — so there were no more riddles left. Science was 'dizzy 
with success* — as Stalin has said in a famous speech celebrating the 
triumphs of rural collectivization on the eve of the great famine of 
1932. 

Other ages have been similarly dizzy with success, convinced that 
they stood on the doorstep of the Temple of Truth. The Pythagoreans 
believed it, before they stumbled into the 'Unspeakable Numbers' and 
the Temple vanished in the mist. Again, in the seventeenth century, 
intoxicated by the vista which the Scientific Revolution had opened 
up, most of its pioneers thought that it would take only one or 
possibly two generations until they wrested its last secret from nature. 
'Give me matter and motion, and I will construct the world', wrote 
Descartes. 'The particular phenomena of the arts and sciences are 



THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS 



251 



really but a handful,' wrote Francis Bacon, 'the invention of all causes 
and all sciences would be a labour of but a few years.* 

Within a generation after Haeckel had proclaimed that the Riddles 
of the Universe had been solved, nearly all the solutions turned out 
to be spurious. In 1925 Whitehead wrote that the physical theory of 
matter 'got into a state which is strongly suggestive of the epicycles 
of astronomy before Copernicus'; in the lifetime of the next genera- 
tion it became a welter of paradoxa, compared to which the universe 
of rotating crystal spheres had been a model of sanity. 

I have written elsewhere about the great vanishing act which accom- 
panied the process of unification in science. It started when Galileo 
discarded colour, sound, smell, and taste as illusions of the senses which 
could all be reduced to the 'primary qualities' of physics, to matter 
and motion. But one after another these 'ultimate and irreducible* 
entities vanished to the tune of the 'Ten Little Nigger Boys*. First the 
indivisible atom went up in fireworks, then the atomic nucleus, then 
the 'elementary particles' in the nucleus; matter evaporated in the 
physicists' hands, and its ultimate constituents joined electricity, mag- 
netism, and gravity as manifestations of excited states of 'fields' which 
could be described only in mathematical terms. Theoretical physics is 
no longer concerned with things, but with the mathematical relations 
between abstractions which are the residue of the vanished things. To 
quote Russell: 'Physics is mathematical not because we know so much 
about the physical world, but because we know so little; it is only its 
mathematical properties that we can discover/ 

For three centuries the reduction of qualities to quantities has been 
spectacularly successful, and it was reasonable to hope that within a 
generation or two the supreme synthesis which would enable us to 
reduce all phenomena in the physical world to a few basic mathe- 
matical formulae — something of the nature of the Unified Held 
Theory on which Einstein worked, unsuccessfully, throughout the 
second half of his life. It is still not unlikely that this hope was well 
founded, that in the foreseeable future subatomic physics will strike 
rock bottom as it were, and obtain the answers to the questions it has 
asked. But it is becoming increasingly evident that both the questions 
and the answers of contemporary physics are couched in an elusive 
symbol-language which has only a very indirect bearing on reality, 
and has lkde to offer to satisfy man's craving for glimpses of the ulti- 
mate truth. Eddington realized long ago that these symbols 'have as 
much resemblance to the real qualities of the material world ... as 



2$2 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



a telephone number has to a subscriber'. And two centuries before him, 
in the jubilant days which followed the unveiling of Newton's uni- 
verse, Swift, the passionate sceptic, had this prophetic intuition: 

He said, that new Systems of Nature were but new Fashions, which 
would vary in every Age; and even those who pretend to demon- 
strate them from Mathematical Principles, would flourish but a short 
Period of Time, and be out of Vogue when that was determined. 20 

Perhaps that saturation point is not far away, and perhaps science 
will then start asking a new type of question. One branch after another 
of chemistry, physics, and cosmology has merged in the majestic river 
as it approaches the estuary — to be swallowed up by the ocean, lose 
its identity, and evaporate into the clouds; the final act of the great 
vanishing process, and the beginning, one hopes, of a new cycle. It 
has been said that we know more and more about less and less. It 
seems that the more universal the laws' which we discover, the more 
elusive they become, and that the ultimate consummation of all rivers 
of knowledge is in the cloud of unknowing. 

Thus, contrary to appearances and beliefs, science, like poetry or 
architecture or painting, has its genres, 'movements', schools, theories 
which it pursues with increasing perfection until the level of saturation 
is reached where all is done and said — and then embarks on a new 
approach, based on a different type of curiosity, a different scale of 
values. Not only Newton, but Leonardo, Mozart, and Flaubert saw 
further because they too stood on the shoulders of giants; and Ein- 
stein's space is no closer to reality than Van Gogh's sky. The glory of 
science is not in a truth *more absolute' than the truth of Bach or 
Tolstoy, but in the act of creation itself. The scientist's discoveries 
impose his own order on chaos, as the composer or painter imposes 
his; an order that always refers to limited aspects of reality, and is 
biassed by the observer's frame of reference, which differs from period 
to period, as a Rembrandt nude differs from a nude by Manet. 

Summary 

The history of science shows recurrent cycles of differentiation and 
specialization foEowed by reintegrations on a higher level; from unity 
to variety to more generalized patterns of unity-in-variety. The 
process also has certain analogies with biological evolution — such as 



THE EVOLUTION OP IDEAS 



253 



wastefulness, sudden mutations, the struggle for survival between 
competing theories. 

The various phases in the historic cycle correspond to the character- 
istic stages of individual discovery: the periods of creative anarchy to 
the period of incubation; the emergence of the new synthesis to the 
bisociative act. It may emerge suddenly, sparked off by a single 
individual discovery; or gradually, as in die history of electro- 
magnetism, where a series of individual discoveries acted as 'links'. 
Each revolutionary historic advance has a constructive and a destructive 
aspect: the thaw of orthodox doctrines and the resulting fertile chaos 
correspond to the regressive phase of the individual reader-pour- 
mienx-sauter phenomenon. Lastly, the process of verification and 
elaboration of individual discoveries is reflected on the map of history 
as the consolidation of the new frontier — followed by the develop- 
ment of a new orthodoxy, a hardening of the collective matrix — until 
it gets blocked and the cycle starts again. 

The decisive phase in the historic cycle, the dawn of the new 
synthesis, appears as the confluence of previously separate branches of 
science, or a cross-fertihzation between different mental disciplines or 
experimental techniques. The collection of new empirical data is of 
essential importance, but both the collection and interpretation of the 
data are selective processes guided by theoretical considerations. The 
history of every science proves that observations and experiments 
which prima facie seem to contradict a theory do not necessarily lead 
to its abandonment; and vice versa, successful theories (such as the 
heliocentric system or Special Relativity) have been built on data which 
had been available for a long time by rearranging the mosaic of hard 
facts into a different pattern. I 

'Snowblindness', faulty integrations, and other forms of the indi- 
vidual pathology of thought, are reflected on a vasdy magnified scale 
in the history of science; and the power of habit over the individual 
mind is reflected in the conservatism of scientific bodies and schools — 
which has impeded progress for periods ranging from years to centuries. 

Thus the progress of science is neither continuous, nor cumulative 
in the strict sense. Its discoveries are often forgotten or ignored, and re- 
discovered later on. Its history echoes with controversies which prove 
that the same bundle of objective data* and even the same 'crucial 
experiment* can be interpreted in more than one way. No experi- 
mental test can provide the scientist with absolute certainty; and the 
difference in the verifiability' between various types of scientific and 



254 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



artistic statements is a matter of degree (see also below, Chap. XVII). 
Some scientific controversies are decided by cumulative weight of 
evidence; others are resolved by a synthesis embracing both competing 
theories; but still others are pseudo-controversies reflecting differences 
in emphasis and fashions of thought — and the latter are often as sub- 
jective and emotional as fashions in art. 

Lasdy, a distinction should be made between progress in the pre- 
cision of scientific statements and their explanatory power. The latter 
depends on the type of question the statement is meant to answer; and 
history shows that the questions change with the changing values in 
different periods and cultures. 

NOTES 

To p. 228. See Appendix I. 

To p. 230. Bronowski (1961), p.27. Cf. also: *The most fortunate moments 
in the history of knowledge occur when facts which have been as yet no more 
than special data are suddenly referred to other apparently distant facts, and thus 
appear in a. new light* (Wolfgang Kohler, 1940, p.89). 

To p. 234. The French theoretical astronomer, Leverrier, had predicted 
the existence of an eighth planet from disturbances in the motion of the seventh 
planet, Uranus. The planet was discovered by the German astronomer Galle on 
24 September 1846. 

To p. 244. In his Presidential Address to Section 1 of the British Association, 
Cambridge, 1938, C. G. Darwin said of D. C. Miller's experiments: 'We cannot 
see any reason to think that this work would be inferior to Michelson*s work, 
as he had at his disposal not only all the experience of Michelson's work, but also 
the very great technical development of the intervening period, but in fact he 
failed to verify the exact vanishing of the aether drift. What happened? Nobody 
doubted relativity. There must therefore be some unknown source of error 
which had upset Miller's work.' 

To p. 240), It took two thousand yean until Archimedes and Euclid were 
rediscovered. It took four hundred years until the Occamites' work on impetus 
was appreciated. In the hectic nineteenth century, it took thirty-five years until 
the significance of Mendel's work was recognized. In 1845 J. J. Waterston wrote 
a paper on the molecular theory of gases which partly anticipated Maxwell: "The 
referee of the Royal Society to whom the paper was submitted said: "The paper 
is nothing but nonsense," and the work lay in utter oblivion until exhumed 
forty-five years later. Waterston lived on disappointed and obscure for many 
years and then mysteriously disappeared leaving no sign. As Trotter remarks, this 
story must strike a chill upon anyone impatient for the advancement of know- 
ledge. Many discoveries must have thus been stillborn or smothered at birth. 
We know only those that survived* (Beveridge, op. cit., p. 108). 

There may be thousands of relevant bits of information lying dormant in 
hundreds of technical journals on dusty library shelves which, if remembered, 
would act as Open Sesames. 



XI 

SCIENCE AND EMOTION 
Three Character-Types 

Iet me revert for a moment to our starring point, the triptych of 
creative activities. 
In folklore and popular literature the Artist is traditionally rep- 
resented as an inspired dreamer — a solitary figure, eccentric, im- 
practical, unselfish, and quixotic. 

His opposite number is the earthy and cynical Jester — Falstaff or 
Sancho Panza; he spurns the dreamer, refuses to be taken in by any 
romantic nonsense, is wide-awake, quick to see his advantage and to 
get the better of his fellows. His weapons range from the bludgeon of 
peasant cunning to the rapier of irony; he always exercises his wits at 
the expense of others; he is aggressive and self-asserting. 

In between these antagonistic types once stood the Sage who com- 
bined the qualities of both: a sagacious dreamer, with his head in the 
clouds and his feet on the solid earth. But his modern incarnation, the 
Scientist, is no longer represented by a single figure in the waxworks 
of popular imagination; instead of one prototype, we had better 
compose three. 

The first is the Benevolent Magician, whose ancestry derives from 
the rain-making Shamans and the calendar-making Priest-Astronomers 
of Babylon. At the dawn of Greek science we find him assuming the 
semi-mythical figure of Pythagoras, the only mortal who could hear 
with ears of flesh the music made by the orbiting stars; and from there 
onward, every century created its own savant-shamans whom it could 
venerate — even throughout the Dark Ages of science. The first millen- 
nium was seen in by Sylvester II, the 'Magician Pope*, who reinstated 
the belief that the earth was round. The Jews had their Maimonides, 
the Arabs their Alkhazen, Christendom the Venerable Bede, before 
St, Thomas Aquinas and Albert the Great revived the study of nature. 

255 



2$6 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



From the Renaissance on there is an uninterrupted procession of 
magicians whose names were legends, admired and worshipped by 
a public which had only the vaguest notion of their achievements: 
Paracelsus, Tycho on his Sorcerer's Island, Galileo with his telescope, 
Newton who brought the Light, Franklin who tamed the thunder- 
bolt, Mesmer who cured by magnetism; Edison, Pasteur, Einstein, 
Freud. The popular image of the Magician has certain features in 
common with that of the Artist: both are unselfishly devoted to 
lofty tasks — which frequently overlapped in the uomo universale of the 
Renaissance. 

The second archetype is the 'Mad Professor' who, in contrast to the 
former, practises black instead of white magic for the sake of his own 
aggrandizement and power. Empedokles jumped into the crater of Etna 
to gain immortaHty; Paracelsus's rival, Agrippa, was allied to the devil 
in the shape of an enormous black poodle; the Anatomists were allied 
to body-snatchers for their sinister purposes. The alchemists distilled 
witches' brews; electric rays became a favourite delusion in persecu- 
tion manias; vivisection, and even compulsory vaccination, became 
symbols of the scientist's blasphemous presumption and cruelty. The 
Mad Professor — either a sadist or obsessed with power — looms large 
in popular fiction from Jules Verne's Captain Nemo and H. G. Wells' 
Dr. Moreau to Caligari, Frankenstein, and the monsters of the horror- 
comics. He is -a Mephistophelian character, endowed with caustic wit; 
he spouts sarcasm, a sinister jester plotting to commit some monstrous 
practical joke on humanity. His place in the waxworks is next to the 
malicious satirist's, as the Benevolent Magician's is next to the imagina- 
tive Artist's. 

The last of the three figures into which the popular image of the 
scientist has split occupies the centre space and is of relatively recent 
origin: the dry, dull, diligent, pedantic, uninspired, scholarly book- 
worm or laboratory worker. He is aloof and detached, not because he 
has outgrown passion but because he is devoid of temperament, desic- 
cated, and hard of hearing — yet peevish and petulant and jealous of 
anybody who dares to interfere with his crabbed little world. This 
imaginary type probably originates with the Schoolmen of the period 
of decline, whom Erasmus lampooned: 'They smother me beneath 
six hundred dogmas; they are surrounded with a bodyguard of 
definitions, conclusions, corrolaries, propositions explicit and proposi- 
tions implicit; they are looking in utter darkness for that which has no 
existence whatsoever.' 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



257 



Swift satirized the type in Gulliver in Laputa; then Goethe in his 
Famulus Wagner: Mit Eifer hab 1 ich mich der Studien bejlissen — Zwar 
weiss ich viel, dock mocht* ich alles wissen. 'Thanks to my diligeace, my 
wisdom is growing — If I hut persevere I shall he all-knowing/ His 
modern incarnations are the Herr Professor of German comedy, 
and the mummified dons of Anglo-Saxon fiction. At his worst, he 
incarnates the pathological aspects in the development of science: 
rigidity, orthodoxy, snowhlindness, divorce from reality. But the 
patience and dogged endurance of the infantrymen of science are as 
indispensable as the geniuses who form its spearhead. 'The progress of 
science', Schiller wrote, 'takes place through a few master-architects, or 
in any case through a number of guiding brains which constantly set all 
the industrious labourers at work for decades.' 1 That the industrious 
labourers tend to form trade unions with a closed-shop policy and 
restrictive practices, is an apparently unavoidable development. It is no 
less conspicuous in the history of the arts: the uninspired versifiers, the 
craftsmen of the novel and the stage, the mediocrities of academic 
painting and sculpture, they all hang on for dear life to the prevailing 
school and style which some genius initiated, and defend it with 
stubbornness and venom against heretic innovators. 

Thus we now have five figures facing us at our allegorical Madame 
Tussaud's. They are from left to right: the malicious Jester; the Mad 
Professor with his delusions of grandeur; the uninspired Pedant; the 
Benevolent Magician; and the Artist. 

At the moment only the three figures in the centre concern us. If 
we strip them of the gaudy adornments which folklore and fiction 
bestowed upon them, the figure of the Black Magician will turn out to 
be an archetypal symbol of the self-assertive element in the scientist's 
aspirations. In mythology, this element is represented by the Pro- 
methean quest for omnipotence and immortality; in science-fiction it 
is caricatured as a monstrous lusting for power; in actual life, it appears 
as the unavoidable component of competitiveness, jealousy, and self- 
righteousness in the scientist's complex motivational drive. 'Without 
ambition and without vanity', wrote the biologist Charles Nicolle, 
'no one would enter a profession so contrary to our natural appetites.' 2 
Freud was even more outspoken: 'I am not really a man of science, not 
an observer, not an experimenter, and not a thinker. I am by tempera- 
ment nothing but a conquistador . . . with the curiosity, the boldness, 
and the tenacity that belong to that type of person.' 3 
The unassuming figure of the Pedant in the centre of the waxworks 



258 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



is an indispensable stabilizing element; he acts as a restraining influence 
on the selfcasserting, vainglorious conquistadorial urges, but also as a 
sceptical critic of the inspired dreamer on his other side. 

This last figure, the White Magician, symbolizes the self-transcend- 
ing element in the scientist's motivational drive and emotional make- 
up; his humble immersion into the mysteries of nature, his quest for the 
harmony of the spheres, the origins of life, the equations of a unified 
field theory. The conquistadorial urge is derived from a sense of power, 
the participatory urge from a sense of oceanic wonder. 'Men were first 
led to the study of natural philosophy', wrote Aristode, 'as indeed they 
are today, by wonder.' 4 Maxwell's earliest memory was 'lying on the 
grass, looking at the sun, and wondering . Einstein struck the same chord 
when he wrote that whoever is devoid of the capacity to wonder, 
'whoever remains unmoved, whoever cannot contemplate or know 
the deep shudder of the soul in enchantment, might just as well be dead 
for he has already closed his eyes upon life'. 5 

This oceanic feeling of wonder is the common source of religious 
mysticism, of pure science and art for art's sake; it is their common 
denominator and emotional bond. 

Magic and Sublimation 

The creative scientist in actual life hardly resembles any of these 
single wax-figures — the Conquistador, the Pedant, or the inspired 
Dreamer; he contains ingredients of all of them in varying proportions, 
melted down as it were, and recast according to a personal formula. I 
have said already (p. 87 f.) that by calling science the 'neutral art' I did 
not mean that the scientist operates 'dispassionately' — as the cliche goes; 
but on the contrary, that he is motivated by a particular blend of 
passions into which both the self-asserting and participatory drives 
enter, but in a highly sublimated state, complementing each other. A 
modicum of ambition or vanity or financial need, or even aggression, 
is indispensable to the most 'disinterested' scientist or explorer— but the 
conquistadorial appetite must have undergone a great amount of 
refinement if it is to find its satisfaction in the publication of a paper, 
representing years of labour, in the columns of a technical journal. 
Except for the chosen few who attain popular fame, the vast majority 
of scientists spend their lifetime working in obscurity, and for paltry 
rewards. In his private life, the scientist can indulge his ego; but in his 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



259 



work, ambition and vanity are denied all but die most indirect and 
tortuous outlets, in conformity with the complex rules of the game. 
The compensation for this sacrifice is in the game itself— in that 
'enchantment of the soul' which makes interest disinterested, as it were. 

The sublimation of the self-assertive, aggressive-defensive impulses 
is easily understood, since we all have to go through this painful 
process, abdicating the tyrannic powers of infancy—including the 
primitive fantasies of omnipotence, from which the figure of the Black 
Magician is derived — and accepting the rules of the game of civilized 
society. But the self-transcending, participatory emotions are also 
subject to the process of sublimation, both in the history of the indivi- 
dual and in the evolution of cultures. One aspect of lie latter is the 
sublimation of magic into art; another, of magic into science. 

I have explained earlier on (p. 54 £) that the term 'self-transcending' 
or participatory* tendencies is meant to refer to those emotional states 
where the need is felt to behave as a part of some real or imaginary 
entity which transcends the boundaries of the individual self (whereas 
when governed by the self-assertive class of emotion, the ego is 
experienced as a self-contained whole and the ultimate value). Now 
ob\dously a person s character and pattern of behaviour is to a large 
extent dependent on the nature of that higher entity of which he feels 
himself to be a part. There is of course often a multitude of such 
entities, some forming a hierarchy (family, tribe, nation), others 
causing rival identifications; some are of the nature of social, others of 
spiritual or mystical bonds. It is with the latter that we are concerned; 
more precisely with the transition from one type of mystic partici- 
pation in a universe governed by sympathetic magic, to another type 
of mystic communion with a universe governed by a divine or 
natural order. That transformation was never completed; but even 
the partial transition which the Greeks achieved had a decisive in- 
fluence on the pattern of Western culture. At the risk of repetitiveness 
I must once more mention here the Pythagoreans, the chief engineers 
of that epoch-making change. I have spoken in more detail elsewhere 
of the inspired methods by which, in their religious order, they trans- 
formed the Orphic mystery cult into a religion which considered 
mathematical and astronomical studies as the main forms of divine 
worship and prayer. The physical intoxication which had accompanied 
the Bacchic rites was superseded by the mental intoxication derived 
from pkib-sopkia, the love of knowledge. It was one of the many key 
concepts they coined and which are still basic units in our verbal 



2<5o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



currency. The cliche about the 'mysteries of nature' originates in the 
revolutionary innovation of applying the word referring to the secret 
rites of the worshippers of Orpheus, to the devotions of stargazing. 
'Pure science* is another of their coinages; it signified not merely a 
contrast to the 'applied* sciences, hut also that the contemplation of the 
new mysteria was regarded as a means of purifying the soul by its 
immersion in the eternal. Finally, 'meorizing' comes from Theoria, 
again a word of Orphic origin, meaning a state of fervent contempla- 
tion and participation in the sacred rites (thea spectacle, theoris spectator, 
audience). Contemplation of the 'divine dance of numbers' which held 
both the secrets of music and of the celestial motions became the link 
in the mystic union between human thought and the anima mundu 
Its perfect symbol was the Harmony of the Spheres — the Pythagorean 
Scale, whose musical intervals corresponded to the intervals between- 
the planetary orbits; it went on reverberating through 'soft stillness 
and the night' right into the poetry of the Elizabethans, and into the 
astronomy of Kepler. 

It was indeed this sublimated form of Orphic mysticism which, 
through the Pythagorean revival in Renaissance Italy, inspired the 
Scientific Revolution. Galileo, Descartes, and Newton all regarded 
God as a kind of 'chief mathematician' of the Universe. 'Geometry 
existed before the Creation, is co-eternal with the mind of God, is 
God himself', 6 wrote Kepler; and the other giants echoed his convic- 
tion. The 'oceanic feeling' of religious mysticism had been distilled 
into differential equations; the mind of the anima mundi was reflected 
in the rainbow colours of the spectroscope, the ghostly spirals of 
distant galaxies, the harmonious patterns of iron-filings around a mag- 
net In all the 'great and generous minds', from Nicolas of Cusa down 
to Einstein, we find this feeling of awe and wonder, an intellectual 
ecstasy of distinctly religious flavour. Even those who professed to be 
devoid of it based their labours on an act of faith: the belief that there 
is a harmony of the spheres— that the universe is not a tale told by an 
idiot, but governed by hidden laws waiting to be discovered and 
uttered. 'The mystic believes in an unknown God, the thinker and 
scientist in an unknown order; it is hard to say which surpasses the 
other in nonrational devotion (L. L. Whyte) 7 In a similar vein, 
Butterfield wrote on the pioneers of the scientific revolution: 'The 
aspiration to demonstrate that the universe ran like a piece of clock- 
work . . . was itself initially a religious aspiration. It was felt that there 
would be something defective in Creation itself— something not quite 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



26l 



worthy of God — unless the whole system of the universe could be 
shown to be interlocking, so that it carried the patttern of reasonable- 
ness and orderliness. Kepler, inaugurating the scientist's quest for a 
mechanistic universe in the seventeenth century, is significant here — 
his mysticism, his music of the spheres, his rational deity demand a 
system which has the beauty of a piece of mathematics.' 8 

It is the axiomatic belief that the pointers on his ^ afc do not move 
at random, which makes the readings of his instruments meaningful 
to the scientist. Though Eddington may have been justified in saying 
that the dials, in the present state of physics, have no more bearing on 
reality than telephone numbers, this takes nothing away from the 
excitement of watching their motions. After all, to the worshipful 
lover even her telephone number acquires some of the magic attraction 
of the beloved. 

The sublimation of the self-transcending emotions has transformed 
'magic' into 'science'; but there is no hard-and-fast boundary between 
the two. Unconscious, pre-rational, 'magical' thinking enters both into 
the creative act and into the beliefs or superstitions of the scientist. 
As Dubos said, 'the alchemist never entirely ceased to live and function 
within the academician*. Not only Kepler's astronomy was derived 
from belief in the Holy Trinity and the Harmony of the Spheres*, most 
of the giants of science were similarly inspired by religious, mystical or 
transcendental beliefs. 

In Appendix II the reader will find this generalization exemplified 
by a series of short character-sketches, from Copernicus and Galileo 
to Franklin, Faraday, Maxwell, Darwin, and Pasteur. I shall close this 
section with three quotations by men who played decisive parts in 
shaping the scientific outlook of the twentieth century. The first is 
Louis Pasteur, who was born a Roman Catholic and remained one 
throughout his life. At the age of sixty he was elected a member of the 
Academie Francaise; the wdcorning speech on that ceremonial 
occasion was made, ironically, by that great and wise agnostic, Ernest 
Renan. In his reply Pasteur explained that although an inescapable 
conclusion of thinking, the notion of infinity is incomprehensible to 
human reason— indeed more incomprehensible than all the miracles of 
religion: 'I see everywhere in the world the inevitable expression of the 
concept of infinity. It establishes in the depths of our hearts a belief in 
the supernatural The idea of God is nothing more than one form of die 
idea of infinity. So long as the mystery of the infinite weighs on the 
human mind, so long will temples be raised to the cult of the infinite, 



262 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



whether God be called Brahmah, Allah, Jehovah or Jesus The 

Greeks understood the mysterious power of the hidden side of things. 
They bequeathed to us one of the most beautiful words in our lan- 
guage — the word enthusiasm'—e« theos—a god within. The grandeur 
of human actions is measured by the inspiration from which they 
spring. Happy is he who bears a god within — an ideal of beauty and 
who obeys it, an ideal of art, of science. All are lighted by reflection 
from the infinite/ 

The second quotation is from Einstein who, when questioned about 
his own religious views, described them as 'what in ordinary terms 
one would call pantheistic'. On another occasion he talked of 'cosmic 
religiousness': 

... I maintain that cosmic religiousness is the strongest and most 
noble driving force of scientific research. Only the man who can con- 
ceive the gigantic effort and above all the devotion, without which 
original scientific thought cannot succeed, can measure the strength 
of the feeling from which alone such work . . . can grow. What a deep 
belief in the intelligence of Creation and what longing for under- 
standing, even if only of a meagre reflection in the revealed intelligence 
of this world, must have flourished in Kepler and Newton, enabling 
them as lonely men to unravel over years of work the mechanism of 

celestial mechanics Only the man who devotes his life to such 

goals has a living conception of what inspired these men and gave them 
strength to remain steadfast in their aims in spite of countless failures. 
It is cosmic religiousness that bestows such strength. A contemporary 
has said, not unrightly, that the serious research scholar in our generally 
materialistic age is the only deeply religious human being. 9 

And ksdy here is Bertrand Russell, writing at the age of eighty- 
nine; 

I must, before I die, find some means of saying the essential thing 
which is in me, which I have not yet said, a thing which is neither 
love nor hate nor pity nor scorn but the very breath of life, shining 
and coming from afar, which will link into human life the immensity, 
the frightening, wondrous and implacable forces of the non- 
human. 10 



From the Pythagoreans onward, through the Renaissance to our 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



263 



times, the oceanic feeling, the sense of participation in the mystery of 
the infinite, was the principal inspiration of that winged and flat- 
footed creature, the scientist. 

The Boredom of Science 

We have seen earlier on (pp. 87-89) that the emotional reaction 
which follows the act of discovery is a complex one, reflecting the 
complexity of the motivational drive. There is the sudden explosion 
of tension, which has become redundant and must somehow be worked 
off in gestures or shouts of jubilation — an overflow-reaction continuous 
with laughter, but of a more individual character because derived from 
a more sublimated kind of emotion. Concurrent with it, there is pure 
intellectual delight, the peaceful catharsis of the self-transcending 
emotions. The first is derived from the fact that T made a discovery — 
the second from the fact that a discovery has been made, another 
glimpse of the truth revealed. 

Let me now turn from the creative person's emotional reactions to 
those of the audience, to the 'consumer's* point of view. Whether he 
listens to a joke, or reads a scientific work, or visits an art gallery, he 
is supposed to participate in the intellectual and emotional experiences 
of the producer — to relive or re-create them. The bond between 
them is the need for social communication. The consumer hopes that 
by being allowed to share the creator's vision he will gain a deeper 
and broader view of reality. The producer has an urge to share his own 
experience with others — to win accomplices to his malice, partners in 
understanding, resonance for his emotions. In order to succeed, how- 
ever, he must use appropriate techniques. In Chapter III (pp. 82-86) I 
have discussed certain criteria by which to judge the impact of comic 
inventions — originality, emphasis, and economy. Are these criteria of 
any value when applied to scientific discovery? 

The importance of originality is self-evident. Selective emphasis on 
one particular aspect of reality, with its concommitant exaggerations 
and simplifications is, as we saw, the essence of model-making, and 
plays almost as great a part in the changing fashions and 'schools' in 
science as in art. Economy enters in various ways — from Occam's 
razor and the satisfaction derived from an 'elegant* solution to various 
techniques of enticing the audience in the lecture-room into an 
imaginative, re-creative effort. 



264 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



It is generally supposed that in this respect the creative scientist and 
his audience are at a disadvantage. In contrast to the artist, the scientist 
is not supposed to appeal to emotions, and the student of science not 
to be guided by them. But we have seen that the equation of science 
with logic and reason, of art with intuition and emotion, is a blatant 
popular fallacy. No discovery has even been made by logical deduction; 
no work of art produced without calculating craftsmanship; the emotive 
games of the unconscious enter into both. 

The aesthetic satisfaction derived from an elegant mathematical 
demonstration, a cosmological theory, a map of the human brain, 
or an ingenious chess problem, may equal that of any artistic ex- 
perience — given a certain connoisseurship. But connoisseurship is 
equally required for the true appreciation of any but the most vulgar 
forms of art; and particularly for ancient, alien, and 'modern' art. 
However, the absurd division of our society into 'two cultures' pro- 
duced the paradoxical phenomenon that the average educated person 
will be reluctant to admit that a work of art is beyond the level of his 
comprehension; but he will in the same breath and with a certain pride 
confess his complete ignorance of the principles which make his radio 
work, the forces which make the stars go round, the factors which 
determine the heredity of his children, and the location of his own 
viscera and glands. 

One of the consequences of this attitude is that he utilizes the products 
of science and technology in a purely possessive, exploitive manner 
without comprehension or feeling. His relationship to the objects of 
his daily use, the tap which supplies his bath, the pipes which keep 
him warm, the switch which turns on the light — in a word, to the 
environment in which he lives, is impersonal and possessive — like the 
capitalist's attitude to his bank account, not the art collector's to his 
treasures which he cherishes because he 'understands' them, because he 
has a participatory relationship to them. Modern man lives isolated in 
his artificial environment, not because the artificial is evil as such, but 
because of his lack of comprehension of the forces which make it 
work—of the principles which relate his gadgets to the forces of nature, 
to the universal order. It is not central heating which makes his exis- 
tence 'unnatural*, but his refusal to take an interest in the principles 
behind it. By being entirely dependent on science, yet closing his mind 
to it, he leads the life of an urban barbarian. 

The historical causes which led to the split between the two cultures 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



26s 



are outside the scope of this book; but I must mention one specific 
factor which is largely responsible for turning science into a bore, and 
providing the humanist with an excuse for turning his back on it. It 
is the academic cant, of relatively recent origin, that a self-respecting 
scientist must be a bore, that the more dehydrated the style of his 
writing, and the more technical the jargon he uses, the more respect he 
will command. I repeat, this is a recent fashion, less than a century old, 
but its effect is devastating. The pre-Socratics frequently wrote their 
treatises in verse; the ancient Peruvian language had a single word — 
hamavec — for both poet and inventor. Galileo's Dialogues and polemical 
writings were literary masterpieces which had a lasting influence on 
the development of Italian didactic prose; Kepler's New Astronomy is 
a baroque tale of suspense; Vesalius' Anatomy was illustrated by 
a pupil of Titian. Even the abstract symbol language of the mathe- 
maticians lent itself to works of art. As the great Boltzmann wrote: 
'A mathematician will recognize Cauchy, Gauss, Jacobi, or Helm- 
holtz, after reading a few pages, just as musicians recognize, from the 
first few bars, Mozart, Beethoven, or Schubert/ And Jeans compared 
Maxwell's physics with an enchanted fairyland where no one knew 
what was coming next. 

I have given samples of Pasteur*s and Poincare's style; Franklin was 
an accomplished stylist; Maxwell wrote commendably funny,* and 
Erasmus Darwin unintentionally funny verse; as for William James, I 
must confess that I find his style far more enjoyable than his brother 
Henry's. In our present century Eddington, Jeans, Freud, Kretschmer, 
Whitehead, Russell, Schrodinger, to mention only a few, gave con- 
vincing proof that works on science can at the same time be works of 
literary art. (One could also quote works by literary and art critics as 
pedantic and desiccated as papers in a technical journal for applied 
chemistry.) Needless to say, technical communications addressed to 
specialists must employ technical language; but even here the over- 
loading with jargon, the tortuous and cramped style, are largely a 
matter of conforming to fashion. 

The same inhuman— in fact anti-humanistic — trend pervades the 
climate in which science is taught, the classrooms and the textbooks. 
To derive pleasure from the art of discovery, as from the other arts, 
the consumer— in this case the student— must be made to re-live, to 
some extent, the creative process. In other words, he must be induced, 
with proper aid and guidance, to make some of the fundamental dis- 
coveries of science by himself) to experience in his own mind some of 



266 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



those flashes of insight which have lightened its path. This means that 
the history of science ought to be made an essential part of the curricu- 
lum, that science should be represented in its evolutionary context— 
and not as a Minvera born fully armed. It further means that the 
paradoxes, the 'blocked matrices' which confronted Archimedes, 
Copernicus, Galileo, Newton, Harvey, Darwin, Einstein should be 
reconstructed in their historical setting and presented in the form of 
riddles — with appropriate hints — to eager young minds. The most 
productive form of learning is problem-solving (Book Two, XIII- 
XIX). The traditional method of confronting the student not with the 
problem but with the finished solution, means depriving him of all 
excitement, to shut off the creative impulse, to reduce the adventure of 
mankind to a dusty heap of theorems. 

Art is a form of communication which aims at eliciting a re-creative 
echo. Education should be regarded as an art, and use the appropriate 
techniques of art to call forth that echo. The novice, who has gone 
through some of the main stages in the evolution of the race during his 
pre-natal development, and of the evolution from savage to civilized 
society by the time he reaches adolescence, should then be made to 
continue his curriculum by re-capitulating some of the decisive episodes, 
impasses, and turning points on the road to the conquest of knowledge. 
Our textbooks and methods of teaching reflect a static, pre-evolu- 
tionary concept of the world. For man cannot inherit the past; he has 
to re-create it. 



Summary 

The scientist's motivational drive is a blend of passions in which both 
the self-asserting and self-transcending tendencies participate — sym- 
bolized by the Mad Professor and the Benevolent Magician of folklore. 
It is, however, a blend in which both tendencies are sublimated and 
balance each other. This development is already foreshadowed in the 
exploratory behaviour of clever animals. "When Kohler's chimpanzee 
Sultan discovered, after many unsuccessful efforts, that he could rake 
the banana into the cage by fitting two short hollow sticks into each 
other, his motivation was obviously to get at the banana. But his new 
discovery 'pleased him so immensely* that he kept repeating the trick 
and forgot to eat the banana (for similar observations, see Book Two, 
VHE), If Archimedes was originally motivated by the desire to obtain 



SCIENCE AND EMOTION 



2<57 



money or favours from the tyrant of Syracuse, his jubilant shout was 
certainly not due to anticipation of the reward. 

Ambition, greed, vanity can enter the service of creativity only 
through indirect channels; and the self-transcending emotions must 
undergo a similar process of sublimation from mystic immersion in 
the harmony of the spheres to the scrupulous attention paid to eight 
minutes arc. The process is reflected in the gradual transformation of 
magic into science. 

The creative achievements of the scientist lack the 'audience appeal* 
of the artist's for several reasons briefly mentioned— technical jargon, 
antiquated teaching methods, cultural prejudice. The boredom created 
by these factors has accentuated the artificial frontiers between con- 
tinuous domains of creativity. 

NOTE 

To page 2651 See Appendix II, p, 691. 



PART THREE 



A. THE PARTICIPATORY EMOTIONS 



XII 

THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 

Laughter and Weeping 

The classic responses to comedy and tragedy are laughter and 
weeping. Both are overflow channels for the disposal of 
emotions; luxury reflexes without apparent utility. This much 
they have in common; in other respects they are direct opposites. 

There is a vast literature on the psychology of laughter, but hardly 
any on the psychology of weeping.* The theory of the comic which I 
have proposed, however controversial, can at least be judged in the 
light of earlier theories on similar or opposite lines; where weeping is 
concerned we are on virgin territory. This indifference towards the 
manifestation of emotions in weeping (which is after all neither an 
uncommon nor a trivial phenomenon) is in itself symptomatic of the 
contemporary trend in psychology — about which later. 

Weeping and crying confront us with an even more confusing variety 
of expressions than laughter. There are variations in intensity; in mood; 
in spontaneity. The bawling of a spoilt child, the contrived sobs of 
public or private stagecraft are secondary derivatives which distort 
the original pattern; cultural restraints and social infection are further 
superimpositions on it. We must disregard these adventitious elements 
and concentrate on spontaneous weeping in its pure form, as an auto- 
matic 'reflex* (see pp. 28-29). 

The first step is to distinguish between weeping and crying — it is a 
peculiarity of the English language to treat them as synonyms. Weeping 
has two basic reflex-characteristics which are found in all its varieties: 
the overflow of the tear-glands and a specific form of breathing. These 
vary in intensity from a mere moistening of the eye and 'catching one's 
breath* (or feeling *a lump in the throat') to a profusion of tears 
accompanied by convulsive sobbing; just as laughter varies in intensity 
from smiling to convulsions. Crying, on the other hand, is the emitting 

271 



272 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



of sounds signalling distress, protest, or some other emotion. It may be 
combined with, or alternate with, weeping. Frequently when a child, 
or a depressed patient, is said to be crying his head off* his eyes are in 
fact dry: he is not weeping. On the other hand, when your char-lady 
has a 'good cry' at the movies, she isn't crying at all but weeping. 
Crying is a form of communication (even if the audience is only 
imagined); weeping is not. 

Let me now compare the external manifestations — bodily changes — 
in weeping and in laughter. In weeping, the eyes are 'blinded* by 
tears: they lose their focus and lustre. The laugher's eyes sparkle, the 
corners are wrinkled, but brow and cheeks are taut and smooth, which 
lends the face an expression of radiance; the lips are parted, the corners 
lifted. In weeping, the features crinkle and crumple; even when 
weeping for joy or in aesthetic rapture, the transfigured face reflects 
a serene languidness. 

The breathing pattern in weeping is a series of short, deep, gasping 
inspirations, i.e. sobs, followed by long, sighing expirations, with the 
glottis partially closed — the lump in the throat. This is the exact 
opposite of the breathing pattern of laughter with its bursts of ex- 
piratory puffs — sobs in reverse, followed by long, deep intakes — re- 
versed sighs. A prolonged, violent fit of laughter, however, may pro- 
duce the sobbing type of respiration as an after-effect — a phenomenon 
which strengthens the hypothesis (see below) that laughter and crying 
are mediated by rival branches of the autonomous nervous system — 
the first being sympathicotonic, the second vagotonic. 

The third contrast is between bodily postures and motions. The 
person who laughs tends to throw his head back by a vigorous con- 
traction of the elevators in the neck; the person who weeps 'lets the 
head droop' (into the hands, on the table, or on somebody's shoulder). 
Laughter contracts the muscles and throws the body into violent 
motion— banging the table or slapping one's knees; in weeping, the 
muscles go flabby, the shoulders slump forward, the whole posture 
reflects a 'breaking down', a 'letting go'. 

In the fourth place, vocalization in laughter — roaring, giggling, 
chuckling, etc. — is expressive of joie de vivre with aggressive overtones; 
but if weeping is accompanied by crying, the sounds express lament, 
appeals for sympathy. 

finally, in laughter tension is suddenly exploded, emotion debunked; 
In weeping it is drained away in a gradual process which does not break 
the continuity of mood; there is no disowning of emotion, thought and 



THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 



273 



sentiment remain united to the end. Moreover, the gradual relief in 
weeping does not prevent the simultaneous generation of more emo- 
tion of the same type, so that the influx may balance the overflow, 
and relief is incomplete, or not even experienced as such. 

Why do we Weep? 

Let me discuss a few typical situations which may cause the shedding 
of tears. 

A. Raptness. Listening to the organ in a cathedral, looking at a 
majestic landscape from the top of a mountain, observing an infant 
hesitantly returning a smile, being in love — any of these experiences 
may cause a welling-up of emotions, a moistening or overflowing of 
the eyes, while the body is becalmed and drained of its tensions. A few 
steps higher on the intensity-scale, and the T seems no longer to exist, 
to dissolve in the experience like a grain of salt in water; awareness 
becomes de-personalized and expands into 'the oceanic feeling of 
limitless extension and oneness with the universe'.* 

Here, then, we see the self-transcending emotions displayed in their 
purest form. Once you start fondling the smiling baby and making a 
fuss of it, an active, possessive element enters into the situation and the 
spell is broken. The purely self-transcending emotions do not tend towards 
action, but towards quiescence, tranquillity, and catharsis. Respiration and 
pulse-rate are slowed down, muscle-tone is lowered; 'entrancement' 
is a step towards the trance-like states induced by the contemplative 
techniques of Eastern mysticism and by certain drugs. The experience 
of 'the blending of the finite with the infinite' can become so intense 
that it evokes Faust's prayer: O Augenblick verweile — let this moment 
last for eternity, let me die. But there is nothing morbid in this; it 
is a yearning for an even more complete communion, the ultimate 
catharsis or samadhu 

The reason for their passive, quietistic nature is that the self-trans- 
cending emotions cannot be consummated by any specific voluntary action. 
You cannot take the mountain panorama home with you; the surest 
method to break the charm is clicking your camera. You cannot merge 
with the infinite or dissolve in the universe by any exertion of the 
body; and even in the most sd&ess forms of love and communion each 
individual remains an island. To be 'overwhelmed' by love, wonder, 
devotion, 'enraptured' by a smile, 'entranced* by beauty—each verb 



274 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



expresses a passive state, a surrender; the surplus of emotion cannot be 
worked off in action— it can be consummated only in internal, visceral 
and glandular, processes. 

These observations are again in keeping with the character of the 
two divisions of the autonomous nervous system. We have seen that 
the self-assertive emotions operate through the powerful adrenal- 
sympathico system which galvanizes the body into action under the 
stress of hunger, pain, rage, and fear. The parasympathetic division, 
on the other hand, never goes into action as a compact unit; it does not 
dispose of a powerful pep-hormone like adrenalin, acting direcdy on 
the body as a whole. The sympathetic division has been compared to 
the pedals of a piano, which affect all the notes sounded; the parasym- 
pathetic to the separate keys which act locally on various organs. 
In the main, its function is to counteract and to complement sympathico- 
adrenal excitation: to lower blood-pressure and pulse-rate, neutralize 
excesses of blood-sugar and acidity, to facilitate digestion and the dis- 
posal of body-wastes, to activate the flow of tears, etc. In other words, 
the general action of the para-sympathetic system is inward-directed, 
calming, and cathartic. All this, and other arguments of a more technical 
nature, point to the correlation of the participatory emotions with the 
parasympathetic system.* 

B. Mourning. A woman is notified of the sudden death ofher husband. 
At first she is stunned, unable to believe the news; then she finds some 
relief in tears. 

Again, it is a situation in which nothing purposeful can be done, 
which does not beget action, but passive surrender — 'giving in to 
grief*. And, again, the emotion originates in the experience of 'belong- 
ing to', 'belonging together, of a communion which transcends the 
boundaries of the self. Resentment, guilt, unconscious gratification, 
may, of course, enter into the widow's mixed feelings, but we are 
concerned at the moment only with her experience of identification 
and belonging. That experience, and the emotions generated by it, 
have not come to an end with the husband's death; on the contrary, 
they have at the same time become more intense and frustrated. The 
overflow of tears is insufficient to relieve her from this surplus of 
emotions; she weeps 'in grief, whereas the euphoric experiences of 
the previous section caused 'weeping in joy'. 

But the difference is in fact a matter of degrees. The moist eyes in 
the transfigured face of the young mother also reflect an emotion which 



THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 



275 



cannot be completely consummated, lived out; the urge to transcend 
the self's boundaries, to break out of its insulation always carries a 
certain amount of frustration. Saints and mystics spend their lives trying 
to escape the prison of the flesh; Hemingway, who was not a saint, 
wrote of the 'heart-breaking profile' of his young Venetian contessa; 
and to be overwhelmed by beauty may indeed be as 'heart-breaking' 
as a widow's tears sweetened by self-pity. A long, enforced separation 
may be as painful as a final one; and there are cases of mourning where 
worship of the dead partner, with or without hope for a reunion in 
after-life, creates a more harmonious, if imaginary, communion than 
the actual partnership ever did. 

These continuous transitions between * weeping in joy* and weeping 
in sorrow' reflect the relative nature of 'pleasure' and 'unpleasure* 
(Unlust, disphoria, as distinct from physical pain). Emotions have 
been called overheated drives'. A drive becomes overheated* when it 
has no immediate outlet; or when its intensity is so increased that the 
normal outlets are insufficient; or for both reasons. A moderate amount 
of overheating may be experienced as a pleasurable arousal, thrill, 
excitement, or appetite—while anticipating (or imagining) the con- 
summatory act. Even physical discomfort and pain are readily tolera- 
ted (for instance, in mounts-climbing or trout-fishing on an icy 
morning) in the pleasurable anticipation of the reward. But when the 
'overheating' exceeds a critical level it is experienced as tension, stress, 
frustration, suffering. However, the pleasure-unpleasure tone is deter- 
mined not only by the intensity of emotive pressure; it also depends on 
whether the pressure is increasing or decreasing. Intense frustration 
changes into incipient relief the moment the consummatory action 
has started — or has merely come into sight. Decrease of tension is 
pleasurable— up to a point If the water-level, so to speak, falls below a 
critical point, there is a sensation of drying-up, of boredom and rest- 
lessness. At this stage increases of emotion are induced by various 
methods of seeking out thrills— from wild-game hunting to horror 
comics and other forms of what one might call 'emotional window- 
shopping': the vicarious satisfactions derived from reading the social 
gossip columns or watching a strip-tease. In these cases the pleasurable 
experience is derived not from anticipating, but from imagining the 
reward; and the satisfaction obtained— such as it is — consists in the 
'internal consummation' of those components in the complex drive 
which can be lived out in fantasy. 

Thus pleasure-unpleasure form a continuous scale of 'feeling-tones' 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



which accompany emotion: the former indicating the progress (real, 
anticipated, or imagined) of a drive towards its consummation, the 
latter indicating its frustration. 

This leads us to a quasi three-dimensional theory of emotions 
(which sounds involved, but is probably still a woeful over-simpli- 
fication). In the first place, we must obviously differentiate between the 
various emotions according to the nature of the drive, originating in 
various physiological, social, or 'psychogenic' 1 needs and urges — 
hunger, sex, protection of ofBpring, curiosity (the 'exploratory drive'), 
conviviality, etc. To use a coarse but comfortable analogy, let each of 
these be represented by a different tap in a saloon-bar, which is turned 
on as the demand arises, each serving a beverage with a different flavour. 
In the second place, we have the pleasure-unpleasure scale, correspond- 
ing to the pressure in the tap — whether the liquid flows smoothly, or 
gurgles and splutters because of air-locks or excess pressure. In the 
third place, we have the polarity between the self-assertive and par- 
ticipatory tendencies which enter into each emotion (for instance, 
possessiveness versus identification in maternal love); this could be rep- 
resented by the relative proportion of alcohol and water in the liquid. 
We can thus distinguish between three variables or 'parameters' in 
every emotional experience: 'flavour ' (hunger, love, curiosity); 
pressure', pleasant or unpleasant; and 'alcohol-content': toxic, i.e. 
aggressive-defensive, or soothing and cathartic. 

C. Relief A woman whose son has been reported by the War Office 
as missing suddenly sees him walking into her room, safe and sound. 
Again the first reaction is shock and rigidity; then she flings herself 
into his arms, alternately laughing and weeping. 

Obviously there are two processes involved here. The first is the 
sudden, dramatic relief from anxiety; the other an overwhelming joy, 
love, tenderness. Some writers on the subject are apt to confuse these 
two reactions — to regard all joyous emotion as due to relief from 
anxious tension. But clearly a tender reaction would be expected in 
any case from the mother on her son's return — even if he were merely 
returning from a day at school, and there had been no previous 
anxiety. Vice versa, relief from anxiety in itself, though always 
pleasant, does not create tender feelings overflowing in tears. What 
happened in the present case is that the agony the woman endured had 
increased the intensity of her yearning and love; and that relief from 
anxiety had increased out of all proportion the gratification she 



THE LOGIC OP THE MOIST EYE 



277 



would have felt on his return after an absence under normal circum- 
stances. 

Let me be a little more explicit— for the situation has, as we shall 
see, a direct bearing on the emotional reactions induced by works of 
dramatic art. The mother's sudden relief from anxiety could be ver- 
balized as 'thank God you are not dead'. Up to that moment she had 
tried to control her fears, to banish from consciousness the terrible 
images of what may have been happening to her boy. Now she can 
let herself go, allow her emotions a free outlet. Hence the manic dis- 
play of hugging, bustling, laughing, calling in the neighbours, and 
upsetting the tea kettle: she is working off the adrenalin of all that 
pent-up and suddenly released anxiety. But in the middle of these 
hectic activities there are moments when she glances at the embarrassed 
prodigal with a kind of incredulous, rapt expression and her eyes again 
overflow with soothing, peaceful tears. The alternation and over- 
lapping of the two patterns — one eruptive and agitated, the other 
gradual and cathartic — indicate the now familiar two processes and 
the nature of the emotions acted out. 

These become even more evident in exclamations such as 'How silly 
of me to cry', followed by more bustling and merriment. The unex- 
pected return of the boy was like a the 'bolt out of the blue* which cut 
short the tense narrative of her anxious fantasies; the tension has sud- 
denly become redundant, and is disowned by reason. At other moments 
she is still unable 'to believe her eyes' and emotion wells up again. This 
may even include some unconscious resentment against the cause of so 
much needless worry, who stands in her room, sunburnt and grinning, 
unaware of the suffering he has caused: "What a fool I have been to 
worry so much* may be translated as 'What a fool you have made of me*. 

'Laughing through one's tears' is caused by quickly oscillating mental 
states, where reason and emotion are alternately united and dissociated. 
A sudden shock which demands a major emotional readjustment is 
often followed by such oscilatory phases in which the subject alter- 
nately believes and disbelieves her eyes, until a full grasp of reality is 
reached on all levels. If instead of the happy ending, there had been a 
tragic one— a telegram informing the woman of her boy's death— then, 
instead of disbelieving her eyes, she would have been tempted to dis- 
believe the news; and while the happy mother behaves at moments as 
if the boy were still in danger, the bereaved mother may behave at 
times as if he were still alive. In the former case, the successive flashes of 
reality which disrupt the web of illusion bring happy relief; in the 



278 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



latter, each flash brings renewed despair. A person with psychotic 
dispositions may, however, cling to the illusion, and it will be the 
matrix of reality which disintegrates instead. The 'hollow' laughter in 
certain forms of insanity seems to echo the effort of reversing the pro- 
cess of adjustment— the effort of going mad in the teeth of a world that 
is sane. 

In the milder forms of paranoia induced by the stage and screen, 
the oscillations between illusion and reality are deliberately created and 
prolonged. The cathartic effect of the antique mysteries and of the 
modern drama alike are derived from man's unique faculty of believ- 
ing and disbelieving his eyes in the same blink. 

D. When a woman weeps in sympathy with another persons sorrow 
(or joy), she partially identifies herself with that person by an act of 
projection, introjecrion, or empathy— whatever you like to call it. The 
same is true when the 'other person 9 is a heroine on the screen or in the 
pages of a novel. But it is essential to distinguish here between two 
emotional processes— although they are experienced simultaneously 
and mixed together. 

The first is the act of identification itself— the fact that the subject 
has for the moment more or less forgotten her own existence and par- 
ticipates in the existence of another, at another place and time. This in 
itself is a self-transcending, gratifying and 'ennobling' experience for 
the simple reason that while it lasts, the subject, Mrs. Smith, is pre- 
vented from thinking of her own anxieties, ambitions, and grudges 
against Mr. Smith. In other words, the act of identification tem- 
porarily inhibits the self-asserting tendencies. 

The second process is mediated by the first: the act of identification 
leads to the experiencing of vicarious emotions. When Mrs. Smith is 
'sharing Mrs. Brown's sorrow* there is in the first place the sharing, 
and in the second, the sorrow. The first is an unselfish participatory 
experience which makes her feel 'good' — in the literal, not in the 
cheap sense (when self-congratulatory or gloating sentiments are 
present, there is no true identification). The second is the sorrow— a 
vicarious experience, but genuinely felt. It may of course be joy or 
anxiety instead. The tears of Mrs. Smith at the happy ending when the 
lovers on the screen are reunited or the baby's life is saved in the nick 
of time, are released by the same process as the tears of the woman 
whose son has suddenly returned: relief from anxiety, and a hot surge 
of joy. 



THE tOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 



279 



The anxiety which grips the spectator of a thr&er-film, though 
vicarious, is nevertheless real; it is reflected in the familiar physical 
symptoms — palpitations, tensed muscles, sudden jumps' of alarm. 
The same applies to the anger felt at the machinations of the perfidious 
villain on the screen, whom Mexican audiences have been known to 
riddle with bullets. This leads us to an apparent paradox which is 
basic to the understanding of all dramatic art forms. We have seen 
that on the one hand the self-transcending emotions—participation, 
projection, identification — inhibit the self-asserting tendencies: they 
soothe, calm, eliminate worry and desire, purge body and mind of its 
tensions. On the other hand, the act of self-transcending identification 
may stimulate the surge of anger, fear, cruelty, which, although ex- 
perienced on behalf of somebody else, nevertheless belong to the sel£- 
assertive, aggressive-defensive class and display all their bodily symp- 
toms. The mother's bustling, laughter, agitation on her son s return, 
shows the classic 'adreno-toxk' pattern, characteristic of the self- 
assertive emotions — although her anxiety was centred not on herself, 
but experienced on behalf of her son. Anger, fear, and the related 
'emergency-reactions' use the same physiological mechanism whether 
the threat is directed at one's own person, or the person with whom 
one has identified oneself. They are always 'self-assertive' — although 
the 'self' has momentarily changed its address — by being, for instance, 
projected into the handsome and guileless heroine on the screen. 
Righteous indignation about injustices inflicted on others can generate 
behaviour just as fanatical as the sting of a personal insult. Self-sacri- 
ficing devotion to a creed bred ruthless inquisitors— 'the worst of 
madmen is a saint run mad'. 

The glory and the tragedy of the human condition are closely 
related to the fact that under certain circumstances the participatory 
tendencies may serve as mediators or vehicles for emotions belonging 
to the opposite class; whereas under different circumstances the two 
tendencies counteract and harmoniously balance each other. We shall 
return to this subject, from a different angle, in the next section; but 
let me note in passing that the preceding remarks on the various ways 
in which the two tendencies interact on the psychological level are 
again in keeping with the facts (as far as known) about the different 
modes of interaction between the two divisions of the autonomous 
nervous system, which may be antagonistic, compensatory, cathartic, 
or catalytic, according to conditions. 2 



280 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



E. Self-Pity. A litdy boy is beaten up by a gang of bullies. For a while 
he tries to fight back, to hit, scratch, and kick, but his tormentors 
immobilize him, and at last he begins to cry in 'impotent rage\ 

But the expression is misleading. Anybody who has watched child- 
ren fight knows that weeping will start only after the victim has given 
up struggling and wriggling and accepted defeat. After a while new 
outbursts of rage may renew the struggle, but, each time this happens, 
weeping is interrupted. It is not an expression of rage (although the 
two may overlap) but an expression of helplessness after rage has been 
exhausted and a feeling of being abandoned has set in — a yearning for 
love, sympathy, consolation. In other words, the tears once more 
signify a frustration of the participatory emotions; and if no sym- 
pathy is formcoming, self-pity will provide a substitute — a mild dis- 
sociation of the personality, in which the self is experienced almost 
as an alien object of loving commiseration. 

Similar considerations apply to so-called 'crying in pain*. In states of 
violent physical pain, as in acute states of rage, the organism is fully 
occupied coping with the emergency and has no time for tears. 

'Great pain', wrote Darwin, 'urges all animals, and has urged them 
during endless generations, to make the most violent and diversi- 
fied efforts to escape from the cause of sufferings. Even when a limb 
or other separate part of the body is hurt, we often see a tendency to 
shake it as if to shake off the cause, though this obviously be im- 
possible. Thus a habit of exerting with the utmost force all the 
muscles will have been established whenever great suffering is 
experienced.' 8 

Camion has shown that the Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear, and 
Rage (the title of his classic work) all follow the same basic pattern, 
that they are emergency responses of the sympathico-adrenal system. 
Violent pain seems to be experienced by the unconscious mind as an 
aggression, whether it is inflicted by an outside agent or not. When 
the aggressor is a tooth or a cramp in the stomach we are apt to say 'it 
hurts', as if the offending organ were not part of oneself and we try 
to shake the aggressor off, as animals do, by writhing, or pressing 
against it. Only when the pain has abated to a tolerably steady, 'dull' 
level do we accept it as part of ourselves— we 'have' a headache or 'are' 
under the weather — at the same time admitting that nothing can be 
done about it; writhing and struggling cease in the admission of defeat, 



THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 



28l 



as in the case of the child in the grip of its tormentors. * Weeping in 
pain* starts only when the specific pain-behaviour stops, as 'weeping 
with rage* starts when rage-behaviour stops, and for precisely the 
same reasons: it is an abandoning of defences, an expression of help- 
lessness, a craving for sympathy, and — if accompanied by vocal cries — 
an appeal for help. 

Another misconception is that children 'cry with fear', if crying' is 
used as a synonym for weeping. A child may cry out, in the literal 
sense, when suddenly frightened; it may run away, and if it cannot, 
strain away from the threatening apparition, lift his hands in protec- 
tion, and distort his face into a mask of terror. Once more, the tears 
will come only after the acute fright and the specific strained fright- 
reactions have ceased; they do not mean 'I am frightened* but 1 was 
so frightened, and maybe still am a little, and now I want to be 
comforted.' 

Consider what happens when a little boy, running along a gravel 
path, suddenly stumbles and falls. The fright-reaction consists in the 
protective outstretching of hands, and related muscle-reflexes. Once the 
contact with the earth is made and the first shock overcome, the acute 
scare ebbs away, the muscles relax in surrender, the facial expression 
changes from fear to the sympathy-begging grimace of incipient 
weeping. If there is no witness to the drama, self-pity will again pro- 
vide the overflow. If it is witnessed by the mother, who makes a fuss 
and betrays her anxiety, this will increase the child's craving for tender- 
ness and its tears will ask for more. If, on the other hand, she gently 
but firmly debunks the drama, then, after a moment of puzzlement, 
the child may break into rather hesitant laughter — the residue of the 
scare, and even the slight pain, are denied by reason and worked off, 
while at the same time the sympathy-craving emotions are nipped in 
the bud by the mother's matter-of-fact attitude. 

Lasdy, 'crying in hunger'. A baby never weeps from hunger— it 
cries to signal hunger. The proof is that crying instantaneously stops 
when the botde or breast is offered, before hunger can have ceased; 
furthermore, once the child is weaned from breast and bottle, hunger 
ceases to be expressed by crying or weeping. 4 

Needless to say, when a baby cries to attract attention, to signal that 
it is hungry or in distress, if often breaks into tears at the same time. 
Yet in such situations we say 'the baby is crying', not *the baby is 
weeping*, because the essence of the performance is the vocal protest 
or appeal for help; the shedding of tears is merely an accompaniment. 



282 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



The baby's bawling, kicking, and tossing is a typical and impressive 
emergency-reaction in 'pain, hunger, fear, and rage' of a dramatically 
self-asserting kind. The simultaneous overflow of the tear-glands may 
be 'genuine' weeping — longing for affection and tenderness — as an 
accompaniment to the bawling; it may also be due to physiological 
causes. Watering of the eyes can be induced as a purely physiological 
defence reflex against the intrusion of a foreign body — a piece of grit 
or the molecules which carry the smell of onions. (Lachrymation caused 
by such local irritation is, by the way, unilateral — it occurs initially in 
the affected eye only). 5 It can also be caused by coughing, sneezing, 
vomiting, and after prolonged fits of laughter. The physiological 
mechanism is still somewhat obscure, except that all these violent 
exertions affect the mucous membranes of the nose and throat, and 
tend to dry them; the lachrymal glands may have the function of 
restoring lubrication through tears entering the nose. 6 When one 
sees a baby cry its head off with dry eyes until it gets hoarse, one in- 
tuitively feels that tears would be a relief— both psychologically and 
physiologically. The same applies to adults in situations of extreme 
distress. 

Home they brought the warrior dead; 
She nor swooned nor uttered cry. 
All her maidens, watching said, 
'She must weep or she will die'. 

(Tennyson, The Princess) 

Lastly, weeping may start in the child as a genuine, spontaneous 
overflow-reflex, but once the power of tears has been consciously or 
unconsciously recognized, the flow may be initiated automatically, 
or even voluntarily, as a weapon more subde and more effective than 
mere cries of complaint or protest.* 'We seem to acquire specific 
visceral habits just as we pick up characteristic verbal and manual 
habits,' Kling has remarked, 7 and we ought to include in 'visceral 
habits* the exercise of the lachrymal glands. Weeping may be re- 
cruited into the service of hysteria, emotional blackmail, and even 
courtly behaviour (as a proof of sensibility less strenuous than swoon- 
ing) ; it may be associated with convulsions, shrieks, and agitated display; 
but its true character is manifested by the person who weeps alone — 
helpless in her surrender to an emotion which, by its nature, can find 
no other outlet, whether it is caused by the thunder of a church organ, 
or the fall of a sparrow. 



NOTES 



To p. 271. So scant arc the references of any significance to the subject in 
the technical literature, that I thought it would be useful to future students to 
list what I could find under a separate heading at the end of the bibliography. 
My indebtedness to those who helped in this is acknowledged in the Preface. 

To p. 273. Romain Rolland describing the character of religious experience 
in a letter to Freud— who regretfully professed never to have felt anything of the 
sort. 

To p. 274. "The characteristic anatomical organization of the parasym- 
pathetic is correlated with absence of unitary action in this system. It is not sur- 
prising therefore that the adrenal medulla ... has no counterpart in the para- 
sympathetic system, and that no parasympathomimetic hormone capable of 
acting extensively upon organs innervated by this system is liberated in the body.' 
(Madeod, ed. Bard, 1941 ed.) *. . . In contrast to the sympathomimetic hormones, 
the vagus substance is rapidly destroyed, and therefore produces very localized 
response. These effects are in line with the general behaviour of the sympathetic 
and parasympathetic systems of nerves.' (White and Smithwick, 1941, 2nd. ed.) 

'AH the viscera can be influenced simultaneously in one direction or the other 
by varying, up or down, the . . . tonic activity of the sympathetic division. And 
any special viscus can be separately influenced ... by varying ... the tonic 
activity of the special nerve of the opposed cranial or sacral [parasympathetic] 
division. . . . The sympathetic is like the loud and soft pedals, modulating all the 
notes together; the cranial and sacral [parasympathetic] innervations are like the 
separate keys.* (Cannon, 1929, 2nd. ed.) 

In the years since this has been written the significance for psychology of the 
anatomical and physiological contrast between the two branches of the auto- 
nomic nervous system has become more evident, to the extent that 'rage is 
called the most adrenergic, and love the most cholinergic reaction' (Cobb, 1950). 
A further correspondence between patterns of emotive behaviour and modes of 
interaction between the two branches of the autonomic nervous system emerged 
when it was shown that the vagoinsulin system may act, in different circum- 
stances, as an inhibitory or a catalytic agent in the glucose-utilization process 
and may also produce overcompensatory after effects (Gellhom, 1943, and 1957). 
Hebb (1949) suggested that a distinction should be made between two categories 
of emotions, 'those in which the tendency is to maintain or increase the original 
stimulating conditions (pleasurable or integrative emotions)* and 'those in which 
the tendency is to abolish or decrease the stimulus (rage, fear, disgust)*. Whereas 
the latter have a disruptive effect on cortical behaviour, the former have not. A 
few years later, Olds (1959 and i960) and others demonstrated the existence of 
'positive' and '.negative' emotive systems by electric stimulation, and further 
showed that they were activated respectively by the parasympathetic and sym- 
pathetic centres in the hypothalamus. 

These hints all seem to point in the same direction, but in fairness to the 
general reader I ought to point out that, while there is ample experimental 
proof that the hunger-rage-fear emotions are mediated by the sympathico- 
adrenal division, there is no direct evidence for the symmetrical correlation pro- 
posed here. Such proof can be forthcoming only when emotions outside the 
hunger-rage-fcar class will be recognized as a worthwhile object of study by ex- 
periment! d psychology— which at present is not the case. 

283 



284 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



To p. 282. A psychoanalyst friend of mine, after reading the manuscript of 
the preceding section* objected that his patients frequently weep during the 
analytical hour 'in anger and frustration*. But he agreed that anger alone would 
not have produced the tears, and that the frustration was due, metaphorically 
speaking, to the analyst's refusal *to give the patient the breast and sing a lullaby*. 



XIII 



PARTNESS AND WHOLENESS 

Stepchildren of Psychology 

The self-txanscending emotions* are the stepchildren of con- 
temporary psychology. One of the reasons is perhaps that they 
do not tend towards observable muscular activity but towards 
quietude; grief) longing, worship, raptness, aesthetic pleasure are 
emotions consummated not in overt but in internalized, visceral be- 
haviour, with weeping as its extreme manifestation. But even the 
shedding of tears is not so much an activity but rather a 'passivity*. 

The word 'emotion* is derived from 'motion*; and an emotion 
which tends to calm down motion seems to be a contradiction in 
terms. Yet the aesthetic or religious experiences which we call 'moving' 
are precisely those which induce passive contemplation, silent en- 
joyment. When the experimental psychologist talks of 'emotive be- 
haviour', however, he nearly always refers to rage, fear, sex, and 
hunger, whereas emotions which do not beget overt activity are 
slurred over as 'moods* or sentiments — with the implication that they 
are a suspect category of pseudo-emotions unworthy of the scientist's 
attention. This is probably a hangover of the great ideological currents 
of the nineteenth century stressing the biological struggle for existence, 
the survival of the fittest, the acquisitive and competitive aspects of 
social behaviour. The ambiance of this 'Darwinistic psychology* is 
reflected in passages like the following, from Crile's The Origin and 
Nature of the Emotions, published in 1915: 

When the business man is conducting a struggle for existence 
against his rivals, and when the contest is at its height, he may 
clench his fists, pound the table, perhaps show his teeth, and exhibit 
every expression of physical combat. Fixing the jaw and showing 
the teeth in anger merely emphasize the remarkable tenacity of 
philogeny . . . 

285 



286 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



It must be admitted, though, that the social climate of the nineteenth 
century did not favour the contemplative life, nor the arousal of 
genuine self-transcending emotions. The Victorian versions of religion, 
patriotism, and love were so thoroughly impregnated with prudery 
and hypocrisy that the experimental psychologist, devoted to measur- 
ing sensory threshholds and muscle twitches could hardly be expected 
to take such attitudes seriously, and to put them on a par with die sex 
and hunger drives. Around the turn of the century, the so-called James- 
Lange theory of emotions emphasized the importance of visceral pro- 
cesses, but it was nevertheless taken for granted that the 'true* or 'major' 
emotions were characterized by impulses to muscular action — mainly 
to hit, run, or rape. "When Cannon showed that hunger, pain, rage, and 
fear were, so to speak, variations on a single theme, it was tacidy taken 
for granted that all emotions worthy of that name were of the active, 
adreno-toxic, hit-run-mate-devour kind. Laughter and tears, awe and 
wonder, religious and aesthetic feeling, the whole 'violet' side of the 
rainbow of emotions was left to the poets to worry about; the so- 
called behavioural sciences had no room for them. Hence the paucity 
of the literature on weeping for instance — although it is certainly an 
observable behavioural phenomenon. 

The emotions of the neglected half of the spectrum are as real as 
rage and fear; that much we know for certain from everyday ex- 
perience. The theory which I have proposed assumes that they form 
a class, characterized by certain shared basic features. These are pardy 
negative: the absence of adreno-sympathetic excitation alone puts 
them in a category apart from the emergency responses. On the 
positive side, emotional states as different as mourning and aesthetic 
enchantment share the logic of the moist eye: they are passive, cathar- 
tic, dominated by parasympathetic reactions. From the psycholo- 
gical point of view, the sel£asserting emotions, derived from 
emergency reactions, involve a narrowing of consciousness; the partici- 
patory emotions an expanison of consciousness by identiflcatory 
processes of various kinds. 

There exist, however, considerations of a more precise and at the 
same time, more general nature on which this theory of the emotions 
is based. These arc discussed in Book Two, but I must briefly allude to 
them. In that wider context, the polarity between the self-asserting and 
participatory tendencies turns out to be merely a particular instance of 
a general phenomenon: namely, that every member of a living organ- 
ism or social body has the dual attributes of'wholeness' and partness'. It 



FASTNESS AND WHOLENESS 



287 



acts as an autonomous, self-governing whole on its own subordinate 
parts on lower levels of the organic or social hierarchy; but it is sub- 
servient to the co-ordinating centre on the next higher leveL In other 
words it displays both self-assertive and participatory tendencies. 

The Concept of Hierarchy 

The word 'hierarchy* is used here in a special sense. It does not mean 
simply * order of rank' (as in the pecking hierarchy' of the farmyard); 
it means a special type of organization (such as a military hierarchy) in 
which the overall control is centralized at the apex of a kind of genea- 
logical tree, which branches out downward. At the first branching-out, 
the commanders of the land-, sea-, and air-forces would correspond to 
the co-ordinating centres of, say, the digestive, respiratory, and re- 
productive organ-systems; each of these is subdivided into units or 
organs on lower levels of the hierarchy with their own co-ordinating 
centres, C.O.S and N.C.O.s; the organs in turn are subdivided into 
organ-parts; and so the branching-process goes on down to the 
cellular level and beyond. 

But each sub-organization, regardless on what level, retains a 
certain amount of autonomy or self-government. "Without this dele- 
gation of powers the organization could not function effectively: the 
supreme commander cannot deal with individual privates; he must 
transmit strategical orders through 'regulation channels*, which at 
each level are translated into tactical and sub-tactical moves. In the 
same way, information on what is happening in the various fields of 
operation (the sensory input) is selectively filtered on each level before 
being transmitted to the higher echelons. A living organism or social 
body is not an aggregation of elementary parts or elementary processes; 
it is an integrated hierarchy of semi-autonomous sub-wholes, consist- 
ing of sub-sub-wholes, and so on. Thus the functional units on every 
level of the hierarchy are double-faced as it were: they act as wholes 
when facing downwards, as parts when facing upwards. 

On the upper limit of the organic hierarchy, we find the same 
double-aspect: the individual animal or man is a whole relative to the 
parts of his body, but a part relative to the social organization to which 
he belongs. All advanced forms of social organization are again 
hierarchic: the individual is part of the family, which is part of the 
clan, which is part of the tribe, etc.; but instead of 'part* we ought 



288 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



in each case to say 'sub-whole* to convey the semi-autonomous 
character and self-assertive tendency of each functional unit. 

In the living organism, too, each part must assert its individuality, 
for otherwise the organism would lose its articulation and efficiency — 
but at the same time the part must remain subordinate to the demands 
of the whole. Let me give a few examples. The heart as an organ 
enjoys, of course, an advanced form of self-government: it has its own 
pacemakers' which regulate its rhythm; if one is knocked out a second 
automatically takes over. But the kidneys, intestines, and stomach 
also have their autonomous, self-regulating devices. Muscles, even 
single muscle cells, isolated from the body, will contract in response to 
appropriate stimulation. Any strip of tissue from an animal's heart will 
go on beating in vitro in its own, intrinsic rhythm. Each of these organs 
and organ-parts has a degree of self-sufficiency, a specific rhythm or 
pattern of activity, governed by a built-in, organic 'code'. Even a 
single cell has its organelles' which independendy look after its 
growth, motion, reproduction, communication, energy-supply, etc.; 
each according to its own sub-code of more or less fixed 'rules of the 
game*. On the other hand, of course, these autonomous action- 
patterns of the part are activated, inhibited or modified by controls on 
higher levels of the hierarchy. The pacemaker-system of the heart, for 
instance, is controlled by the autonomous nervous system and by 
hormones; these in turn depend on orders from centres in the brain. 
Generally speaking, each organ-matrix (e.g. a cell-organelle) has its 
mtrinsic code which determines the fixed, invariant pattern of its 
functioning; but it is at the same time a member of a matrix on a 
higher level (e.g. the cell), which in turn is a member of an organ or 
tissue, and so forth. Thus the two complementary pairs: matrix and 
code, self-asserting and participatory tendencies, are both derived from 
the hierarchic structure of organic life. 

Complex skilk, too, have a hierarchic structure. However much 
you try to disguise your handwriting, the expert will find you out by 
some characteristic way of forming or connecting certain groups of 
letters— the pattern has become an automatized and autonomous 
functional sub-whole which asserts itself against attempts of conscious 
interference. People whose right hand has been injured and who learn 
to write with the left soon develop a signature which is indistinguish- 
able from the previous right-handed one — 'the signature is in the brain', 
as a neurologist has said. 1 Again, touch-typing is a hierarchically 
ordered skill, where the 'letter habits' (finding the right key without 



PABTNESS AND WHOLENESS 



looking) enter as members into 'word-habits* (automatized move- 
ment-sequences, each with a 'feel* of its own, which are triggered off 
as wholes, c£ Book Two, XEE). Ask a skilled typist to misspell the 
word 'the' as *hte* each time it occurs — and watch how the code of the 
correct sequence asserts its autonomy. Functional habits must have 
some kind of structural representation in the neuron-matrices of the 
brain; and these patterned circuits must be hierarchically organized — 
as organ-systems are — to account for such complex and flexible skills 
as, for instance, transposing a tune from one key into another. 

Under normal conditions, the various parts of an organism — nerves, 
viscera, limbs — perform their semi-autonomous functions as sub- 
wholes, while at the same time submitting to the regulative control 
of the higher centres. But under conditions of stress the part called on 
to cope with the disturbance may become over-excited and get 'out of 
control*. The same may happen if the organism's powers of control 
are impaired—by senescence, for instance, or by a physiological block- 
age. In both cases the self-assertive tendencies of the part, isolated and 
released from the restraining influence of the whole, will express them- 
selves in deleterious ways; these range from the remorseless prolifera- 
tion of cancer cells to the obsessions and delusions, beyond rational 
control, in mental disorder (cf. Book Two, m, IV). 

The single individual represents the top-level of the organismic 
hierarchy and at the same time the lowest unit of the social hierarchy. 
It is on this boundary line between physiological and social organiza- 
tion that the two antagonistic tendencies, which are at work on every 
level, even in a single cell, manifest themselves in the form of 'emotive 
behaviour'. Under normal conditions the self-asserting tendencies of 
the individual are dynamically balanced by his dependence on and 
participation in the life of the community to which he belongs. In the 
body social physiological controls are of course superseded by institu- 
tional controls, which restrain, stimulate, or modify the autonomous 
patterns of activity of its social sub-wholes on all levels, down to the 
individual. When tensions arise, or control is impaired, a social 'organ* 
(the barons, or the military, or the miners) may get over-excited and 
out of control; the individual, for the same reasons, may give un- 
restrained expression to rage, panic, or lust, and cease to obey the rules 
of the game imposed by the social whole of which he is part. 

The participatory tendencies are as firmly anchored in the organic 
hierarchy as are their opponents. From the genetic point of view, the 
duality is reflected in the complementary processes of difFerentiation 



200 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



of structure and integration of function. We may extend the scope of 
the inquiry even further downward, from animal to vegetable and 
mineral, and discover analogous pairs of self-asserting and partici- 
patory forces in inanimate nature. From the particles in an atom to 
the planets circling the sun, we find relatively stable dynamic systems, 
in which the disruptive, centrifugal forces are balanced by binding 
forces which hold the system together as a whole. The metaphors we 
commonly use reflect an intuitive awareness that the pairs of opposites 
on various levels form a continuous series: when in rage, 'we fly off at 
a tangent' as if carried away by a centrifugal force; and contrariwise, we 
speak of social 'cohesion', personal 'affinities', and the 'attraction 
exerted by an idea. These are no more than analogies; the 'attraction' 
between two people of opposite sex does not obey the inverse square 
law and is by no means proportionate to their mass; yet it remains 
nevertheless true that on every level of the evolutionary hierarchy 
stability is maintained by the equilibration of forces pulling in opposite 
directions: centrifugal and centripetal, the former asserting the part's 
independence, autonomy, individuaHty, the second keeping it in its 
place as a dependent part in the whole. Kepler kept affirming that his 
comparison between the moving force that emanates from the sun 
and the Holy Ghost was more than an analogy; the cohesion between 
the free-floating bodies in the solar system must have a divine cause. 
Newton himself toyed with similar ideas.* 

I must apologize for the seemingly sweeping generalizations in the 
preceding section; the reader will find them substantiated in some detail 
in the biological chapters of Book Two. For the time being, I only 
meant to give some indication of the broader theoretical considerations 
on which the proposed classification of emotions is based — namely, 
that 'part-behaviour 9 and 'whole-behaviour' are opposite tendencies in 
dynamic equilibrium on every level of a living organism, and can be 
extrapolated by way of analogy, both upwards into the hierarchies of 
the body social, and downward into stable anorganic systems. 

Such an approach does not imply any philosophical dualism; it is in 
fact no more dualistic than Newton's law of action and reaction, or the 
conventional method of 'thinking in opposites'. The choice of 'ultimate* 
and 'irreducible' principles (such as Freud's Eros and Tanatos) is always 
largely a matter of taste; partness* and 'wholeness' recommend them- 
selves as a serviceable pair of complementary concepts because they are 
derived from the ubiquitously hierarchic organization of all living 
matter. They also enable us to discuss the basic features of biological, 



PARTNESS AND WHOLENESS 



291 



social, and mental evolution in uniform terms as the emergence of more 
differentiated and specialized structures, balanced by more complex 
and delicate integrations of function. 

Lastly, increased complexity means increased risks of breakdowns, 
which can only be repaired by processes of the regenerative, reenter- 
pour-mieux-sauter type that I have mentioned before and which will 
occupy us again. I shall try to show that seen in the light of the relation 
of part to whole, these processes assume a new significance as aids to 
the understanding of the creative mind. 

NOTES 

To p. 285. I am using 'self-transcending emotions' as a short-hand expres- 
sion for * emotional states in which the self-transcending tendencies dominate'. 

To p. 2$o. In the only excursion into science fiction of which I am guilty, I 
made a visiting maiden from an alien planet explain the basic doctrine of its 
quasi-Kcplerian religion: 

\ . . "We worship gravitation. It is the only force which does not travel 
through space in a rush; it is everywhere in repose. It keeps the stars in their 
orbits and our feet on our earth. It is Nature's fear of loneliness, the earth's 
longing for the moon; it is love in its pure, inorganic form.* {Twilight Bar, 1945.) 



XIV 

ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 



In the chapter on the 'Logic of the Moist Eye* I have discussed 
weeping as a manifestation of frustrated participatory emotions. 
Let me now briefly consider the normal manifestations of this 
class of emotions in childhood and adult life. 

As Freud, Piaget, and others have shown, the very young child does 
not differentiate between ego and environment. The mother's breast 
seems to it a more intimate possession than the toes on its own body. 
It is aware of events, but not for a long time of itself as a separate 
entity. It lives in a state of mental symbiosis with the outer world, a 
continuation of the biological symbiosis in the womb, a state which 
Piaget calls 'protoplasmic consciousness'. 1 The universe is focussed 
on the self, and the self is the universe; the outer environment is only 
a kind of second womb. 

From this original state of protoplasmic or symbiotic consciousness, 
the development towards autonomous individuation is slow, gradual, 
and will never be entirely completed. The initial state of consciousness 
may be likened to a liquid, fluid universe traversed by dynamic currents, 
by the rhythmic rise and fall of physiological needs, causing minor 
storms which come and go without leaving any solid traces. Gradually 
the floods recede and the first islands of objective reality emerge; their 
contours grow firmer and sharper and are set off against the undifferen- 
tiated flux. The islands are followed by continents, the dry territories 
of reality are mapped out; but side by side with them the liquid world 
co-exists, surrounding it, interpenetrating it by canals and inland 
lakes, the relics of the erstwhile oceanic communion. In the words of 
Freud: 

Originally the ego includes everything, later it detaches from 
itself the external world. The ego-feeling we are aware of now is 
292 



ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 



293 



thus only a shrunken vestige of a far more extensive feeling—a 
feeling which embraced the universe and expressed an inseparable 
connection of the ego with the external world. If we may suppose 
that this primary ego-feeling has been preserved in the minds of 
many people, to a greater or lesser extent, it would co-exist like a 
sort of counterpart with the narrower and more sharply outlined 
ego-feeling of maturity, and the ideational content belonging to it 
would be precisely the notion of limitless extension and oneness with 
the universe. 2 

It is this 'oceanic feeling' which mystics and artists strive to recapture 
on a higher level of development — at a higher turn of the spiral. 

Until the end of the second or third year, while the separation of ego 
and non-ego is as yet incomplete, the child tends to confuse the sub- 
jective and the objective, dream and reality, the perceived and the 
imagined, its thoughts and the things thought about. Children and 
primitives not only believe in the magical transformations which occur 
in myths and fairy tales, but also believe themselves capable of per- 
forming them. The child at play becomes at will transformed into a 
horse, tie doctor, a burglar, or a locomotive. Some primitives believe 
that they change at night into certain animals; if the animal is killed, 
they have to die. Magic causation precedes physical causation; to wish 
for an event is almost the same as producing it; children are great 
believers in the omnipotence of thought. As thought becomes in- 
creasingly centred in verbal and visual symbols, these become in- 
struments of wishful evocation — of word-magic and symbol-magic. 

This erstwhile method of establishing magic connections between 
events — regardless of distance in space, succession in time, or physical 
intermediaries, is a basic feature of primitive, but also of some highly 
developed societies, particularly in the East. Levy-Bruhl — an anthro- 
pologist now somewhat out of fashion who greatly influenced Freud, 
Piaget, and Jung — had called this phenomenon participation mystique 
or the 'Law of Participation'. 3 It is reflected in innumerable rites and 
observances; in the individual's experience of a quasi-symbiotic com- 
munion between himself, his tribe, and his totem; between a man and 
his name, a man and his portrait, a man and his shadow; between the 
deity and its symbol; between a desired event — rain, or a successful 
hunt — and its symbolic enactment in dance, ritual play, or pictorial 
representation. Here is the ancient, unitary source out of which the 
dance and the song, the mystery plays of the Achaens, the calendars of 



294 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the Babylonian priest-astronomers, and the cave-paintings of Altaniira 
were to branch out later on— a magic source which, however great the 
distance travelled, still provides artist and explorer with his basic 
nourishment. 

At an even earlier stage of social evolution, magic participation 
could be achieved by still more direct methods: the physical prowess 
of animals, the courage and wisdom of other men, the body and blood 
of the sacrificed god, could be acquired and shared by the simple 
means of eating them.* The sacrament of Holy Communion reflects, 
in a symbolic and sublimated form, the ecstasies of the Dionysian and 
Orphic mystery-rites: the devouring of the torn god. The partici- 
patory magic of trans-substantiation operates here not only between 
the communicant and his god, but also between all those who have 
partaken in the rite, and incorporated the same substance into them- 
selves. A ghastly degeneration of this ritual was revealed when the cir- 
cumstances of taking the Mau-Mau oath became known. A more 
harmless form of it is the 'blood-brother ceremony among Arab 
tribes, performed by drinking a few drops of the elected brother's 
blood; a socially valuable survival of it are the rites of conviviality — 
from the symbolic sharing of bread and salt, to the ceremonial ban- 
queting of the Chevaliers du Taste-Vin. The emotions derived from 
the feeding-drive seem to be of the purely self-assertive type; in fact, 
commensality, with its archetypal echoes, invests them with a more 
or less pronounced participatory character. 

The progress from the historically earlier, or infantile forms of 
symbiotic consciousness towards voluntary self-transcendence through 
artistic, religious or social communion, reflects the sublimation of the 
participatory tendencies — emerging at the other end of the tunnel, 
as it were. Needless to say, the culture in which we live is not very 
favourable to this progress; the majority of our contemporaries never 
emerge from the tunnel, and get only occasional mtimations of a 
distant pinpoint of light The forces which effect the gradual replace- 
ment of the child's subjective by objective reality arise through con- 
tinuous friction between self and environment. Hard facts emerge 
because objects are hard, and hurt if one bangs against them; wishes do 
not displace mountains, not even rocking horses. A second type of 
friction, between the self and other selves, drives home the fact that 
these latter too exist in their own right. Biological communion with 
the mother is dissolved by a succession of separative acts: expulsion 
from the womb, weaning from the breast, the cessation of fondling 



ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 



29$ 



and petting, Western man's 'taboo on tenderness*. Things and people 
wage a continuous war of attrition on the magic forms of participation 
— until the floods recede, and the waterways dry up. Symbiotic con- 
sciousness wanes with maturation, as it must; but modern education 
provides hardly any stimuli for awakening cosmic consciousness to 
replace it. The child is taught petitionary prayer instead of meditation, 
religious dogma instead of contemplation of the infinite; the mysteries 
of nature are drummed into his head as if they were paragraphs in the 
penal code. In tribal societies puberty is a signal for solemn and severe 
initiation rites, to impress upon the individual his collective ties, before 
he is accepted as a part in the social whole. Vestiges of these rites still 
survive in institutions such as the Church and the Army; yet the 
majority of individuals take their place in the body social not by a 
process of integration, but as a result of random circumstances and 
pressures. The romantic bursts of enthusiasm in adolescence are like a 
last, euphoric flicker of the self-transcending emotions before they 
submit to atrophy and begin to shrivel away. 

But they are never completely defeated. For one thing, the attritive 
forces of the social environment affect different strata of the personality 
in different ways. The most affected are the conscious, rational surface- 
layers directly exposed to contact; whereas the non-socialized, non- 
verbalized strata become the natural refuge of the thwarted partici- 
patory tendencies. The more remote from the surface, the less sharp 
the boundaries between the self and non-self; in those depths the sym- 
biotic channels still remain navigable in the dream and other games of 
the underground, from which mysticism, discovery, and art draw their 
intuitions. 

There exists, however, a whole range of more ordinary phenomena 
through which the self-transcending emotions manifest themselves in 
everyday life, and which I must briefly mention. The most banal of 
these is perceptual projection, which does not properly belong in this 
context — except in so far as it demonstrates that the boundaries of the 
self in our subjective experiences are not as clear-cut as we are wont to 
believe. 'Projection* in this technical sense means that the processes 
which take place in the retina and the brain are experienced as taking 
place not where they actually do take place, but yards or miles away. 
(This becomes at once obvious when one remembers that very low- 
pitched sounds are experienced — correctly — as reverberations inside the 
ear, and darling flashes, again correctly, as occurring in the retina^ 
Similarly, when you drive a nail into the wall you are aware, not that 



296 THE ACT OF CREATION 

the handle has struck your palm, but that its head has struck the nail, 
as if the hammer had become part of your body. 4 These are not in- 
ventions of psychologists to make the simple appear as complicated, 
but examples of our tendency to confuse what happens in the self 
with what happens outside it— a kind of perceptual symbiosis* between 
ego and environment. 

Projective empathy — again in a technical sense — is based on a similar 
confusion: an arrow drawn on paper is felt to manifest a dynamic 
tendency to move (probably a consequence of our own unconscious 
eye-movements); a church spire seems to 'soar* upwards, a picture has 
'movement' and 'balance*, and so on. Not only motions, but emotions 
too are projected from the self into lifeless objects; my car, climbing a 
hill, 'groans' and 'pants* under its 'effort*; the weeping willow weeps, 
the thunder growls. The tendency to animism, to project unconsciously 
life and feeling into inanimate bodies, is well-nigh kresistible — witness 
the two millennia of Aristotelian physics; we can only conclude that 
it is a basic feature of our psychic make-up. 

Equally inveterate is the tendency to project our own emotions into 
other living beings — animals and people. The first leads to anthro- 
pomorphism — ascribing to our pet dogs, horses, and canaries reasoning 
processes modelled on our own; the second to what one might call 
'egomorphism* — the illusion that others must feel on any subject 
exactly as I do. A more complicated projective transaction is trans- 
ference — where A projects his feelings, originally aimed at B, on to a 
substitute, C: a father figure, sister figure, or what have you, each 
further transferable to D, E, etc. The Who's Who of the subconscious 
seems to be printed with coloured inks on blotting paper. 

Introjection is meant to signify the reverse of projection, though the 
two phenomena are often ^distinguishable from each other.* When 
somebody bangs his head on the doorpost, I wince; when a forward 
in a soccer game has a favourable opportunity to shoot, I kick my 
neighbour's shin. Adolescents unconsciously ape their hero's man- 
nerisms; our super-egos were supposedly moulded by our parents at a 
time when the self was still in a fluid state. Throughout his life, the 
individual keeps introjecting chunks and patterns of other people's 
existence into his own; he suffers and enjoys vicariously the emotions 
of those with whom be becomes entangled in identiflcatory rapports. 
Some of these personality-transactions have lasting effects; others are 
more transitory, but at the same time more dramatic. Laughter and 
yawning have an instantly infectious effect; so have cruelty, hysteria, 



ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 297 

hallucinations, religious trances. In the hypnotic state 'the functions of 
the ego seem to be suspended, except those which communicate with 
the hypnotizer as though through a narrow slit in a screen* (Kret- 
schmer); the personality of the hypnotizer has been substituted for the 
dormant parts of the ego; the 'slit* acts as a gap in the frontier between 
the self and non-self, letting in the contraband. 

Freud, though disappointed at an early stage with hypno-therapy, 
kept stressing the affinities between hypnosis and love on die one hand, 
hypnosis and mass-behaviour on the other. In states of extreme en- 
amouredness (the German technical term is Horigkeit — bondage, 
servitude, subjection) its object replaces the super-ego or the hypno- 
tist. The poetry — or pathology — of the condition lies in the total 
fascination of the bondsman by the bond, an attenuated but protracted 
variant of the hypnotic rapport. Awareness is focussed on the object of 
worship, the rest of the world is blurred or screened. The perfect symbol 
of the hypnotic effect is in Stendhal's Charterhouse of Parma: young Fab- 
rice, in his prison cell, stares for hours on end through a narrow slit in the 
screen covering his window, at the figure of Clelia across the street. 

The 'hypnotic effect* of political demagogues has become a cliche, 
but one aspect of mass-psychology must be briefly mentioned. The 
type of crowd or mob to which Le Bon's classic descriptions still apply, 
is fanatical and 'single-minded' because the subtler individual differences 
between its members are temporarily suspended; the whole mass is 
thus intellectually adjusted to its lowest common denominator,* but 
in terms of dynamic action it has a high emcacity, because the impulses 
of its members are aligned through narrow slits — or blinkers — all 
pointing in the same direction; hence their experience of being parts 
of an irresistible power. This experience of partness within a dynamic 
whole leads to a temporary suspension of individual responsibility — 
which is replaced by unconditional subordination to the 'controlling 
centre*, the leader of the crowd. It further entails the temporary 
effacement of all self-assertive tendencies: the total surrender of the 
individual to the collectivity is manifested in altruistic, heroic, self- 
sacrificing acts — and at the same time in bestial cruelty towards the 
enemy or victim of the collective whole. This is a further example of 
the self-transcending emotions serving as catalysts or triggers for their 
opponents. But let us note that the brutality or heroism displayed by a 
fanaticized crowd is quasi-impersonal, and unselfish; it is exercised in 
the interest, or supposed interest, of the whole. The same S.S* detach- 
ments which mowed down the whole male population of Lidice were 



298 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



capable of dying at Oradur like the defenders of Thermopylae. The 
self-assertive behaviour of a mass is based on the participatory be- 
haviour of the individual, which often entails sacrifice of his personal 
interest and even his life. Theories of ethics based on enlightened self- 
interest fail to provide an answer why a man should sacrifice his life 
in the defence of his family-— not to mention country, liberty, beliefs. 
The fact that men have always been prepared to die for (good, bad, or 
futile) causes, proves that the self-transcending tendencies are as basic 
to his mental organization as the others. And since the individual 
cannot survive without some form of social integration, self-preserva- 
tion itself always implies a component of self-transcendence. 

Excepting saints and maniacs, our emotions nearly always consist of 
mixed feelings, where both tendencies (and both branches of the 
autonomous nervous system) participate in the mixture. Love, of 
course, is a many-splendoured thing, both with regard to its variety 
(sexual, platonic, parental, oedipal, narcissistic, patriotic, canine- 
directed, or feline-oriented as the technicians would say), and also with 
regard to the extraordinary cocktail of emotions which each variety 
represents. Much less obvious is the fact, that even such a simple and 
scientifically respectable drive as hunger should give rise to mixed 
emotions. If I may return to the subject (p. 294) for a moment: on the 
one hand, food is 'attacked'; it is 'wolfed'; one 'puts one's teeth into it'; 
biting and snapping are the very prototypes of aggression. On the 
other hand, the 'feeding drive* is stimulated or inhibited by the com- 
pany participating in the meal; and the sacred element in the rituals of 
mensality (still surviving, for instance, in the funeral and wedding 
feasts) I have already mentioned. The teeth are tools of aggression, 
but tie mouth is a preferential zone of affectionate bodily contact in 
billing and kissing. The German idiom 'Ich habe dick zum Fressen gerne 
— I love you so much I could eat you — and the English 'devouring 
love* are symbolized by the behaviour of young mothers mock- 
devouring the baby's fingers and toes; it may be a distant echo of the 
gentle cannibal. Incidentally, we are told that among certain tribes 
practising ritual cannibalism, to be eaten is regarded as a great compli- 
ment; perhaps the male of the praying mantis feels the same way. 

Lasdy, the seemingly most altruistic social behaviour may have an 
admixture of conscious or unconscious self-assertion. Professional do- 
gooders, charity tigresses, hospital matrons, prison visitors, mission- 
aries, and social workers are indispensable to society, and do an 



ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 



299 



admirable amount of good; to pry into their motives, often hidden 
to themselves, would be ungrateful and churlish. 

Sumtnary 

Weeping is an overflow reflex for an excess of the participatory 
emotions, as laughter is for the self-asserting emotions. Its nervous 
mechanism and bodily manifestations are the opposites of those of 
laughter with regard to facial expression, respiratory pattern, bodily 
posture. In laughter tension is exploded, emotion denied; in weeping 
it is gradually drained away without break in the continuity of mood; 
thought and emotion remain united. The self-asserting emotions worked 
off in laughter depend on the sympathico-adrenal system, which 
galvanizes the body into activity; lachrymation is controlled by the 
parasympathetic division whose action is inward-directed and cathartic. 
The self-transcending emotions which overflow in tears cannot be 
satisfied by any specific muscular activity; they tend towards passivity 
and self-abandonment, and are consummated in glandular and visceral 
reactions. 

The various causes of weeping which have been discussed— raptness, 
weeping in sorrow, in joy, in sympathy, or in self-pity — all have a 
basic element in common: a craving to transcend the island boundaries 
of the individual, to enter into a symbiotic communion with a human 
being or some higher entity, real or imaginary, of which the self is 
felt to be a part. Owing to the peculiarities of our cultural climate, the 
participatory emotions have been virtually ignored by contemporary 
psychology, although they are as real and observable in their mani- 
festations as hunger, rage, and fear. They are grounded in the hierarchic 
order of life where every entity has the dual attributes of partness and 
wholeness, and the dual potentialities of behaving as an autonomous 
whole or a dependent part. The classification of emotions which I 
have proposed is based on this general principle of polarity, to be found 
on every level of the organic and social heirarchies (cf. Book Two). 
The dual concept of adaptable matrices with fixed invariant codes is 
derived from the same principle. 

In the development of the individual, as in the evolution of cultures, 
the manifestations of the participatory tendencies show a progression, 
comparable to that of the aggressive-defensive emotions from primi- 
tive and infantile to adult forms. The 'symbiotic consciousness' of 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



infancy, with its fluid ego boundaries, is partly relegated to the sub- 
conscious strata— from which the artist and the mystic draw their 
inspirations; partly superseded by the phenomena of projection and 
introjection, empathy and identification, transference and hypnosis. 
Similarly, the participatory bonds of primitive magic are gradually 
transformed into symbolic rituals, mythological epics, and mystery 
plays: into the magic of illusion. The shadows in Plato's cave are 
symbols of mans loneliness; the paintings in the Lascaux caves are 
symbols of his magic powers. 

The participatory emotions, like their opposites, can be accom- 
panied by feelings of pleasure or un-pleasure which form a con- 
tinuous scale, and add a third dimension to emotional experience. 
Lasdy, identification, in itself a sel£transcending experience, can serve 
as a vehicle (or trigger) for vicarious emotions of anger and fear. 

NOTES 

To p. 294. The point has been succinctly made by Walter de la Mare: 

It's a very odd thing — 
As odd as can be — 
That whatever Miss T. eats 
Turns into Miss T. 

Top. 296. *In relation to the dissolution of the ego complex, identification 
can receive a somewhat different interpretation according as ego-components are 
projected into the outside world or as elements from the outside world are in- 
corporated into the personality. In very fluid dream processes such a distinction 
cannot usually be very accurately drawn; but in schizophrenia, for example, both 
possibilities can be most clearly experienced/ (Kretschmer, 1954, p. 93.) 

To p. 297. The expression 'lowest common denominator* is mathematically 
nonsensical; it should, of course, be 'highest*. But the "highest common deno- 
minator* in a crowd of large numbers is still pretty low; thus the faulty idiom 
conveys the right idea, and the correct expression would only create confusion. 



I 



B. VERBAL CREATION 
XV 

ILLUSION 
The Power of Illusion 

Iiterature begins with the telling of a tale. The tale represents 
certain events by means of auditory and visual signs. The 
— events thus represented are mental events in the narrator's 
mind. His motive is the urge to communicate these events to others, 
to make them relive his thoughts and emotions; the urge to share. The 
audience may be physically present, or an imagined one; the narrator 
may address himself to a single person or to his god alone, but his 
basic need remains the same: he must share his experiences, make 
others participate in them, and thus overcome the isolation of the self. 

To achieve this aim, the narrator must provide patterns of stimuli as 
substitutes for the original stimuli which caused the experience to 
occur. This, obviously, is not an easy task, for he is asking his audience 
to react to things which are not there, such as the smell of grass on a 
summer morning. Since the dawn of civilization, bards and story- 
tellers have produced bags of tricks to provide such Ersatz-stiimdL 
The sum of these tricks is called the art of literature. 

The oldest and most fundamental of all tricks is to disguise people 
in costumes and to put them on a stage with masks or paint on their 
faces; the audience is thereby given the impression that the events 
represented are happening here and now, regardless of how distant they 
really are in space and time. The effect of this procedure is to induce a 
very lively bisociated condition in the minds of the audience. The 
spectator knows, in one compartment of his mind, that the people on 
the stage are actors, whose names are familiar to him; and he knows 
that they are 'acting' for the express purpose of creating an illusion in 
him, the spectator. Yet in another compartment of his mind he ex- 
periences fear, hope, pity, accompanied by palpitations, arrested 
breathing, or tears — all induced by events which he knows to be pure 
make-believe. It is indeed a remarkable phenomenon that a grown-up 

301 



302 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



person, knowing all the time that he faces a screen onto which shadows 
are projected by a machine, and knowing furthermore quite well what 
is going to happen at the end— for instance, that the police will arrive 
just in die nick of time to save the hero— should nevertheless go through 
agonies of suspense, and display the corresponding hodily symptoms. 
It is even more remarkable that this capacity for living in two universes 
at once, one real, one imaginary, should be accepted without wonder 
as a commonplace phenomenon. The following extract from a London 
newspaper report may help to restore our sense of wonder: 1 

Twice a week, with a haunting, trumpeted signature tune and 
a view of terraced roofs stretching away into infinity, Coronation 
Street, Granada Televisions serial of North Country life, goes on 
the air. It has now had 200 issues and is coming up to its second 
birthday next week. It is one of Britain's most popular television 
programmes. Enthusiasts call it a major sociological phenomenon. 
In fact all marathon TV serials with fixed settings and regular 
characters are cunningly designed to turn the viewer into an addict. 
Coronation Street eschews glamour and sensational curtains and 
concentrates on trapping the rugged smug ambience on North 
Country working and lower middle-class life. It will follow a local 
event like a council election or an amateur theatrical through instal- 
ment after instalment with the tenacity of a parish magazine. Its 
characters provide parts that actors can sink their teeth into and 
digest and assimilate. They have become deeply planted, like the 
permanent set of seven terraced houses, the shop on the corner, the 
Mission Hall, and the pub. 

The characters have devotees who insist on believing in their 
reality. When the buxom Elsie Tanner was involved with a sailor 
who, unknown to her, was married, she got scores of letters warning 
her of the danger. Jack Watson, the actor who played the sailor, was 
stopped outside the studio by one gallant mechanic who threatened 
to give him a hiding if he didn't leave Elsie alone. 

Hie strongest personality of them all, the sturdy old bulldog 
bitch, Ena Sharpies, has a huge following. When she was sacked 
feom the Mission Hall of which she was caretaker, viewers from all 
over the country wrote offering her jobs. When she was in hospital 
temporarily bereft of speech, a fight broke out in Salford between a 
gang of her fens and an Irish detractor who said he hoped the old 
bag would stay dumb till Kingdom come. 



ILLUSION 



303 



Moreover, when one of the seven houses on the set became Vacant* 
because its owner was said to have moved — in fact because the actor 
in question had been dropped from the programme — there were several 
applications for renting the house; and when at a dramatic moment of 
the serial the barmaid in the 'Rover's Return* smashed an ornamental 
plate, several viewers sent in replacements to comfort her. 

Of course, these people know that they are watching actors. Do they 
nevertheless believe that the characters are real? The answer is neither 
yes nor no, but yes and no. The so-called law of contradiction in 
logic — that a thing is either A or not-A but cannot be both — is a late 
acquisition in the growth of individuals and cultures (Book Two, 
XV). The unconscious mind, the mind of the child and the primi- 
tive, are indifferent to it. So are the Eastern philosophies which teach 
the unity of opposites, as well as Western theologians and quantum 
physicists. The addicts of Coronation Street who insist on believing in 
the reality of Ena Sharpies have merely carried one step further the 
momentary split-mindedness experienced by a sophisticated movie- 
audience at the climax of a Hitchcock thriller; they live in a more or 
less permanently bisociated world. 

The Value of Illusion 

But where does beauty, aesthetic value, or 'art' enter into the process? 
The answer requires several steps. The first is to recognize the in- 
trinsic value of illusion in itself- It derives from the transfer of attention 
from the 'Now and Here' to the 'Then and There* — that is, to a 
plane remote from self-interest. Self-assertive behaviour is focussed on 
the Here and Now; the transfer of interest and emotion to a different 
time and location is in itself an act of self-transcendence in the literal 
sense. It is achieved through the lure of heroes and victims on the 
stage who attract the spectator's sympathy, with whom he partially 
identifies himself, and for whose sake he temporarily renounces his 
preoccupations with his own worries and desires. Thus the act of 
participating in an illusion has an inhibiting effect on the self-asserting 
tendencies, and facilitates the unfolding of the self-transcending ten- 
dencies. In other words illusion has a cathartic effect — as all ancient and 
modern civilizations recognized by incorporating various forms of 
magic into their purification-rites and abreaction therapies. 
It is true that illusion, from Greek tragedy to horror comics, is also 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



capable of generating fear and anger, palpitations and cold sweat, 
which seems to contradict its cathartic function. But the emotions 
thus generated are vicarious emotions derived from the spectator's 
participation in another person*s existence, which is a self-transcending 
act (<£ pp. 278-9). Consequently, however exciting the action on the 
stage, the anger or fear which it generates will always carry a com- 
ponent of sympathy, an irradiation of unselfish generosity, which 
facilitates catharsis— just as a varying amount of high-voltage current 
is always transformed into heat. At a later stage, when the climax of 
the drama is passed, and the tension ebbs away, the whole amount of 
the current is consumed in a gentle inner glow. 

The Dynamics of Illusion 

In the comedy, the accumulation of suspense, and its subsequent annihi- 
lation in laughter take place at distincdy separate stages (although the 
two may overlap in the smiling, anticipated pleasure of the joke to 
come). la the tragedy, on the other hand, excitation and catharsis are 
continuous. Laughter explodes emotion; weeping is its gentle over- 
flow; there is no break in the continuity of mood, and no separation of 
emotion from reason. The hero, with whom the spectator has identi- 
fied himself, cannot be debunked by slipping on a banana-skin or by any 
sudden incongruity in his behaviour. The gods of the Greek and Hindu 
pantheon might change into any shape— a swan, a bull, a monkey, a 
shower of coins — and yet their paramours would lovingly surrender 
to them. On the bas-reliefs of Indian temples Shiva is often seen making 
love to Parvati while standing on his head, without appearing ridi- 
culous. When the events in epic or drama take an unexpected turn — 
Odysseus's companions transformed into swine or chaste Ophelia 
singing obscene songs— emotion, if aggressively tainted, refuses to 
perform the jump and explodes in laughter; if sympathetic, it will 
follow the hero through all viscissitudes. The abrupt change of situa- 
tion which required an equally quick reorientation of the mind to a 
different associative context, led in the first case to a rupture between 
emotion and reason, in the second to a transfer of emotion to the new 
context whereby its harmonious co-ordination with reason is preserved 
Thus incongruity — the confrontation of incompatible matrices- 
will be experienced as ridiculous, pathetic, or intellectually challen- 
ging, according to whether aggression, identification, or the well- 



ILLUSION 



305 



balanced blend of scientific curiosity prevails in the spectator s mind. 
Don Quixote is a comic or a tragic figure, or a case-history of incipient 
paranoia, depending on the panel of the tryptich in which lie is 
placed. In all three cases the matrices of reality and delusion — of wind- 
mills and phantom-knights — confront each other in the reader's mini 
In the first case they collide, and malice is spilled in laughter. In the 
second, the two universes remain juxtaposed, reason osculates to and 
fro between them, compassion remains attached to it and is easily trans- 
ferred from one matrix to the other. In the third case, the two merge 
in a synthesis: the (emotionally neutral') diagnosis of the clinician. 

Thus compassion, and the other varieties of the participatory emo- 
tions, attach themselves to the narrative told on the stage or in print, 
like faithful dogs, and follow it whatever the surprises, twists, and in- 
congruities the narrator has in store for them. By contrast, hostility, 
malice, and contempt tend to persist in a straight course, impervious to 
the subtleties of intellect; to them a spade is a spade, a windmill a 
windmill, and a Picasso nude with three breasts an object to leer at. 
The self-transcending emotions seem to be guided by the rnavim tout 
comprendre cest tout pardonner; the self-asserting emotions are designed 
for assertion, not comprehension. Hence, when attention is suddenly 
displaced from one frame of reference to another, the self-asserting im- 
pulses, deprived of their raison d'etre, are spilled in the process, whereas 
the participatory emotions are transferred to the new matrix. 

The physiological considerations which lend support to this view I 
have already discussed (pp. 56 £f; 274, 283). Anger and fear owe their 
persistence and momentum to the sympathico-adrenal machinery, 
which causes them to become occasionally dissociated from reasoning* 
The self-transcending emotions, on the other hand, are accompanied 
by parasympathetic reactions which are in every respect the opposite of 
the former; since they are devoid of massiveness and momentum, there 
is no cause for their falling out of step with the higher mental activities, 
and the normal co-ordination of thought and emotion will prevail. If 
your mind has the nimbleness of migrating, at a moment's notice, 
into Romeo's in sixteenth-century Verona, then you will also be capable 
of shedding tears at Juliet's death. 

We must remember, however, that emotions are complex mixtures; 
our amusement at Charlie Chaplin's adventures is full of compassion. 
All that is required for a mildly comic effect is that an aggressive factor 
should DC present of sufficient strength to provide a certain inertia of 
feeling — or anaesthesia of the heart. 



Escapism and Catharsis 



Illusion, then, is the simultaneous presence and interaction in the mind 
of two universes, one real, one imaginary. It transports the spectator 
from the trivial present to a plane remote from self-interest and makes 
him forget his own preoccupations and anxieties; in other words, it 
facilitates the unfolding of his participatory emotions, and inhibits 
or neutralizes his self-asserting tendencies. 

This sounds like an escapist theory of art; and in spite of its deroga- 
tory connotations, the expression contains a grain of truth— though no 
more than a grain. The analysis of any aesthetic experience requires, 
as said before, a series of steps; and the escape offered by transporting 
the spectator from his bed-sitter in Bays water to the Castle of Elsinore 
is merely the bottom step of the ladder. But, nevertheless, it should not 
be under-estimated. In the first place, if illusion offers escape it is 
escape of a particular kind, sharply distinguished from other dis- 
tractions such as playing tennis or bingo. It teaches us to live on two 
planes at once. Children and primitive audiences who, forgetting the 
present, completely accept the reality of the events on the stage, are 
experiencing not an aesthetic thrill, but a kind of hypnotic trance; and 
addiction to it may lead to various degrees of estrangement from 
reality. The aesthetic experience depends on that delicate balance 
arising from the presence of both matrices in the mind; on perceiving 
the hero as Laurence Olivier and Prince Hamlet of Denmark at one 
and the same time; on the lightning oscillations of attention from one 
to the other, like sparks between charged electrodes. It is this precarious 
suspension of awareness between the two planes which facilitates the 
continuous flux of emotion from the Now and Here to the remoter 
worlds of Then and There, and the cathartic effects resulting from it. 
For when interest is deflected from the self it will attach itself to some- 
thing else; when the level of self-assertive tension falls, the self-trans- 
cending impulses become almost automatically dominant. Thus the 
creation of illusion is in itself of cathartic value — even if the product, 
judged by more sophisticated standards, is of cheap quality; for it 
helps the subject to actualize his potential of self-transcending emotions 
thwarted by the dreary routines of existence. Liberated from his 
frustrations and anxieties, man can turn into a rather nice and dreamy 
creature; when he changes intd a dark suit and sits in a theatre, he at 
once shows himself capable of taking a strong and entirely unselfish 
interest in the destinies of the personae on the stage. He participates 

306 



ILLUSION 



307 



in their hopes and sufferings; his frustrated cravings for communion 
find their primeval outlet in the magic of identification. 

To revert to Aristotle, the cathartic function of the tragedy is 
'through incidents arousing horror and pity to accomplish the purga- 
tion of such emotions'. la cruder terms, a good cry, like a good laugh, 
has a more lasting after-effect than the occasion seems to warrant. 
Taking the Aristotelian definition at face value, it would seem that 
the aesthetic experience could purge the mind only of those emotions 
which the stage-play has created; that it would merely take out of the 
nervous system what it has just put in, leaving the mind in the same 
state as before. But this is not so. The emotion is not created, but 
merely stimulated by the actors; it must be worked up* by the spec- 
tator. The work of art does not provide the current, like an electricity 
company, but merely the installations; the current has to be generated 
by the consumer. Although this is obvious once we remember it, we 
tend to fall into the mistake of taking a metaphor at face value and 
believing that the stage 'provides* us with a thrill against cash payment 
for a seat in the stalls. What we buy, however, is not emotion, but a 
sequence of stimuli cunningly designed to trigger off our latent par- 
ticipatory emotions which otherwise would remain frustrated or look 
for coarser outlets, and to assure their ultimate consummation. Life 
constantly generates tensions which run through the mind like stray 
eddies and erratic currents. The aesthetic experience inhibits some, 
canalizes others, but above all, it draws on unconscious sources of 
emotion which otherwise are only active in the games of the under- 
ground. 

Thus the concept of catharsis assumes a twofold meaning. Firstly, it 
signifies that concentration on the illusory events on the stage rids the 
mind of the dross of its self-centred trivial preoccupations; in the 
second place it arouses its dormant self-transcendent potentials and 
provides them with an outlet, until they peacefully ebb away. Peaceful, 
of course, does not necessarily mean a happy ending. It may mean the 
'earthing' of an individual tragedy in the universal tragedy of the 
human condition— as the scientist resolves a problem by showing that 
a particular phenomenon is an instance of a general law. It may dis- 
solve the bitterness of personal sorrow in the vastness of the oceanic 
feeling; and redeem horror by pity. Tragedy, in the Greek sense, is 
the school of self-transcendence. 



Identification and Magic 



The projections of a single cine-camera with its rotating Maltese cross 
arouse anger, terror, and righteous indignation in up to five successive 
audiences on a single day, as if it were a machine designed for the 
wholesale manufacture of adrenalin. Yet the emotions aroused even 
by a cheap rariller-fum are vicarious emotions derived from one of 
the primordial games of the underground: the transformation of one 
person or object into another (Chapter VIII, p. 187 £). The fear and 
anger experienced by the audience is experienced on behalf of another 
person; the adrenalin secreted into their bloodstream is secreted to 
provide another person with excess energy for fight or flight; the 
magic of identification is at work. 

It enters into illusion in two stages. The first is the partial identi- 
fication, in the spectator's mind, of the actor with the character he is 
meant to represent; the second is the partial identification of the spec- 
tator with one or several of the characters. In both cases the identifica- 
tion is only partial, but nevertheless the magic is powerful enough to 
provide the palpitations and activate the supra-renal glands. And when 
I speak of magic, I am not speaking metaphorically; the 'magic of the 
stage* is a cliche which originates in the sympathetic magic practised 
by all primitive and not-so-primitive cultures, rooted in the belief in 
the substantial identity of the masked dancer with the demon he mimes; 
of the impersonator with the power he impersonates. The uncon- 
scious self, manifested in the beliefs of the child and the dreams of the 
adult, is, as we saw, immune to contradiction, unsure of its identity, 
and prone to merging it with others'. 'In the collective representations 
of primitive mentality, objects, beings, events can be, though in a way 
incomprehensible to us, both themselves and something other than 
themselves/ 2 This description of tribal mentality by a Victorian 
anthropologist could be applied almost without qualifications to the 
audiences of Coronation Street. 

I have taken a short-cut from primitive to contemporary magic, but 
the development is in fact historically continuous: the latter is a direct 
descendant of the former. Dramatic art has its origin in ceremonial 
rites— dances, songs, and mime—which enacted important past or 
desired future events: rain, a successful hunt, an abundant harvest. 
The gods, demons, ancestors and animals participating in the event 
were impersonated with the aid of masks, costumes, tattooings and 
make-up. The shaman who danced the part of the rain-god was the 

308 



ILLUSION 



309 



rain-god, and yet remained the shaman at the same time. From the 
stag dances of the Huichol Indians or the serpent dances of the Zuni, 
there is only one step to the goat dance of the Achacans, the precursor 
of Greek drama. 'Tragedy' means 'goat-song' (traoos — he goat, tide — 
song); it probably originated in the ceremonial rites in honour of 
Dyonysius, where the performers were disguised in goat-skins as 
satyrs, and in the related ceremonies in honour of Apollo and Demeter. 
Indian and Chinese stage craft have similarly religious origins. Etruscan 
drama derived from funeral rites; modern European drama evolved 
from the medieval mystery plays performed on the occasion of the 
main church festivals. But though the modem theatre hardly betrays 
its religious ancestry, the magic of illusion still serves essentially the 
same emotional needs: it enables the spectator to transcend the narrow 
confines of his personal identity, and to participate in other forms of 
existence. For — to quote for a last time the unfashionable Levy-Bruhl, 
to whom Freud, Jung, and others owe so much: 

The need of participation remains something more imperious and 
intense, even among people like ourselves, than the thirst for know- 
ledge and the desire for conformity with the claims of reason. It lies 
deeper in us and its source is more remote. During the long pre- 
historic ages, when the claims of reason were scarcely realized or 
even perceived, it was no doubt all-powerful in all human aggregates. 
Even today the mental activity which, by virtue of an intimate 
participation, possesses its object, gives it life and lives through it — 
finds entire satisfaction in this possession. 8 

The Dawn of Literature 

The dawn of literature, too, was bathed in the twilight of mysticism 
and mythology. 'The recitation of the Homeric poems on the Pana- 
thanaea corresponds to the recitation elsewhere of the sacred texts in 
the temple; the statement of Phemios that a god inspired his soul with 
all the varied ways of song expresses the ordinary belief of early 
historical times.* 4 But the earliest literati — priests, prophets, rhapsodes, 
bards — had less direct means to impress their audiences than their 
older colleagues, the masked and painted illusion-mongers. They had 
to 'dramatize' their tales, by techniques which we can only infer from 
hints. The dramatization of an epic recital aims, like stage-craft from 



3io 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



which it is derived, at creating, to some extent at least, the illusion that 
the events told arc happening now and here. Perhaps the oldest of these 
techniques is the use of direct speech, to make the audience believe 
that it is listening not to the narrator but to the characters themselves; 
its use is still as frequent in the modern novel as it was in the Homeric 
epos. In the ancient forms of oral recital it was supplemented by 
imitation of Voice and gesture— another tradition still alive in the 
nursery room. The minstrels and troubadours, the joculators or 
jugglers, the scops and the chansonniers de geste, were direct descendants 
of the Roman mimes — actors who, having lost their livelihood when 
the Roman theatre decayed, became vagabonds and diverted their 
patrons with dancing, tumbling, juggling and recitals as much acted 
as told. The early minstrels were called histriones, stage-players; the 
bard Taillefer, who sang the Chanson de Roland during the battle of 
Hastings, is described as a histrion or mimus. 

There is hardly a novelist who had not wished at times that he were 
a histrion, and could convey by direct voice, grimace, and gesture what 
his characters look like and feel. But writers have evolved other 
techniques to create the illusion that their characters are alive, and to 
make their audience fell in love with a heroine who exists only as 
printer's ink on paper. The real tears shed over Anna Karenina or 
Emma Bovary are the ultimate triumph of sympathetic magic. 



I 



XVI 

RHYTHM AND RHYME 

Pulsation 

The effect of the rhythm of a poem, wrote I. A. Richards, 'is 
not due to our perceiving pattern in something outside us, 
but to our becoming patterned ourselves 1 . 1 Rhythmic perio- 
dicity is a fundamental characteristic of life. All automatic functions of 
the body are patterned by rhythmic pulsations: heart-beat, respiration, 
peristalsis, brain-waves are merely the most obvious ones. For there is 
also an inherent tendency in some parts of the nervous system, par- 
ticularly on its phylogenetically older levels, to burst into spontaneous 
activity when released from the inhibitory control of the higher centres 
by brain-damage, toxic states, or by patterns of stimuli acting as 
triggers. 

Perhaps the most striking example of such a trigger-effect is the 
experimental induction of fits in epileptic patients by shining a bright 
flickering light into their eyes, where the frequency of the flicker 
is made to correspond to a characteristic frequency in the patient's 
electro-encephalogram. This, of course, is an extreme example of a 
trigger-effect by direct physiological stimulation; moreover, the in- 
coming rhythm is synchronized with an inner rhythm to produce an 
unholy resonance effect. The convulsions of voodoo-dancers, on the 
other hand, which have been compared to epileptic fits, are certainly 
not caused by the rhythmic beat of the tom-tom alone; other factors, 
of a psychological nature, must be present to produce the effect. But 
it is nevertheless true that our remarkable responsiveness to rhyth- 
mically patterned stimuli and our readiness 'to become patterned our- 
selves' arises from the depths of the nervous system, from those archaic 
strata of the unconscious which reverberate to the shaman's drum. 

Needless to say, even the contemporary Rock- n -Roll or Twist are 
restrained and sublimated displays compared to the St. Vitus's dance 

311 



312 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



which spread as an infectious form of hysteria through medieval 
Europe, Likewise, if rhythm in poetry is meant, as Yeats said, 'to lull 
the mind into a waking trance', that entrancement carries only a faint, 
remote echo of the incantative power of the muezzin's call, or of the 
recitation of the Homeric poems on the Panathanaea. On the other 
hand, we do experience a common kind of 'waking trance' when we 
keep repeating a silly phrase to the rhythm of the wheels of a railway 
carnage; hypnotists used to rely on metronomes, flickering candles, 
monotonously repeated orders or passes; and the rocking motions 
accompanying the prayers of Oriental religions and mystic sects serve 
the same purpose. Thus experience, both of the exalted and trivial 
kind, indicates that the mind is particularly receptive to and suggestible 
by messages which arrive in a rhythmic pattern, or accompanied by a 
rhythmic pattern. 

This is true even on the elementary levels of perception. We are 
more susceptible to musical tones than to noises, because the former 
consist of periodical, the latter of a-periodical air-waves. Similar con- 
siderations apply to pure colours; or to the symmetry and balance 
which lend a design its 'unity in diversity'. Plato decreed that all 
heavenly motions must take place in perfect circles at uniform speed, 
because only such regular periodicity could assure the steady, eternal 
pulsations of the universe. Perhaps the compulsive pattern-walking 
ritual of certain neurotics, who must always step into the centre of 
pavement-stones, is motivated by the same unconscious craving for 
order and regularity as a protection against the anxiety-arousing threat 
of change. 

Measure and Meaning 

'The superimposition of two systems: thought and metre,' wrote 
Proust, 'is a primary element of ordered complexity, that is to say, of 
beauty/ 2 But this superimposition — in our jargon, the bisociation of 
rhythm and meaning— is again trivalent: it can be put to poetic, 
scientific, or comic use. When rhythm assumes a rigidly repetitive 
form, it no longer recalls the pulsation of life, but the motions of an 
automaton; its superimposition on human behaviour is degrading, and 
yields Bergson s formula of the comic: the mechanical encrusted on 
the living. But here again, all depends on one's emotional attitude: 
pre-war films of German soldiers marching the goose-step — or if it 



RHYTHM AND RHYME 



313 



comes to that, the changing of the Guard at Buckingham Palace — 
will strike one spectator as comic, and appeal to the tribal, or romantic, 
emotions of another. Once one is in a marching column, it is extremely 
difficult to keep out of step; one has become patterned by the rhythmic 
motion in which one participates. But the comedian as an army recruit 
falling chronically out of step is comic, for obvious reasons. 

In the natural sciences, the analysis of rhythmic periodicities — the 
numerical patterns underlying the phenomena of naive experience — 
play a dominant part. The Pythagoreans regarded the universe as a 
large musical box, the organism as a well-tempered instrument, and 
all material phenomena as a dance of numbers. The metre of the poet, 
the metronome of the musician, the centimetre of the mathematician, 
are all derived from the same root, metron: measure, measurement. Yet 
the quantitative patterns in themselves would be meaningless to us if 
they were not accompanied by the sensory qualities of colour, sound, 
heat, taste, texture, and so on; and the rhythms of our brain-waves on 
the electro-encephalogram would be meaningless if we were not con- 
scious of thinking. The scientist takes a 'bi-focaT view of life; and so 
does the reader whose attention is focussed simultaneously both on the 
measure and the message of the poem. 

Without the message, the rhythm is of course meaningless, in poetry 
as in science. A monotonous rhythm, for instance, can be either sleepy- 
making or exciting, according to the message which it carries. Rhyth- 
mic stroking of the skin may be soothing or sexually exciting — it 
depends on the message. The rhythmic rattle of the wheels on a train 
journey will lull one to sleep, as a superior form of counting sheep, if 
one is in a relaxed mood; but I can remember at least one ghastly 
journey, when I found myself in a predicament of my own making, 
and the wheels kept repeating, 'I told you so, I told 'you so, I told you so* 
with such hallucinatory clarity and insistence that I found it difBcult to 
convince myself that the other passengers in the compartment did not 
hear it. Rhythm penetrates so deeply into the unconscious strata that 
it makes us suggestible even to self-addressed messages— from the 
Yogic recitation of mantras to Coue's 'every day in every way . . .\ 

However, unlike the beat of the tom-tom, or the rattle of the car- 
riage wheels, a strophe of verse does not consist in a simple repetitive 
rhythm, but in complex patterns of short and long, stressed and light 
syllables, farther complicated by super-imposed patterns of assonance 
or rhyme. As music has evolved a long way from the simple, repetitive 



314 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



figures of rnonochords and drums, so the various metric forms in poetry 
contain their substructure of rhythmic pulsation in an implied, and no 
longer in an explicit form. In free verse, the rhythmic substructure has 
become so implicit, as to go sometimes unnoticed. 

This development from the explicit to the implicit, from the direct 
statement to the veiled hint, is a phenomenon which we have already 
met (pp 84 fF.), and shall meet again in other provinces of art, as a 
characteristic factor in the evolution of creative techniques in general. 

Repetition and Affinity 

The rhyme is a relatively late offspring of rhythm. Both words are 
derived from the same Greek root, rhutmos; up to the sixteenth century 
they were treated as practically synonymous. Metric patterns based 
exclusively on the regular succession of ups and downs of intonation — 
the only form of verse in Greek and Latin poetry— were later com- 
bined with patterns based on the repetition of single consonants and 
vowels; and thus, via alliteration and assonance, the rhyme came into 
being — as melody was born out of originally unmodulated, rhythmic 
beats. 

But although conscious rhyming was only admitted into formal 
literature in the Middle Ages (at first as the internal rhyme in Leonine 
verse), it has, like rhythm, its primordial roots in the unconscious. The 
repetition of syllables is a conspicuous phenomenon at the very origins 
of language. In the early stages of learning to speak, children seem to 
have an irresistible impulse to jabber repetitive variations of sound 
patterns—from ma-ma and pa-pa to obble-gobble, rninky-pinky and 
so on ad infinitum; gibble-gabble was the Victorian word for it. Simi- 
larly, in many primitive languages as far apart as Polynesian and Bantu, 
words like Kala-Kak or Moku-Moku abound; and why does the 
name Humpty-Durnpty hold such a charm for child and adult 
alike? 

Next to repetition, association by sound affinity — punning — is one of 
die notorious games of the underground, manifested in dreams, in 
the punning mania of children, and in mental disorders. The rhyme is 
nothing but a glorified pun — two strings of ideas tied in an accoustic 
knot. In normal, rationally controlled speech, association by pure sound 
is prohibited, for, if given free rein, it would destroy coherence and 
meaning. Thus, on re-reading the previous sentence, it occurs to me 



RHYTHM AND RHYME 



315 



that 'des-troy' lends itself to a pun (Helen was fated to destroy Troy); 
once one 'tunes in* to the matrix of sound-associations, a number of 
quite idiotic puns and rhymes will invade the mind. No effort is 
required to produce them; on the contrary, when concentration flags, 
and the rational controls are relaxed, thinking has a tendency to revert, 
by its own gravity as it were, to matrices governed by more primitive 
rules of the game. Among these, association by sound-affinities plays 
a prominent part; the free associations of the patient on the analyst's 
couch belong as often as not to this category. Let us also remember 
(pp. 186 f.) that other games based on sound-affinity have exercised a 
perennial attraction on the most varied cultures; anagrams, acrostics, 
and word-puzzles; incantations and verbal spells; hermeneutics and 
Cabala, which interpreted the Scriptures as a collection of the 
Almighty's hidden puns, combining letter-lore with number-lore. 

Thus rhythm and assonance, pun and rhyme are not artificially 
created ornaments of speech; the whole evidence indicates that their 
origins go back to primitive — and infantile — forms of thought and 
utterance, in which sound and meaning are magically interwoven, and 
association by sound-affinities is as legitimate as association based on 
other similarities. Rationality demands that these matrices should be 
relegated underground, but they make their presence felt in sleep and 
sleeplike states, in mental illness and in the temporary regression — the 
reculer-pour-mieux-sauter — of poetic inspiration. But before we come to 
that, let me once more quote additional evidence from neurology, 
more precisely, from brain surgery — a field rarely bisociated with the 
poetic faculty. 



Compulsive Punning 

The phenomenon to be described is known as 'Forster's syndrome'. It 
was first observed by Forster, a German surgeon, in 1929, when he was 
operating on a patient sufFering from a tumour in the third ventricle — 
a small cavity deep down in the phylogenetically ancient regions of 
the mid-brain, adjacent to structures intimately concerned with the 
arousal of emotions. When the surgeon began to manipulate the 
tumour, affecting those sensitive structures, the (conscious) patient 
burst into a manic flight of speech, 'quoting passages in Latin, Greek, 
and Hebrew. He exhibited typical sound associations, and with every 
word of the operator broke into a flight of ideas. Thus, on hearing the 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



operator ask for a Tupfer [tampon] he burst into "Tupfer . . . Tupfer, 
Hupfer, Hiipfer, hup/en Sie tnal . . On hearing the word Messer, he 
burst into "Messer, messer, Metzer, Sie sind ein Metzel, das ist ja ein 
Gemetzel, metzeln Sie dock nicht so messen Sie dock Sie messen ja nicht 
Hen Professor, projiteor, professus sum, profiteri" These manic responses 
were dependent on manipulation of the tumour and could be elicited 
only from the floor of the third ventricle.' 3 

FSrster's patient opened up a curious insight into the processes in 
the poet's brain— in an unexpectedly literal sense of the word. The 
first flight of ideas, Tupfer, Hupfer, etc—tampon, jumper, go and 
jump into the air' — has a gruesome kind of humour coming from a 
man tied face down to the operating table with his skull open. The 
second flight, translated, runs as follows: Messer, Metzer, etc. — 'Knife, 
butcher, you are a butcher in a butchery; truly this is a massacre 
[Gemetzel]; don't go on butchering [metzeln], take measurements 
[raewew] ; why don't you measure, Herr Professor, projiteor, professus sum' 
and so on. 

Thus the patient's apparently delirious punning and babbling con- 
vey a meaningful message to the surgeon — his fear of being butchered, 
and his entreaty that the surgeon should proceed by careful measure- 
ments, that is, in a more cautious, circumspect way. His train of 
thought seems to move under dual control. It is controlled by allitera- 
tion and assonance — for he has regressed to the level of sound-associa- 
tion and must abide by its rules. But it is also controlled by his inter- 
mittent, rational awareness of his situation on the operating table. 
Without this, his flight of words would become meaningless (and does 
so at times). Without the tyranny of the other code, he would address 
the surgeon in simple, sensible prose. As it is, he must serve both masters 
at the same time.* 

Let us take a blasphemous short-cut from patient to poet. We have 
seen that the creative act always involves a regression to earlier, more 
primitive levels in the mental hierarchy, while other processes continue 
simultaneously on the rational surface — a condition that reminds one 
of a skin-diver with a breathing-tube. (Needless to say, the exercise 
has its dangers: skin-divers are prone to fall victims to the *rapture of 
die deep' and tear their breathing-tubes off— the reader sans sauter of 
William Blake and so many others. A less fatal professional disease 
is the Bends, a punishment for attempting to live on two different 
levels at once.) 



Coaxing the Unconscious 



The capacity to regress, more or less at will, to the games of the 
underground, without losing contact with the surface, seems to be the 
essence of the poetic, and of any other form of creativity. 'God guard 
me from those thoughts men think/In the mind alone,/He that sings a 
lasting song/Thinks in a marrow bone* (Yeats); 

or, to quote A. E. Housman: 

... I could no more define poetry than a terrier can define a rat, 
but we both recognize the object by the symptoms which it pro- 
vokes in us. One of these symptoms was described in connection 
with another object by Eliphaz the Temanite: 'A spirit passed before 
my face: the hair of my flesh stood up/ Experience has taught me, 
when I am shaving of a morning, to keep watch over my thoughts, 
because, if a line of poetry strays into my memory, my skin bristles 
so that the razor ceases to act. This particular symptom is accom- 
panied by a shiver down the spine. ... I think that the production 
of poetry, in its first stage, is less an active than a passive and involun- 
tary process; and if I were obliged, not to define poetry, but to name 
the class of things to which it belongs, I should call it a secretion; 
whether a natural secretion, like turpentine in the fir, or a morbid 
secretion, like the pearl in the oyster. I have seldom written poetry 
unless I was rather out of health, and the experience, though pleasur- 
able, was generally agitating and exhausting. 4 

The next quotation, in a more academic vein, is from Paul Val£ry's 
A Course in Poetics (the italics are in the original): 

"When the mind is in question, everything is in question; all is dis- 
order, and every reaction against that disorder is of the same kind as 
itself. For the fact is that disorder is the condition of the mind's 
fertility 

. . . The constitution of poetry ... is rather mysterious. It is strange 
that one should exert himself to formulate a discourse which must 
simultaneously obey perfectly incongruous conditions: musical, 
rational, significant, and suggestive; conditions which require a con- 
tinuous and repeated connection between rhythm and syntax, 
between sound and sense. . . . 

317 



318 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



. . . There is a poetic language in which words are no longer the 
words of free practical usage. They are no longer held together by 
the same attractions; they are charged with two different values 
operating simultaneously and of equivalent importance: their sound 
and their instantaneous psychic effect. They remind us then of those 
complex numbers in geometry; the coupling of the phonetic variable 
with the semantic variable creates problems of extension and con- 
vergence which poets solve blindfold — but they solve them (and 
that is the essential thing), from time to time. 5 

The sceptical reader may object that all these metaphors about the 
blindfold poet thinking in his marrow-bones while secreting pearls 
like an oyster, reflect a too romantic view of the profession; and that 
I have put altogether too much emphasis on the role of the uncon- 
scious. The answer is partly to be found in the chapter on 'Thinking 
Aside', which shows that the unconscious is neither a romantic nor a 
mystic fancy, but a working concept in the absence of which nearly 
every event of mental life would have to be regarded as a miracle. 
There is nothing very romantic about the wheels of the railway carriage 
screaming 'I told you so'; it is simply an observed fact. 

In the second place, though unconscious processes cannot be 
governed by conscious volition, they can at least be coaxed into 
activity by certain tricks acquired at the price of a little patience. 
Friedrich Schiller learned to get himself into a creative frame of mind 
by smelling rotten apples, Turgenev by keeping his feet in a bucket 
of hot water, Balzac by drinking poisonous quantities of black coffee; 
for lesser mortals even a pipe or pacing up and down in the study 
might do. 

And lastly, there is the long process of conscious elaboration — of 
cutting, grinding, polishing the rough stone which inspiration has un- 
earthed. Here the range of variations from one writer to another — 
and from one work to another by the same writer— is as enormous 
as with the elaboration and formulation of a nuclear discovery' in 
science. An excellent account of this process is to be found in an essay, 
far too little known, by A. E. Housman from which I have already 
quoted: 

Having drunk a pint of beer at luncheon— beer is a sedative to the 
brain, and my afternoons are the least intellectual portion of my life — 
I would go out for a walk of two or three hours. As I went along, 



RHYTHM AND RHYME 



319 



thinking of nothing in particular, only looking at things around me 
and following the progress of the seasons, there would flow into my 
mind, with sudden and unaccountable emotion, sometimes a line or 
two of verse, sometimes a whole stanza at once, accompanied, not 
preceded, by a vague notion of the poem which they were destined 
to form part o£ Then there would usually be a lull of an hour or so, 
then perhaps the spring would bubble up again. I say bubble up, 
because, so far as I could make out, the source of the suggestions 
thus proffered to the brain was an abyss which I have already had 
occasion to mention, the pit of the stomach. When I got home I 
wrote them down, leaving gaps, and hoping that further inspiration 
might be forthcoming another day. Sometimes it was, if I took my 
w alks in a receptive and expectant frame of mind; but sometimes the 
poem had to be taken in hand and completed by the brain, which 
was apt to be a matter of trouble and anxiety, involving trial and 
disappointment, and sometimes ending in failure. I happen to 
remember distinctly the genesis of the piece which stands last in my 
first volume. Two of the stanzas, I do not say which, came into my 
head, just as they are printed, while I was crossing the corner of 
Hampstead Heath between the Spaniard's Inn and the footpath to 
Temple Fortune. A third stanza came with a little coaxing after 
tea. One more was needed, but it did not come: I had to turn to and 
compose it myself, and that was a laborious business, I wrote it 
thirteen times, and it was more than a twelvemonth before I got it 
right. 

NOTE 

To. p. 316. Less dramatic than Forster's syndrome but equally convincing 
were experiments by Luria and Vinagradova, which demonstrated that subjects 
who normally associated words by their meaning regressed to association by 
sound when they were made drowsy by chloral hydrate (Br. J. of Psychol, 
May, X9S9). 



■ 



XVII 
IMAGE 
The Hidden Analogy 

In Chapters VH-VHI I have spoken at length of the dose related- 
ness between the scientist seeing an analogy where nobody saw one 
before, and the poet's discovery of an original metaphor or simile. 
Both rely on the mediation of unconscious processes to provide the 
analogy. In the scientist's Eureka process two previously unconnected 
frames of reference are made to intersect, but the same description may 
be applied to the poet's trouvaille — the discovery of a felicitous poetic 
comparison. The difference between them is in the character of the 
'frames of reference', which in the first case are of a more abstract, in 
the second of a more sensuous nature; and the criteria of their validity 
differ accordingly. But the difference, as we have seen, is a matter of 
degrees; and often the two overlap. The discovery of perspective and 
fore-shortening, for instance, belongs to both geometrical science and 
representative art; it establishes formal analogies between two-dimen- 
sional and three-dimensional space, but at the same time a direct 
sensory impact. 

Here is another example which I have already mentioned — the 
account, by one of Freud's earlier biographers, of how the master 
suddenly hit upon the idea of the sublimation of instinct: 

It happened while he was looking at a cartoon in a humorous 
periodical which showed the career of a young girl in two subse- 
quent stages. In the first she was herding a flock of young geese with 
a stick, in the second she was shown as a governess directing a group 
of young girls with her parasol. The girls in the second picture were 
arranged exactly in the same groups as the goslings in the first. 1 

The two cartoons provided the hidden (though not all to deeply 
hidden) analogy for the Eureka process. But vice versa, the two 

320 



IMAGE 321 

cartoons may be regarded as a metaphorical illustration of it. The same 
reversibility applies to Kekule's snake and Faraday's cosmic lines of 
force. Lastly, on the third panel of the triptych, the governess or the 
snake can be turned into a joke — as was actually done by malicious 
contemporaries. 

Emotive Potentials 

Among the simplest metaphors are cross-references from one of the 
senses to another: a 'warm' colour, a 'sweet' voice, a 'sharp' light; the 
'blind lips* of Swinburne, the 'blind hands' of Blake. Such combina- 
tions of different sensory matrices lend a new richness or multi-dimen- 
sionality to experience so that, again with Swinburne, 'light is heard 
as music, music seen as light'. 

The aesthetic satisfaction derived from metaphor, imagery, and re- 
lated techniques (which I shall treat as a single category) depends on 
the emotive potential of the matrices which enter into the game. By 
emotive potential I mean the capacity of a matrix to generate and 
satisfy participatory emotions. This depends of course partly on indi- 
vidual factors, partly on the collective attitudes of different cultures, 
but also on objective factors: on the intrinsic 'calory value', as it were, 
of some associative contexts — mental diets the ingredients of which 
have, for instance, a religious or mythological flavour. 

On the simplest and most general level, the emotive potentials of 
the seiise-modalities — sight, sound, odour, touch — differ widely with 
different people. Robert Graves 2 has confessed that his favourite 
poems have 'without exception* a tactile quality. He quoted as an 
example for it the Early English: 

Cold blows the wind on my true love 
And a few small drops of rain — 

'where*, he comments, 'I feel the rain on my hands and hair rather 
than see it,' He goes on to say that he always liked Keats and dis- 
liked Shelley because 'the characteristic of Keats is, I find, his constant 
appeal to the sense of touch, while Shelley's appeal is as constantly to 
the sense of movement*. Graves's stimulating essay (published in 1925) 
ended with the suggestion that psychologists should engage in 'intense 
research' on this question; it is a pity that it has not been followed up. 
(My guess would be that more people than one suspects can smell 



322 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



poetry— but that, needless to say, is a generalization based on personal 
experience, for I can always smell the dust-cloud raised by the gallop- 
ing horses in a Western film; and the lines 'Cold blows the wind* 
convey to me mainly the fresh smell of the rainy wind and of True 
Love's wet hair.) 

However, granted such personal idiosyncrasies, man lives primarily 
by his eyes and ears. The emotive potentials of patterned sound I 
have already discussed; it adds to the virtues of language the dynamism 
of the dance, the melody of the song, and the magic of incantation. It 
may even happen that the magic makes us forget the message — as 
when (quoting Graves) people read Swinburne for the mere glorious 
rush of his verse, without any more regard for the words than will 
help to a vague scenic background'; and with Blake one often feels 
that the emotive calories generated by the matrix have burnt up the 
meaning. 

The Picture-strip 

Much the same could be said of the emotive power of some visual 
imagery— including Blake's own. We have seen (Chapter VII) that 
'thinking in pictures' dominates the manifestations of the unconscious 
in the dream, in hallucinatory states, but also in the creative work of 
scientists. In fact, the majority of mathematicians and physicists turned 
out to be Visionaries' in the literal sense — that is, visual, not verbal 
thinkers. 

But we have also seen that pictorial thinking is an earlier and more 
primitive form of mentation than conceptual thinking— in the evolu- 
tion of the individual as in that of the species. The language of children 
is 'picturesque* — again in the literal sense of the word; and the lan- 
gauge of primitives is 'like the unfolding of a picture strip, where each 
word expresses a pictorial image, regardless as to whether the picture 
signifies an object, an action, or a quality. Thus "to strike" and "a 
blow" are expressed by the same word. These languages are not merely 
deficient in the more abstract type of imagery, but in practically all 
higher grammatical construction (Kretschmer). 3 

Let me give a concrete example from Kretschmer's textbook, 
followed by the comments of that excellent German psychiatrist — 
whose work, comparable in importance to Jung's, is far too little 
known to the English-speaking public. The example is a simple story 
told in the Bushman language. It is about a Bushman who worked as 



IMAGE 



323 



a shepherd for a white man until the latter ill-treated him; whereupon 
the Bushman ran away, and the white man engaged another Bushman, 
to whom the same thing happened. Translated into Bushman language, 
this story is picturized as follows: 

Bushman-there-go, here-run-to-Whites, White-give-tobacco, 
Bushman-go-smoke, go-fiH-tobacco sack, White-give-meat-Bush- 
man, Bushman-go--eat-meat, get-up-go-home, go-merry, go-sit, 
graze-sheep Whites, White-go-strike-Bushman, Bushman-cry- 
much-pain, Bushman-go-run-away-Whites, White-run-after-Bush- 
man, Bushman-mere-omer-this-graze-sheep, Bushman-all-away. 

Kretschmer comments: 

The thought of primitive peoples allows of but little arrangement 
and condensation of separate images into abstract categories; but the 
sensory perceptions themselves, retained directly as such in memory, 
unwind themselves before us unchanged, like a long picture roll. 
The discrete visual image dominates the scene throughout, whilst 
the relation between the separate pictures is barely indicated. Logical 
connections are as yet quite tenuous and loose. If we wish to con- 
ceive of speech at a slightly lower level still, we shall have to dispense 
with even those slight hints of a syntax which are present; we shall 
then find that the thought-processes of a people using such a language 
would consist entirely of an asyntactical series of pictures. 

Some passages in die Old Testament seem to reflect the transition 
from predominantly pictorial to abstract thought: 

I returned, and saw under the sun, that the race is not to the swift, 
nor the batde to the strong, neither yet bread to the wise, nor yet 
riches to men of understanding, nor yet favour to men of skill; but 
time and chance happeneth to them all. (Ecclesiastes.) 

The tendency to stick to concrete visual images is still evident; but 
the characters in the picture-strip no longer represent individuals — the 
swift, the strong, the wise are collective nouns, abstracted universals. 
Incidentally, George Orwell once wrote a parody of this passage in 
modern academic jargon to highlight the contrast between vivid 
.imagery and desiccated abstraction: 



324 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Objective consideration of contemporary phenomena compels the 
conclusion that success or failure in competitive activities exhibits no 
tendency to be commensurate with innate capacity, but that a con- 
siderable element of the unpredictable must invariably be taken into 
account. 

While dreaming, even a paragon of normality regresses in time not 
merely to Ecclesiastes, but to the earlier mythological creations of the 
Babylonians and the visual concreteness of the Bushman's statements. 
But on awakening 'all the charm is broken, all that phantom world so 
fair, vanishes , — as at the call of the gentleman from Porlock. It may be 
just as well — the quick effacement from memory of the majority of 
our dreams may be a normal protective device of the mind (as distinct 
from pathological repression). In the hallucinatory psychoses, however, 
the regressions are more intense, realistic, enduring, and unforgettable 
in a painful sense; hence the remarkable affinities between the paint- 
ings of schizophrenics and primitive art. To quote Kretschmer again: 
'Schizophrenic symbols, like primitive and dream symbols, are the 
pictorial antecedents of concepts and are not developed beyond that 
stage/ He then relates the case of one of his patients, a gifted young 
man who, between periods of normality and abnormality, lived 
through a prolonged transitional phase, enlivened by what he csiJled 
his picture show': 

In these phases he passively experiences the outcropping of a mass 
of images which arise from abstract concepts, or which appear to 
exist in concrete objects. The images often 'resemble old Norse 
ornaments or Roman sculptures'; sometimes they are grotesque 
figures, sometimes sensible film-like scenes of knights and soldiers 
who occupy a real old castle which lies in the valley. Most interesting 
are the images which arise directly out of abstract thought. For 
example, he is reading a philosophical work of Kant, and as he reads, 
the abstract thoughts are continuously converted into imagery. 
"Whilst reading Kant on the question of the infinity of space he had 
the following experience: "The pictures crowded on me— towers, 
circles behind circles, a cylinder which thrust itself obliquely into the 
whole picture. Everything is showing movement and growth; the 
circle acquires depth and thus becomes cylindrical; the towers 
become higher and higher; everything is arbitrary as in an experi- 
mental picture or a dream.' 



IMAGE 



325 



In case-histories like this we see the extreme development of ten- 
dencies which on a moderate scale are present in the normal imagina- 
tive person; just as we saw in the punning and rhyming patient on the 
operating table the pathological extreme of the poet's urge to convey 
his meaning in rhythmic patterns. And just as rhythm is not an arti- 
ficial embellishment of language but a form of expression which pre- 
dates language, so visual images and symbols are not fanciful em- 
broideries of concepts, but precursors of conceptual thought. The 
artist does not climb a ladder to stick ornaments on a facade of ideas — 
he is more like a pot-holer in search of underground rivers. To quote 
Kretschmer for the last time: 'Such creative products of the artistic 
imagination tend to emerge from a psychic twilight, a state of lessened 
consciousness and diminished attentivity to external stimuli. Further, 
the condition is one of "absent-mindedness" with hypnoidal over- 
concentration on a single focus, providing an entirely passive experi- 
ence, frequently of a visual character, divorced from the categories of 
space and time, and reason and will. These dreamlike phases of artistic 
creation evoke primitive phylogenetic tendencies towards rhythm and 
stylization with elemental violence; and the emergent images thus 
acquire in the very act of birth regular form and symmetry/ 



On Law and Order 

Some images seem to appeal more to the intellect than to emotion 
because of their logical and didactic character — but nevertheless evoke 
an emotive response: 

And how dieth the wise man? as the fool (Ecclesiastes) 

Golden lads and girls all must, 

As chimney-sweepers, come to dust. 

(Cymbeline) 

When Adam dolve and Eve span, 
Who was then a gentleman? 

(John Ball ?) 



Bach of these quotes may be described as a particular illustration of 
a general truth: the first and second affirm that all men must die, the 



326 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



third proclaims that all men are equal. If we wish to be pedantic, we 
can enumerate the various bisociative techniques which enter into 
them: sense and sound in the last two; or in the first two, me joining 
of habitually incompatible opposites in the focal concepts 'dying' and 
'dust'. We may further note die archaic, or archetypal, resonances of 
Adam, Eve, the sage, the fool, and the golden lads. Finally, the tech- 
nique of condensation and implication in the third quote poses a kind 
of naive riddle which enhances its effect. But when all these points are 
made, the main feature which the three quotes share remains their 
didactic intent of driving home a message, of demonstrating a universal 
law by means of concrete imagery. 

Now such reductions of particular instances to universal causes or 
abstract laws are supposed to represent a purely intellectual pastime 
which has nothing to do with art and emotion; in fact, however, they 
give rise to the most powerful emotional release. When John Ball 
exhorted the peasants at Blackheath to rise against their Lords, he ad- 
vertently chose 'When Adam dolve' as his text, because it enabled 
him to prove that their particular grievances were based on a Law 
ordained by the Creator: that there should be no privilege of birth. 
It is significant that this same text, with its indirect affirmation implied 
in a riddle, should have such an explosive effect— not only in England, 
but also during the peasant risings in Germany, where it became the 
marching song of the rebels ('Als Adam grub und Eva spann — Wo war 
da der Edelmann?'). Blake's 

There came a voice without reply — 
"lis man's perdition to be safe, 
When for the truth he ought to die, 

might serve as a motto for all appeals to the emotions which are ex- 
plained and justified by reference to divine law — the Voice Without 
Reply. 

The Will of God, or the Laws of Nature, as the organizing and har- 
monizing principle of the universe is one of the most powerful arche- 
types of human experience. No doubt it originates to a large part in 
feelings of insecurity, of cosmic anxiety, the need for protection — 
hence the reassurance and relief which are felt whenever a threatening 
or merely puzzling phenomenon can be Explained* as a manifestation 
of some universal law or divine order. For the opposite of order is 
chaos — which means unpredictability of events, absence of protection, 



IMAGE 



327 



exposure to the whims of incomprehensible forces. The emergence or 
order from chaos is a leitmotif of all mythologies; even the blood- 
thirsty goddesses of the Hindus and the choleric deities of the Pantheon 
provided a measure of reassurance, because they were moved by 
human passions which could be comprehended by the mind; so that 
everything that befell one was satisfactorily explained. 

Thus virtually any explanation — valid or not—which commands 
belief has a calming and cathartic effect. It can be observed on every 
level: from the sudden, smiling relief of the small child when some 
startling appearance is shown to be related to something familiar, and 
recognized as part of the general order of things — to the euphoria of 
the scientist, who has solved his problem. Even painful experiences 
are tempered with relief once they are recognized as particular in- 
stances of a general law. To lose a relative by a 'stupid accident' is more 
painful than to lose one 'kwfully', through old age or incurable illness. 
The only effective consolation in the face of death is that it is part of 
the cosmic order; if chimneysweepers were exempted from it, we 
should resent it very much indeed. The idea of 'blind chance* deciding 
our fate is intolerable; the mind abhors gaps in the lawful order as 
nature abhors the vacuum. 



On Truth and Beauty 

However, the reduction of the uncanny and vexing to the orderly and 
familiar, of the rustling of leaves in the dark forest to the whisper of 
fairies or the vibrations of compressed air— both equally reassuring — 
is merely the negative aspect of the power of explanation: relief from 
anxiety. Its positive aspect is epitomized in the Pythagorean belief 
that musical harmonies govern the motion of the stars. The myth of 
creation appeals not only to man's abhorrence of chaos, but also to his 
sense of wonder at the cosmic order: light is more than the absence of 
darkness, and law more than the absence of disorder. I have spoken 
repeatedly of that sense of 'oceanic wonder' — the most sublimated ex- 
pression of the self-transcending emotions — which is at the root of the 
scientist's quest for ultimate causes, and the artist's quest for the ulti- 
mate realities of experience. The sensation of 'marvellous clarity' which 
enraptured Kepler when he discovered his second law is snared by 
every artist when a strophe suddenly fells into what seems to be its 
predestined pattern, or when the felicitous image unfolds in the mind 



328 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



— the only one which can explain* by symbols the rationally unex- 
plainable — and express the inexpressible. 

Experiences of this kind, when something previously turbid be- 
comes suddenly transparent and permeated by light, are always 
accompanied by the sudden expansion and subsequent catharsis of the 
self-transcending emotions. I have called this the earthing' of emotion, 
on the analogy of earthing (or 'grounding') an electrically charged 
body, so that its tensions are drained by the immense current-absorb- 
ing capacity of mother earth'. The scientist attains catharsis through 
the reduction of phenomena to their primary causes; a disturbing par- 
ticular problem is mentally 'earthed* into the universal order. The 
same description applies to the artist, except that his 'primary causes' 
and 'laws of order' are differently constituted. They derive from 
mythology and magic, from the compulsive powers of rhythm and 
form, from archetypal symbols which arouse unconscious resonances. 
But their 'explanatory power', though not of a rational order, is 
emotionally as satisfying as that of the scientist's explanations; both 
mediate the 'earthing' of particular experiences into a universal frame; 
and the catharsis which follows scientific discovery or artistic trou- 
vaille has the same 'oceanic* quality. The melancholy charm of the 
golden lads who come to dust because that is the condition of man, is 
due to the 'earthing' of our personal predicaments in a universal 
predicament. Art, like religion, is a school of self-transcendence; it 
expands individual awareness into cosmic awareness, as science teaches 
us to reduce any particular puzzle to the great universal puzzle. 

"When Rembrandt had the audacity to paint the carcass of a flayed 
ox, he taught his public to see and accept behind the repulsive par- 
ticular object the timeless patterns of light, shadow, and colour. We 
have seen that the discoveries of art derive from the sudden transfer 
of attention from one matrix to another with a higher emotive poten- 
tial. The intellectual aspect of this Eureka process is closely akin to the 
scientist's — or the mystic's — 'spontaneous iHumraation*: the percep- 
tion of a familiar object or event in a new, significant, light; its emotive 
aspect is the rapt stillness of oceanic wonder. The two together— intellec- 
tual iQumination and emotional catharsis — are the essence of the 
aesthetic experience. The first constitutes the moment of truth; the 
second provides the experience of beauty. The two are complemen- 
tary aspects of an indivisible process— that 'earthing' process where 
'the infinite is made to blend itself with the finite, to stand visible, as it 
were, attainable there* (Carlyle). 



IMAGE 



329 



Every scientific discovery gives rise, in the connoisseur, to the ex- 
perience of beauty, because the solution of the problem creates har- 
mony out of dissonance; and vice versa, the experience of beauty can 
occur only if the intellect endorses the validity of the operation — 
whatever its nature— designed to elicit the experience. A virgin by 
Botticelli, and a mathematical theorem by Poincare, do not betray 
any similarity between the motivations or aspirations of their res- 
pective creators; the first seemed to aim at 'truth', the second at 
'beauty*. But it was Poincare who wrote that what guided him in his 
unconscious gropings towards the 'happy combinations' which yield 
new discoveries was 'the feeling of mathematical beauty, of the har- 
mony of number, of forms, of geometric elegance. This is a true 
aesthetic feeling thai all mathematicians know.' The greatest among 
mathematicians and scientists, from Kepler to Einstein, made similar 
confessions. 'Beauty is the first test; there is no permanent place in the 
world for ugly mathematics*, wrote G. H. Hardy in his classic, A 
Mathematician s Apology. Jacques Hadamard, whose pioneer work on 
the psychology of invention I have quoted, drew the final conclusion: 
'The sense of beauty as a "drive'* for discovery in our mathematical 
field, seems to be almost the only one/ And the laconic pronouncement 
of Dirac, addressed to his fellow-physicists, bears repeating: 'It is more 
important to have beauty in one's equations than to have them fit 
experiment/ 

If we now turn to the opposite camp, we find that painters and 
sculptors, not to mention architects, have always been guided, and 
often obsessed, by scientific and pseudo-scientific theories — the golden 
section, the secrets of perspective, Diirer's and Leonardo's 'ultimate 
laws* of proportion,* Cezanne's doctrine 'everything in nature is 
modelled on the sphere, the cone and the cylinder'; Braque's substitu- 
tion of cubes for spheres; the elaborate theorizings of the neo-impres- 
sionists; Le Corbusier's modulator theory based on the so-called 
Fibonacci sequence of numbers— the list could be continued endlessly. 
The counterpart to A Mathematician's Apology, which puts beauty 
before rational method, is Seurat's pronouncement (in a letter to a 
friend): 'They see poetry in what I have done. No, I apply my method, 
and that is all there is to it/ 

Both sides seem to be leaning over backwards: the artist to rationalize 
his creative processes, the scientist to irrationalize them, so to speak. But 
this fact in itself is significant. The scientist feels the urge to confess his 
indebtedness to unconscious intuitions which guide his theorizing; the 



330 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



artist values, or over-values, the theoretical discipline which controls 
his intuition. The two factors are complementary; the proportions in 
which they combine depend — other things being equal—foremost on 
the medium in which the creative drive finds its expression; and they 
shade into each other like the colours of the rainbow. 

The act of creation itself, as we have seen, is based on essentially the 
same underlying pattern in all ranges of the continuous rainbow spec- 
trum. But the criteria for judging the finished product differ of course 
from one medium to another. Though the psychological processes 
which led to the creation of Poincare's theorem and of Botticelli's 
virgin lie not as far apart as commonly assumed, the first can be 
rigorously verified by logical operations, the second not. There seems 
to be a crack in Keats's Grecian urn, and its message to sound rather 
hollow; but if we recall two essential points made earlier on, the crack 
will heal. 

The first is that verification comes only post factum, when the crea- 
tive act is completed; the act itself is always a leap into the dark, a dive 
into the deeps, and the diver is more likely to come up with a handful 
of mud than with a coral. False inspirations and freak theories are as 
abundant in the history of science as bad works of art; yet they com- 
mand in the victim's mind the same forceful conviction, the same 
euphoria, catharsis, and experience of beauty as those happy finds which 
are post factum proven right. Truth, as Kepler said, is an elusive hussy 
— who frequendy managed to fool even Galileo, Descartes, Leibniz, 
Pasteur, and Einstein, to mention only a few. In this respect, then, 
Poincare is in no better position than Botticelli: while in the throes of 
the creative process, guidance by truth is as uncertain and subjective as 
guidance by beauty. 

The second point refers to the verifiability of the product after the 
act; we have seen that even in this respect the contrast is not absolute, 
but a matter of degrees (Chapter X). A physical theory is far more 
open to verification than a work of art; but experiments, even so- 
called crucial experiments, are subject to interpretation; and the his- 
tory of science is to a large part a history of controversies, because the 
interpretation of facts to 'confirm' or refute* a theory always contains 
a subjective factor, dependent on the scientific fashions and prejudices 
of the period. There were indeed times in the history of most sciences 
when the interpretations of empirical data assumed a degree of sub- 
jectivity and arbitrariness compared to which literary criticism appeared 
almost to be an 'exact science'. 



IMAGE 



331 



I do not wish to exaggerate; there is certainly a considerable dif- 
ference, in precision and objectivity, between the methods of judging 
a theorem in physics and a work of art. But I wish to stress once more 
that there are continuous transitions between the two. The diagram 
on p. 332 shows one among many such continuous series. Even pure 
mathematics at the top of the series had its logical foundations shaken 
by paradoxes like Godel's theorem; or earlier on by Cantors theory 
of infinite aggregates (as a result of which Cantor was barred from 
promotion in all German universities, and the mathematical journals 
refused to publish his papers). Thus even in mathematics 'objective 
truth' and logical veriflability' are far from absolute. As we descend 
to atomic physics, the contradictions and controversial interpretation 
of data increase rapidly; and as we move further down the slope, 
through such hybrid domains as psychiatry, historiography, and biog- 
raphy, from the w T orld of Poincare towards that of Botticelli, the 
criteria of truth gradually change in character, become more avowedly 
subjective, more overtly dependent on the fashions of the time, and, 
above all, less amenable to abstract, verbal formulation. But neverthe- 
less the experience of truth, however subjective, must be present for 
the experience of beauty to arise; and vice versa, the solution of any 
of 'nature's riddles', however abstract, makes one exclaim 'how 
beautiful'. 

Thus, to heal the crack in the Grecian urn and to make it acceptable 
in this computer age we would have to improve on its wording (as 
Orwell did on Ecclesiastes): Beauty is a function of truth, truth a 
function of beauty. They can be separated by analysis, but in the lived 
experience of the creative act — and of its re-creative echo in the 
beholder — they are inseparable as thought is inseparable from emotion. 
They signal, one in the language of the brain, the other of the bowels, 
the moment of the Eureka cry, when 'the infinite is made to blend 
itself with the finite* — when eternity is looking through the window 
of time. Whether it is a medieval stained-glass window or Newton's 
equation of universal gravity is a matter of upbringing and chance; 
both are transparent to the unprejudiced eye. 



NOTES 

To p. $29. 'proportions op the human figure. 

'From the chin to the starting of the hair is a tenth part of the figure. 

'From the chin to the top of the head is an eighth part. 



333 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



'And from the chin to the nostrils is a third part of the face. 

*And the same from the nostrils to the eyebrows, and from the eyebrows to 
the starting of the hair. 

'If you set your legs so far apart as to take a fourteenth part from your height, 
and you open and raise your arms until you touch the line of the crown of the 
head with your middle fingers, you must know that the centre of the circle 
formed by the extremities of the outstretched limbs will be the navel, and the 
space between the legs will form an equilateral triangle. 

'The span of a man's outstretched arms is equal to his height/ (From Leonardo's 
Notebooks, quoted by R. Goldwater and M. Treves, cds., 1947, p. 51.) 



Figure 10 





'-Medicine 




'''..IfoveL 




subjective 



See text on pages 28, 331 



XVIII 
INFOLDING 



Iet me return once more to the three main criteria of the technical 
excellence of a comic work: its originality, emphasis, and 
-J economy; and let us see how far they are applicable to other 
forms of art. 



Originality and Emphasis 

From antiquity until well into the Renaissance artists thought, or pro- 
fessed to think, that they were copying nature; even Leonardo wrote 
into his notebook 'that painting is most praiseworthy which is most 
like the thing represented'. Of course, they were doing nothing of the 
sort. They were creating, as Plato had reproached them, 'man-made 
dreams for those who are awake'. The thing represented had to pass 
through two distorting lenses: the artist's mind, and his medium of 
expression, before it emerged as a man-made dream — the two, of 
course, being intimately connected and interacting with each other. 

To start with the medium: the space of the painter's canvas is smaller 
than the landscape to be copied, and his pigment is different from the 
colours he sees; the writer's ink cannot render a voice nor exhale the 
smell of a rose. The nature of the medium always excludes direct 
imitation. Some aspects of experience cannot be reproduced at all; 
some only by gross oversimplification or distortion; and some only at 
the price of sacrificing others. The limitations and peculiarities of his 
medium force the artist at each step to make choices, consciously or un- 
consciously; to select for representation those features or aspects which 
he considers to be relevant, and to discard those which he considers 
irrelevant. Thus we meet again the trinity of selection, exaggeration, 
and simplification which I have discussed before (pp. 82-6; 263 £). Even 

333 



334 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the most naturalistic picture, chronicle, or novel, whose maker naively 
hopes to copy reality, contains an unavoidable element of bias, of 
selective emphasis. Its direction depends on the distorting lenses in the 
artist's mind — the perceptual and conceptual matrices which pattern 
his experience, and determine which aspects of it should be regarded 
as relevant, which not. This part-automatic, part-conscious processing 
of the experience, over which the medium exercises a kind of 'feed- 
back-control', determines to a large extent what we call an artist's 
individual style. 

Theoretically, the range of choice before him is enormous. In 
practice, it is narrowed down considerably by the conventions of his 
period or school. They are imposed on him not only by external 
pressures — the public's taste and the critics' censure — but mainly from 
inside. The controls of skilled activities function, as we saw, below the 
level of awareness on which that activity takes place — whether it con- 
sists in riding a bicycle or 'taking in' a landscape. The codes which 
govern the matrices of perception are hidden persuaders; their in- 
fluence permeates the whole personality, shapes his pattern of vision, 
determines which aspects of reality should be considered significant, 
while others are ignored, like the ticking of one's watch. For centuries 
painters did not seem to have noticed that shadows have colours, nor 
the fluidity of contours in hazy air; and if we were to add up those 
aspects of existence which literature has ignored at one time or another, 
they would cover practically the whole range of human experience. 
Conversely, every period over-emphasizes some particular aspects of 
experience and produces its special brand of 'stylization and compul- 
sive mannerisms — obvious to all but itself. For instance, the emphasis 
on contour in classical painting is still so firmly embedded in our frames 
of perception that we are unaware of the impossibility of seeing fore- 
ground figure and background landscape simultaneously in sharp 
focus. But we are aware of the absence of shadows in Chinese painting 
—or the absence of sex in Victorian fiction. 

The measure of an artist's originality, put into the simplest terms, is 
the extent to which his selective emphasis deviates from the conven- 
tional norm and establishes new standards of relevance. All great in- 
novations, which inaugurate a new era, movement, or school, consist 
in such sudden shifts of attention and displacements of emphasis onto 
some previously neglected aspect of experience, some blacked-out 
range of the existential spectrum. The decisive turning points in the 
history of every art-form are discoveries which show the characteristic 



INFOLDING 



335 



features already discussed: they uncover what has always been there; 
they are 'revolutionary', that is, destructive and constructive; they 
compel us to revalue our values and impose a new set of rules on 
the eternal game. 

Most of the general considerations in the chapter on 'The Evolution 
of Ideas' equally apply to Revolution of art. In both fields the truly 
original geniuses are rare compared with the enormous number of 
talented practitioners; the former acting as spearheads, opening up new 
territories, which the latter will then diligently cultivate. In both 
fields there are periods of crisis, of 'creative anarchy', leading to a 
break-through to new frontiers — followed by decades, or centuries of 
consolidation, orthodoxy, stagnation, and decadence — until a new 
crisis arises, a holy discontent, which starts the cycle again. Other 
parallels could be drawn: multiple discoveries* — the simultaneous 
emergence of a new style, for which the time is ripe, independently in 
several places; 'collective discoveries' originating in a closely knit 
group, clique, school, or team; 'rediscoveries* — the periodic revivals of 
past and forgotten forms of art; lastly 'cross-fertilizations' between 
seemingly distant provinces of science and art. To quote a single 
example: the rediscovery of the treatise on conic sections by Apol- 
lonius of Perga, dating from the fourth century B.C., gave the ellipse 
to Kepler who built on it a new astronomy — and to Guarini, who 
introduced new vistas into architecture. 



Economy 

Yesterday's discoveries are today's commonplaces; a daringly fresh 
image soon becomes stale by repetition, degenerates into a cliche, and 
loses its emotive appeal. The newborn day or the piercing cry are no 
longer even perceived as metaphorical: the once separate contexts of 
birth and dawn have merged, there is no juxtaposition — reverting to 
jargon, bisociative dynamism has been converted into associative 
routine. 

The recurrent cycles of stagnation, crisis, and new departure in the 
arts are to a large extent caused by the gradual saturation which any 
particular invention or technique produces in artist and audience. A 
child or a savage, who is taken to the cinema for the first time, derives 
wonder and delight not so much from the context of the film as from 
the magic of illusion as such. In the sophisticated theatre-goer's mind, 



33°" 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



illusion in itself plays a relatively subordinate part— except when, 
watching a thriller, he regresses to infancy; the two matrices have 
become virtually integrated into one, so that he is capable of thinking 
critically of the quality of the acting and of appreciating at the same 
time the merits of the play. But to recapture the erstwhile magic, in all 
its freshness, he must turn to something new: experimental theatre, 
avant-garde films, or Japanese KabuH, perhaps; novel experiences 
which compel him to strain his imagination, in order to make sense of 
the seemingly absurd — to participate, and re-create. 

When the styles and techniques of an art have become conventiona- 
lized and stagnant, the audience is exempted from the necessity to 
exert its intelligence and imagination — and deprived of its reward. 
The 'consumer' reads the conventional novel, looks at the conventional 
landscape, and watches the conventional play with perfect ease and 
self-assurance — and a complete absence of awe and wonder. He pre- 
fers the familiar to the unfamiliar, because it presents no challenge and 
demands no creative effort. Art becomes a mildly pleasant pastime and 
loses its emotive impact, its transcendental appeal and cathartic effect. 
The artist, in growing frustration, senses that the conventional tech- 
niques have become 'stale*, that they have lost their power over the 
audience, and become inadequate as means of communication and 
self-expression. Of course the technique itself cannot become 'stale': 
blank verse has the same rhythmic qualities today as it had three cen- 
turies ago; Fragonard's nymphs and shepherds are as delightful as 
ever, but they dance no more. We have become immunized against 
their emotional appeal — at least for the time being. We may again 
become susceptible to them at the next romantic revival, at some 
future turn of the spiral. 

The history of art could be written in terms of the artist's struggle 
against the deadening cumulative effect of saturation. The way out of 
the cul-de-sac is either a revolutionary departure towards new horizons, 
or the rediscovery of past techniques, or a combination of both. 
(Egyptian art went through a revival of archaic styles under the 
twenty-sixth dynasty, in the seventh century B.C.; Rome had a Renais- 
sance of sorts in the second century a.d. when Hadrian built his 
Athenaeum; and so on to the pre-Raphaelites and the relatively recent 
rediscovery of primitive art.) 

But in between these dramatic turning points one can observe a 
more gradual evolution of styles which seems to proceed in two 
opposite directions— both intended to counteract saturation. One is a 



INFOLDING 



337 



tread towards more pointed emphasis; the other towards more economy 
or implicitness. The first strives to recapture the artist's waning mastery 
over the audience by providing a spicier fare for jaded appetites: 
exaggerated mannerisms, frills, flamboyance, an overly explicit appeal 
to me emotions, 'rubbing it in* — symptoms of decadence and im- 
potence, which need not concern us further. The opposite trend is 
towards economy and implicitness in the sense previously defined 
(p. 82 et seq.); it has been eloquently described by Mallarme in a passage 
which outlined the programme of the French symbolist movement: 

Je pense qu'il faut quil n y ait qu allusion. La contemplation des 
objets, 1' image s'envolant des reveries sucitees par eux, sont le chant: 
les Parnassiens, eux, prennent la chose entierement et la montrent; 
par la il manquent de mystere; ils retirent aux esprits cette pie 
dilicieuse de croire quits creent. Nommer un objet, e'est supprimer les 
trois quarts de la jouissance du poeme, qui est fait du bonheur de 
deviner peu a peu: le suggerer, voila le reve. C'est le parfait usage 
de ce mystere qui constitue le symbol: evoquer petit a petit un 
objet pour montrer un etat d'ame, ou, inversement, choisir un 
objet et en degager un etat d'£me, par une serie de dechiffrements. . . . 

(Enquete sur Involution Litteraire.) 
(It seems to me that there should be only allusions. The contempla- 
tion of objects, the volatile image of the dreams they evoke, these make 
the song: the Parnassians [the classicist movement of Leconte de Lisle, 
Heredia, etc.] who make a complete demonstration of the object 
thereby lack mystery; they deprive the [reader's] mind of that delicious joy 
of imagining that it creates. To name the thing means forsaking three 
quarters of a poem's enjoyment — which is derived from unravelling it 
gradually, by happy guesswork: to suggest the thing creates the dream* 
Symbols are formed when this secret is used to perfection: to evoke 
little by little, the image of an object in order to demonstrate a mood; 
or, conversely, to choose an object and to extract from it a mood, by 
a series of decipherings.) 

However, it was not the French symbolists who invented the trend 
from the explicit statement to the implicit hint, from the obvious to 
the allusive and oblique; it is as old as art itself. All mythology is 
studded with symbols, veiled in allegory; the parables of Christ pose 
riddles which the audience must solve. The intention is not to obscure 
the message, but to make it more luminous by compelling the recipient 
to work it out by himself— to re-create it. Hence the message must be 



338 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



banded to him in implied form — and implied means 'folded in. To 
make it unfold, he must fill in the gaps, complete the hint, see through 
the symbolic disguise. But the audience has a tendency to become more 
sophisticated witb time; once it has mastered all the tricks, the excite- 
ment goes out of the game; so the message must be made more im- 
plicit, more tightly folded. I believe that this development towards 
greater economy (meaning not brevity, but implicitness) can be traced 
in virtually all periods and forms of art. To indulge in a little law- 
making, let me call it the 'law of infolding*. It is the antidote to the 
law of diminishing returns in the domain of the emotions. 

Greek tragedy, as far as we can tell, starts with the 'goat song', 
derived from the worshipful ceremonies in honour of Bacchus- 
Dionysius. These in turn originate even further back in the past, in 
rituals accompanied by human sacrifice, which the Bacchantae enacted 
in symbolic ways, that is, by implication; their traces can still be found 
in Euripides. At some stage, the epic recital of events branched off 
from their direct representation by actors in disguise. The early bards 
were probably still impersonating their heroes by voice and gesture, as 
the mimes and histriones did in medieval days; but economy demanded 
that histrionics be banned from recitation — it is practised now mainly 
by artistically minded nannies, and on the B.B.C. children s hour. 
And even legitimate histrionics, the art of acting, shows a trend towards 
less emphasis, more economy. Not only do Victorian melodramatics 
strike one as grotesque; but even films no more than twenty years old, 
and highly valued at the time, appear surprisingly dated — overdone, 
obvious, over-explicit. 

Somewhere around 600 B.C. the Homeric epics were consolidated 
in their final version, disguised in written symbols, and folded into 
parchment. The actor in his mask impersonated the hero; the bard 
imitated his voice; the printed book evokes the illusion that some- 
body is talking by a pair of inverted commas— yet we can almost hear 
Karenina's whisper or Uriah Heap's ingratiating whine. 

We have gone a long way in learning to create magic by the most 
frugal means. Only a hundred years ago the average Victorian novelist 
did not shrink from crude methods of dramatization: printed illus- 
trations, the use of the historic present, invitations addressed to the 
gentle reader to follow the narrator to a certain house in a certain 
town on a winter evening of the year 183 . . and peep through the 
window. Here, as in pre-Raphaelite painting, we find emphasis sans 
economy at work— a safe criterion of bad art. 



INPOIDXNG 



339 



One method of economy is 'leaving out* — firstly, everything that 
by the writer's standards is irrelevant, in the second place everything 
that is obvious, i.e. which the reader can and should supply out of his 
own imagination. 'The more bloody good stuff you cut out the more 
bloody good your novel will be,* Hemingway advised a young writer. 
Modern prose had to accelerate its pace, not because trains run faster 
than mailcoaches, but because the trains of thought run faster th?n a 
century ago, on tracks beaten smooth by popular psychology, the 
mass-media, and torrents of print. The novelist no longer needs to 
crank up the reader's imagination as if it were a model-T car; he 
pushes the button of the self-starter and leaves the rest to the battery. 
A glance at the opening lines of Mountains like White Elephants, or 
Cat in the Rain, will show that the comparison is hardly exaggerated. 

But there exist other, different, methods of infolding — obliquity, 
compression, and the Seven Types of Ambiguity — a modest estimate 
of Empson's. The later Joyce, for instance, makes one realize why the 
German word for writing poetry is 'dichten — to condense {certainly 
more poetical than 'composing*, i.e. 'putting together'; but perhaps 
less poetical than the Hungarian kolteni — to hatch). Freud actually 
believed that to condense or compress several meanings or allusions 
into a word or phrase was the essence of poetry. It is certainly an essen- 
tial ingredient with Joyce; almost every word in the great monologues 
in Finnegans Wake is overcharged with allusions and implications. To 
revert to an earlier metaphor, economy demands that the stepping- 
stones of the narrative should be spaced wide enough apart to require 
a significant effort from the reader; Joyce makes him feel like a runner 
in a marathon race with hurdles every other step and aggravated by a 
mile-long row of hieroglyphs which he must decipher. Joyce would 
perhaps be the perfect writer — if the perfect reader existed. 

Evidently, if the infolding technique is pushed too far, obscurity 
results, as witnessed by much contemporary poetry. It may be only a 
passing effect, due to a time-lag between the artist's and his public's 
maturity and range of perception; it may also be a conscious or half- 
conscious deception, practised by the artist on his public — including 
himself. To decide which of these alternatives applies to a difficult work 
of art is one of the trickiest problems for the critic; here, as a warning 
example, is Tolstoy's assessment of the French symbolists: 1 

The productions of another celebrity, Verlaine, are not less 
affected and unintelligible, ... I must pause to note the amazing 



340 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



celebrity of these two versifiers, Baudelaire and Verlaine. . . . How 
the French . . . could attribute such importance to these versifiers who 
were far from skilful in form and most contemptible in subject- 
matter, is to me incomprehensible. 

The Last Veil 

We have seen the Law of Infolding at work in the evolution of humour 
— from the coarse comedian's rubbing in of the joke to the mere hint, 
the New Yorker type of riddle. The comic simile starts with comparing 
a rnan to a pig or an ass (neither of them comic any longer, but simply 
a colloquial adjective) — and progresses to Heine's esoteric comparison 
of a girl's face to a palimpsest. A similar progression could be shown 
towards more oblique or condensed forms of metaphor and poetic 
imagery, replacing explicit analogies which, through wear and tear, 
have shrivelled to empty cliches. Long before the Symbolists, Blake 
realized the drawbacks of trying to make 'a complete demonstration 
of the object* and thereby depriving it of its mystery: 

The vision of Christ that thou doest see 

Is my visions greatest enemy. Thine has a great 

hook nose like thine 
Mine has a snub nose like to mine. 

Rhythm has undergone a similar evolution. Unlike the beat of the 
tom-tom or the rattling of the carriage wheels, metre does not consist 
of simple repetitions, but of intricate patterns of short and long 
stressed and light syllables, on which patterns of assonance and allitera- 
tion have further been superimposed. As music has travelled a long 
way from the simple repetitive figures performed on monochords and 
other primitive single-tone instruments, so has metre. Its original, 
simple pulse is only preserved in its sub-structure — implied, but no 
longer pounded out, 

In his analysis of metric form, L A. Richards 2 calls its effect 'patterned 
expectancy*: 

Rhythm and its specialized form, metre, depend upon repetition, 
and expectancy. Equally where what is expected recurs and where it 
fails, all rhythmical and metrical effects spring from anticipation. 
As a rule this anticipation is unconscious. . . . The mind, after 



INFOLDING 



341 



reading a line or two of verse . . . prepares itself for any one of a 
number of possible sequences, at the same time negatively incapaci- 
tating itself for others. The effect produced by what actually follows 
depends very closely upon this unconscious preparation and consists 
largely of the further twist which it gives to expectancy. It is in 
terms of the variation in these twists that rhythm is to be 
described This texture of expectations, satisfactions, disappoint- 
ments, surprisals, which the sequence of syllables brings about, is 
rhythm. . . . Evidently there can be no surprise and no disappoint- 
ment unless there is expectation Hence the rapidity with which 

too simple rhythms, those which are too easily 'seen through', 
grow cloying or hispid. 

if the mind is to experience the * waking trance* which Yeats promised 
as poetry's reward it must actively co-operate by filling in the missing 
beats and extending the sequence into the future. The witch-doctor 
hypnotizes his audience with the monotonous rhythm of his drum; 
the poet merely provides the audience with the means to hypnotize 
itself. 

"While elaborate metric forms impose a strain on our patterned ex- 
pectation, the Thyme is its sudden and full reward; it has the same 
cathartic effect as the harmonious resolution of a musical phrase. It is 
gloriously explicit in its amrmation of unity in variety; of the magic 
connection between sense and sound; of the oggly-gobbly delights of 
sheer repetition. That is obviously the reason for its unpopularity with 
contemporary poets; it offends against the ascetic diet imposed by the 
law of infolding. I am old-fashioned enough to regret its passing, as I 
regret the passing of the barrel-organ. 

Emphasis derives from the selection, exaggeration, and simplification 
of those elements which the artist chooses to regard as significant; it is 
a means to impose his vision on his audience. Economy is a technique 
designed to entice the audience into active co-operation, to make them 
re-create the artist's vision. To do so the audience must decipher the 
implied message; put into technical terms, he must (cf. pp. 84-6) 
intrapolate (fill in the gaps between the stepping stones'); extrapolate 
(complete the hint); and transform or reinterpret the symbols, images, 
and analogies; unwrap the veiled allegory. Now these operations which 
the audience must perform (interpolation, extrapolation, transforma- 
tion) to get the artist's implied message, correspond— like mirror 



342 THE ACT OF CREATION 

images, as it were — to the devices for lending a message emphasis: ex- 
aggeration, simplification, selection. The artist, intent on driving home 
his message, exaggerates and simplifies — the audience co-operates 
by filling in the gaps and extending the range of the communica- 
tion. He chooses what he considers to be the significant aspect among 
other aspects of a given experience— the audience discovers the sig- 
nificance by reinterpreting the message. All this may sound a little 
abstract, but it leads to a simple conclusion: explicit works of art with 
an emphatic, pointed message contain all the elements in ready-made 
form which otherwise the audience would have to contribute. The 
surest symptom of decadent art is that it leaves nothing to the imagina- 
tion; the muse has bared her flabby bosom like a too obliging harlot — 
there is no veiled promise, no mystery, nothing to divine. 

The law of infolding affects science too, though in a different way. 
Aristode had thought that nearly everything worth discovering about 
the ways of the universe had already been discovered; Francis Bacon 
and Descartes believed that to complete the edifice of science would 
take but a generation or two; Haeckel proclaimed that all the seven 
riddles of the universe had been solved. The idea of progress (in 
science and any other £cld) is only about three centuries old; and only 
since the collapse of mechanistic science around the turn of the last 
century did it begin to dawn on the more far-sighted among scientists, 
that the unfolding of the secrets of nature was accompanied by a 
parallel process of infolding—that we were learning more and more 
about less and less. The more precise knowledge the physicist acquired, 
the more ambiguous and oblique symbols he had to use to express it; 
he could no longer make an intelligible model of sub-atomic reality, 
he could only allude to it by formal equations which have as much 
resemblance to reality 'as a telephone number has to the subscriber. 
One might almost think that physical science is determined to imple- 
ment the programme of the French symbolists. 

It may seem that I have laid too much stress on the law of infolding. 
But quite obviously it plays an essential role in the progress of art 
and understanding; and it is in fact a characteristic of the human 
condition. For man is a symbol-making animal. He constructs a 
symbolic model of outer reality in his brain, and expresses it by a second 
set of symbols in terms of words, equations, pigment, or stone. All he 
knows directly are bodily sensations, and all he can directly do is to 
perform bodily motions; the rest of his knowledge and means of ex- 
pression is symbolical. To use a phrase coined by J. Cohen, 3 rr»ar> has a 



INFOLDING 



343 



metaphorical consciousness. Any attempt to get a direct grasp at 
naked reality is self-defeating; Urania, too, like the other muses, al- 
ways has a last veil left to fold in. 

Summary 

Art originates in sympathetic magic; in the illusions of stagecraft its 
origin is directly reflected. In the mind of naive audiences, the im- 
personator becomes identified with the character impersonated, as in 
ancient days the masked dancer became identified with the rain-god. 
On the other hand, sophisticated audiences are conscious and critical 
of the actors* performance, but are nevertheless caught by the illusion 
to the extent of producing the physical symptoms of intense emotion; 
their awareness suspended between two planes of experience, they 
exemplify the bisociative process in its purest form 

The escapist character of illusion facilitates the unfolding of the 
participatory emotions and inhibits the self-asserting emotions, except 
those of a vicarious character; it draws on untapped resources of 
emotion and leads them to catharsis. 

Rhythm and rhyme, assonance and pun are not artificial creations, 
but vestigial echoes of primitive phases in the development of lan- 
guage, and of the even more primitive pulsations of living matter; 
hence our particular receptiveness for messages which arrive in a 
rhythmic pattern, and their hypnotic effect. Association by sound 
affinity is still employed in subconscious mentation; it is manifested 
in the punning mania of children, in sleep, fatigue and mental disorder. 
The poet creates by bisociating sound and sense, metre and meaning; 
his voice is bi-vocal — so to speak. 

Metaphor and imagery come into existence by a process, familiar 
from scientific discovery, of seeing an analogy where nobody saw one 
before. The aesthetic satisfaction derived from the analogy depends on 
the emotiove potential of the matrices which participate in it. Synes- 
thetic cross-references from sight to touch, for instance, may enrich 
the experience, depending on personal preferences. Visual imagery, 
derived from the most important sense organ, carries a special emotive 
appeal; the 'picture-strip' language of concrete imagery pre-dates 
conceptualized thought. The highest emotive potential is found in 
images which evoke archetypal symbols and arouse unconscious 
resonances. They lead to the 'earthing* of emotion by relating 



344 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



particular experiences to a universal frame, the temporal to the eternal 
— as die scientist relates particular phenomena to general laws and 
ultimate causes. In both cases the flash of spontaneous illumination is 
followed by emotional catharsis; 'truth' and beauty* appear as 
complementary aspects of the indivisible experience. The difference 
between the two in objective verifiability is a matter of degrees, and 
arises only after the act; the act itself is in both cases a leap into the 
dark, where scientist and artist are equally dependent on their fallible 
intuitions. 

Originality, selective emphasis, and economy are certainly not the 
only criteria of literary excellence, but they proved to be a kind of 
handy mariner's compass for the critic at sea; and the 'law of infolding' 
appears to be equally valid — and tantalizing — in science as in art. 



XIX 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 

Identification 

In his monologue in Act 33, after the Hrst Player's dramatic recital, 
Hamlet asks a pertinent question: 

Is it not monstrous that this player here, 
But in a fiction, in a dream of passion, 
Could force his soul so to his own conceit 
That from, her working all the visage wann'd, 
Tears in his eyes, distraction in *s aspect, 
A broken voice . . . 

. . . and all for nothing, 

For Hecuba! 

What's Hecuba to him, or he to Hecuba, 
That he should weep for her? 

The answer to Hamlet's question was given by Flaubert: Emma 
Bovary, cest moL 

The magic tie is identification. "Without it, why indeed should our 
tear-glands become active on Hecuba's behalf? Goethe's early novel, 
The Sorrows of Young Werther, unleashed an epidemic of suicide in 
Germany; every romantic young man felt that he was Wcrther. 

The extent to which a character in a novel 'lives' depends on the 
intensity of the reader's participatory ties with him. To know what 
Hamlet feels while listening to the ghost, is the same thing as to know 
how it feels to be Hamlet. I must project part of myself into Hamlet, 
or Hamlet into myself— 'projection* and *introjection' are metaphors 
referring to the partial breakdown of the crust of personal identity. 
This remains true, regardless whether the reader admires, despises, 

345 



34<* 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



hates, or loves the fictional character. In order to love or hate some- 
thing which exists only as a series of signs made with printer's ink, the 
reader must endow it with a phantom life, an emanation from his 
conscious or unconscious self. The major contribution will probably 
come from the unconscious, which takes phantoms for granted and is 
apt to confuse personal identities. 

Thus the figments of Bovary, Little Lord Faunderoy, and Alyosha 
Karamazov which float around us in the air, are projections which 
body forth from our intimate selves, like the medium's ectoplasm. The 
author has created the prototype-phantoms, and the reader creates out 
of himself a copy, which he assumes to be like the original, though this 
is not necessarily the case. Whether the Elizabethans saw Shylock in a 
tragic or grotesque light, my own Shylock is a tragic figure — he has a 
great hook nose like mine, not a snub nose like to thine. 

Some novelists give meticulous descriptions of the visual appearances 
of their characters; others give little or none. Here again the general 
trend is away from the over-explicit statement towards the suggestive 
hint which entices the reader to build up his own image of the character. 
I am always annoyed when the author informs me that Sally Anne has 
auburn hair and green eyes. I don't particularly like the combination, 
and would have gone along more willingly with the author's intention 
that I should fall in love with Sally Anne if he had left the colour-scheme 
to me. There is a misplaced concreteness which gets in the way of the 
imagination. It is chiefly due to the misconception that 'imagination' 
means literally seeing images in the mind's eye; and consequendy that, 
for a character to come alive, I must carry a complete picture of it in 
my mind. Now this is an old fallacy which affects the subject we are 
discussing only indirecdy, but has a direct bearing on certain basic 
assumptions about the nature of perception and memory, on which 
the present theory rests. These are discussed in Book Two, which also 
contains the detailed evidence for the rather summary remarks which 
follow* 

Phantoms and Images 

Jn the first place, the evidence shows that there are people endowed 
with the faculty of so-called eidetic imagery— that is, of really seeing 
mental images with dream-like, hallucinatory vividness; but this 
faculty, though relatively frequent in children, is rare in adults. The 
average adult does not really see anything approaching a complete and 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 



347 



sharp image when lie recalls a memory — for instance, the face of a 
friend — though he may deceive himself into believing that he does. 
How do we know that he is deceiving himself? Here is one way of 
proving it— among many others. The experimenter lets the subject 
look at a square o£ say, four rows of four letters (which do not form 
any meaningful sequences) until the subject thinks he can see them in 
his mind's eye. He can, in fact, fluently read' them out after the square 
has been taken away — or so he believes. For when he is asked to read 
the square backwards, or diagonally, his fluency is gone. He has, in 
fact, learned the sequence by rote without realizing it— which is quite 
a different matter from forming a visual image. If he could really see 
the square, he could read it in all directions with the same ease and 
speed 

The ordinary citizen, who does not happen to be a painter, or a 
policeman, or of a particularly observant type, would be at a loss to 
give an exact visual description even of people whom he knows quite 
well- What we do remember of a person is a combination of (a) 
certain vivid details, and (b) what we call 'general impressions'. The 
'vivid detail' may be a gesture, an intonation, an outstanding visual 
feature — the mole on Granny's chin—which, for one reason or an- 
other, has stuck in one's memory, like a fragment from a picture- 
strip, and which functions pars pro toto — as a part, or sign deputizing 
for the whole. 

The 'general impression' on the other hand, is based on the opposite 
method of memory-formation: it is a schematized, sketchy, quasi 
'skeletonized* outline of a whole configuration, regardless of detail. 
A woman may say to a man, *I haven't seen you wearing that tie 
before* — though she has not the faintest recollection of any of the 
ties he has worn in the past. She recognizes a deviation from memories 
which she is unable to recall. The explanation of the paradox is that 
although she cannot remember the colour or pattern of any single tie 
which that man wore in the past, she does remember that they were 
generally subdued and discreet, which the new tie is not. It deviates not 
from any particular past experience, but from the general code, from 
an abstracted visual quality that these past experiences had in common. 
Such perceptual codes function as selective filters, as it were; the filter 
rejects as 'wrong' anything which does not fit its 'mesh'; and accepts 
or 'recognizes' anything that fits it, i.e. which gives the same 'general 
impression . The gentleman with the new tie, for instance, can get his 
own back with the remark, 'You have done something to your hair, 



348 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



haven't you?' He has never noticed her previous hair-dos at all, but he 
does notice that the present one just doesn't go with her mousy appear- 
ance. Here the code is 'mousiness' which, like all visual schematizations, 
is difficult to describe in words, but instantly recognized by the eye. 
We talk of an 'innocent' or 'lascivious' expression, of 'sensitive' or 
'brutal' features — characteristics which defy verbal description, but 
which can be sketched with a few lines — as emotions can be indi- 
cated by a few basic strokes indicating the slant of mouth and eyes. 
Other codes of recognition may combine form and motion, or 
vision and hearing: a characteristic gait, the timbre of a voice. 

Thus recognizing a person docs not mean matching a retinal image 
against a memory image of photographic likeness. My memory of 
John Brown is not a photographic record; it consists of several, simpli- 
fied and schematized 'general impressions' whose combination, plus a 
few 'vivid details', enable me to recognize him when we meet, or to 
remember him in his absence. But that remembrance is only partly of 
a pictorial nature, and much less so than I believe it to be — see the 
experiment with the letter-square. The reason for this self-deception is 
that the process of combining those simplified visual and other schemata 
and adorning them with a few genuine 'photographic fragments, is 
unconscious and instantaneous. The perceptual codes function below 
the level of awareness; we arc playing a game without being aware 
of the rules. We overestimate the precision of our imagery, as we 
overestimate the precision of our verbal thinking (quite often we thml- 
that we have understood the meaning of a difficult text and discover 
later that we haven't really) because we are unaware of the gaps 
between the words and between the sketchy contours of the schemata. 
All introspective 'visual' thinkers, from Einstein downward, em- 
phasized the vagueness, haziness, and abstract character of their con- 
scious visual imagery. True picture-strip thinking is confined to the 
dream, and other manifestations of the subconscious. 

The point of this apparent digression was to show that if the above 
is true regarding our mental images of real people whom we know, it 
must be all the more true regarding our images of fictional characters 
which lack any sensory basis. A character may indeed be 'alive' with 
the utmost vividness in the reader's mind, but this vividness need not 
be of a visual nature. The reader may fall in love with Kargnina, 
despair when she throws herself under the train, mourn her death— 
and yet be unable to visualize her in his mind's eye or give a detailed 
description of her appearance. Her 'living image' in the reader is not 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 



349 



a photographic image, but a multi-dimensional construct of a variety 
of aspects of her general appearance, her gestures and voice, her pat- 
terns of thinking and behaving. It is a combination of various 'general 
impressions' and 'vivid details' — that is, constructed on much the same 
principles as images of real people. 

In fact, there is no sharp dividing line between our images of people 
whom we have met in the flesh, and those whom we know only from 
descriptions — whether factual or fictional (or a combination of both). 
The dream knows no distinction between factual and fictitious charac- 
ters, and children as well as primitives are apt to confuse the two. 

Thus the phantoms of Bovary and Karenina which float around 
us are not so very different from our apparently solid memories of Joe 
Smith and Peter Brown; both varieties are made of the same stuff. 
In one of Muriel Spark's novels, a wise old bird asks his woman friend: 
'Do you think, Jean, that other people exist? ... I mean, do you 
consider that people — the people around us — are real or illusory? 
Surely you see that here is a respectable question. Given that yon 
believe in your own existence as self-evident, do you believe in that of 
others? Do you believe that I for instance, at this moment exist?' 1 

The only certainty that other people exist, not merely as physical 
shapes, but as sentient beings, is derived from partly conscious, but 
mostly unconscious, inference, i.e. empathy. We automatically infer 
from minute pointers in a person's face or gestures — which we mostly 
do not even register consciously — his character, mood, how he will 
behave in an emergency, and a lot of other things. Without this 
faculty of projecting part of one's own sentient personality into the 
other person s shell, which enables us to say *I know how you feel*, 
the pointers would be meaningless. Lorenz has shown that the various 
postures and flexions of the wolf's tail are indicative of at least ten 
different moods. As we have lost our tails we cannot empathize with 
these moods— but since our labial muscles are not very different, we 
feel at once the significance of bared teeth. 

The semi-abstract schematizations which we call 'general impres- 
sions' of appearance, character, and personality, are intuitive pointer- 
readings based on empathy. It is by this means that we assign reality 
and sentience to other people. Once more, the process diners from 
bringing a fictional character alive in our minds mainly by the nature 
of the pointers. A bland face at a cocktail party uttering the conven- 
tional type of remark may provide less pointers for empathy and imagi- 
nation than the cunningly planted hints of die novelist, specially 



350 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



designed to produce positive or negative identifications. Some phan- 
toms can be more real to the mind than many a bore made of solid 
flesh. The distinction between fact and fiction is a late acquisition of 
rational thought — unknown to the unconscious, and largely ignored 
by the emotions. 

Conflict 

Drama strives on conflict, and so does the novel. The nature of the 
conflict may be explicitly stated or merely implied; but an element of 
it must be present, otherwise the characters would be gliding through 
a frictionless universe. 

The conflict may be fought in the divided heart of a single charac- 
ter; or between two or more persons; or between man and his destiny. 
The conflict between personalities may be due to a clash of ideas or 
temperaments, to incompatible codes of behaviour or scales of value. 
But whatever its motif, a quarrel will assume the dignity of drama only 
if the audience is lead to accept the attitude of both sides as valid, each 
within its own frame of reference. If the author succeeds in this, the 
conflict will be projected into the spectator's or reader's mind, and 
experienced as a clash between two simultaneous and incompatible 
identifications. 'We make out of our quarrels with others rhetoric, 
but of our quarrels with ourselves poetry,* said Yeats. 

Dramatic conflict thus always reveals some paradox which is latent 
in the mind. It reflects both sides of the medal whereas in our practical 
pursuits we see only one at a time. The paradox may be seemingly 
superficial, as when our sympathies are divided between Hamlet and 
Laertes, two equally worthy contestants, with the resulting desire to 
help both, that is to harm both. But at least the double complicity in 
the double slaughter is prompted not by hate but love, and we are 
made to realize that it was destiny, not their own volition, which made 
them destroy each other; the paradox is 'earthed* in the human 
condition. 

Thus the artist compels his audience to live on several planes at 
once. He identifies himself with several characters in turn — Caesar, 
Brutus, Antony, projecting some aspect of himself into each of them, 
and speaking through their mouths; or introjecting them, if you like, 
and lending them his voice. He presents Brutus and Caesar alternately 
in situations where they command sympathy and impose their patterns 
of reasoning, their scales of value, until each has established his own 



CHARACTER AND BLOT 



351 



independent matrix in the spectator's mind. Having acquired these 
multiple identities, the spectator is led to a powerful climax, where he 
is both murderer and victim; and thence to catharsis. In the Bhagavid 
Gila the Lord Krishna appears on the battlefield in the role of charioteer 
to his disciple Arjuna, whom he cures of his pacifist scruples by ex- 
plaining that the slayer and the slain are One, because both are em- 
bodiments of the indestructible Atma; therefore 'the truly wise mourn 
neither for the living nor for the dead.' I doubt whether this doctrine, 
taken literally, had a beneficial effect on the ethics of Hinduism,* but 
to be both Caesar and Brutus in one's imagination has a profound 
cathartic effect, and is one way of approaching Nirvana. 

Brutus is an honourable man; so is Caesar; but what about Iago? 
Through pitying Desdemona, and sharing Othello's despair, we are 
compelled to hate Iago; but we can hate Iago only if he has come to 
life for us and in us; and he has come to life in us because he too com- 
mands our understanding and, at moments, our sympathy — the 
resonance of our own frustrated ambitions and jealousies. Without 
this unavowed feeling of complicity, he would be a mere stage-prop, 
and we could hate him no more than a piece of cardboard. Iago, 
Richard III, Stavrogin, the great villains of literature, have an irresist- 
ible appeal to some common, repressed villainousness in ourselves, 
and give us a wonderfully purifying opportunity to discover what it 
feels like to be frankly a villain. 

But true-black villains are limit cases; the more evenly our sym- 
pathies are distributed among the antagonists, the more successfully 
the work will actualize latent aspects of our personalities. Caliban and 
Prospero, Faust and Mephisto, Don Quixote and Sancho Panza, Christ 
and the Great Inquisitor — each pair is locked in an everlasting duel in 
which we act as seconds for both. In each of these conflicts two self-, 
contained frames of reference, two sets of values, two universes of 
discourse collide. All great works of literature contain variations and 
combinations, overt or implied, of such archetypal conflicts inherent 
in the condition of man, which first occur in the symbols of mythology, 
and are restated in the particular idiom of each culture and period. All 
literature, wrote Gerhart Hauptmann, is 'the distant echo of the primi- 
tive word behind the veil of words'; and the action of a drama or 
novel is always the distant echo of some ancestral action behind the 
veil of the period's costumes and conventions. There are no new 
themes in literature, as there are no new human instincts; but every age 
provides new variations and sublimations, new settings and a different 



35^ THE ACT OF CREATION 

set of rules for fighting the old battles all over again. To quote G. W. 
Brandt: 'There is basically only a limited number of plots; they can be 
seen, in different guises, recurring down the ages. The reason is in life 
itself. Human relationships, whilst infinitely varied in detail, reveal — 
stripped down to fundamentals — a number of repetitive patterns. 
Writers straining to invent a plot entirely fresh have known this for a 
long time. Goethe quoted Gozzi's opinion that there were only thirty- 
six tragic situations-— and he added that Schiller, who believed that 
there were more, had not even succeeded in finding as many as that/ 2 

Integrations and Confrontations 

If the individual act of discovery displays essentially the same psycho- 
logical pattern in science and in art, their collective progress differs in 
one important respect. We have seen (Chapter X) that the evolution 
of science is neither continuous nor cumulative in a strict sense; but it 
is nevertheless more so than the evolution of art. 

In the discoveries of science, the bisociated matrices merge in a new 
synthesis, which in turn merges with others on a higher level of the 
hierarchy; it is a process of successive confluences towards unitary, 
universal laws (at least, this applies to a given province of science in a 
given period or cycle). The progress of art does not display this overall 
'river-delta* pattern. The matrices with which the artist operates are 
chosen for their sensory qualities and emotive potential; his bisociative 
act is a juxtaposition of these planes or aspects of experience, not their 
fusion in an intellectual synthesis— to which, by their very nature, they 
do not lend themselves. This difference is reflected in the quasi-linear 
progression of science, compared with the quasi-timeless character of 
art, its continual re-statements of basic patterns of experience in chang- 
ing idioms. If the explanations of science are like streams joining rivers, 
rivers moving towards the unifying ocean, the explanations of art 
may be compared to the tracing back of a ripple in the stream to its 
source in a distant moimtain-spring. 

But I must once more repeat, at the risk of being tedious, that in all 
domains of creative activity intellectual and aesthetic experience arc 
both present in various mixtures; that 'science' and 'art' form a con- 
tinuum; that changes of fashion are common in the zig-zag course of 
science, while on the other hand, development of a given art-form over 
a period often shows a distinct 'river-delta' pattern.* The modern 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 



353 



atom-physicist knows more than Democritus, but then Joyce's 
Ulysses also knows more than Homer's Odysseus; and in some respects 
this progress in knowledge, too, is of a cumulative order. 

Archetypes 

Always bearing these qualifications in mind, we might spin out the 
metaphor: if the great confluence towards which science strives is the 
universal logos, the ultimate spring of aesthetic experience is the 
archetypos. The literal meaning of the word is 'implanted' [typos=z 
stamp) 'from the beginning'. Jung described archetypes as 'the psychic 
residua of numberless experiences of the same type' encountered by 
our ancestors, and stamped into the memory of the race — that is, into 
the deep layers of the 'collective unconscious , below the level of per- 
sonal memories. Hence, whenever some archetypal motif is sounded, 
the response is much stronger than warranted by its face value — the 
mind responds like a tuning fork to a pure tone. 

One need not be a follower of Jung to recognize the same arche- 
typal experiences crystallized into symbols in the mythologies of 
cultures widely separate in space and time. Examples of such recurrent 
patterns are the death-and-resurrection motif; the extension of the 
sexual duality into the metaphysical polarities of masculine logic and 
feminine intuition, mother earth and heavenly father, etc.; the strife 
between generations — and its counterpoint, the taboo on incest; the 
Promethean struggle to wrest power from the gods — and the impera- 
tive need to placate them by sacrifice; the urge to penetrate to the 
ultimate mystery — and the resigned admission that reality is beyond 
the mind's grasp, hidden by the veil of Maya, reduced to shadows in 
Plato's cave. These perennial patterns of victory and defeat recur in 
ever-changing variations throughout the ages, because they derive 
from the very essence of the human condition — its paradoxes and 
predicaments. They play an all-important part in literature, from 
Greek tragedy down to the present, permeating both the whole and 
the part: the plot, and the images employed in it. The poetic image 
attains its highest vibrational intensity as it were, when it strikes 
archetypal chords— when eternity looks through the window of time. 

William Empson 8 has given a convincing analysis of the archetypal 
imagery in Nash's famous lines — which, however often quoted, never 
lose their power: 'Brightness falls from the air./Queens have died young 



354 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



and fair./Dust hath closed Helen's eye./I am sick, I must die/Lord have 
mercy upon us.' 

'If death did not exist', wrote Schopenhauer, 'there would be no 
philosophy — nor would there he poetry.' That does not mean that 
either philosophy, or art, must be obsessively preoccupied with death; 
merely, that great works of art are always transparent to some dim 
outline of the ultimate experience, the archetypal image. It need not 
have a tragic shape, and it may be no more than the indirect reflection 
of a reflection, the echo of an echo. But metaphor and imagery yield 
aesthetic value only if the two contexts which are involved in the com- 
parison form an ascending gradient — if one of them is felt to be 
nearer to the source of the stream. Mutatis mutandum, a scientific 
theory need not be direcdy concerned with the ultimate secret of the 
universe, but it must point towards it by bringing order and harmony 
into some obscure corner. To clinch the argument, I must quote once 
more Housman's essay on The Name and Nature of Poetry: 

In these six simple words of Milton — 

Nymphs and shepherds, dance no more — 

what is it that can draw tears, as I know it can, to the eyes . . . ? 
"What in the world is there to cry about? Why have the mere words 
the physical effect of pathos when the sense of the passage is blithe 
and gay? I can only say, because they are poetry, and find their way 
to something in man which is obscure and latent, something older 
than the present organization of his nature, like the patches of fen 
which still linger here and there in the drained lands of Cambridge- 
shire. 



Cataloguing Plots 

Let me mention a few examples of archetypal patterns in literature — 
without any attempt at cataloguing Goethe's thirty-six bask plots. 

The Promethean striving for omnipotence and omniscience is 
symbolized in Jacob's struggle with the angel, the Tower of Babel, 
the flight of Icarus, the Faustus legend, and so on through Voltaire's 
Candide, down to the broken Promethean heroes of H. G. Wells 
(Dr. Moreau) or Dostoyevski (Stavrogin in The Possessed). In the 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 



355 



modern development of the theme, it is of course treated in a more 
allusive, implicit manner; but in the mass media and pulp magazines, 
Supermen, Space Cadets, and Black Magicians are all happily running 
true to archetype. 

The next catalogue-heading would be 'Individual against Society', 
with several subheadings, such as 'from Oedipus to Schmoedipus, or 
shall we love mamma?' Next would come polygonal patterns of 
libidinous relations' (triangles, quadrangles, etc.); a title I have actually 
borrowed from a learned publication by a field-anthropologist; it 
shows that if you collect archetypes methodically, they crumble to 
dust. Yet under this heading belongs at least half the total bulk of world 
literature, from the Vulcan-Venus-Mars triangle onward. Next might 
come the War of the Sexes — from the Amazon myths through 
Lysistrata to Ann Veronica and Simone de Beauvoir; next, love 
triumphant, or defeated— the Song of Songs alternating with Isolde's 
Liehestod. Lastly, the Conquest of the Flesh, from the Buddha to 
Aldous Huxley. 

Still under the heading 'Man and Society* would come the sub- 
headings: the hubris of Power; the hubris of Cleverness; the hubris of the 
Ivory Tower and, less obvious, the hubris of Sanctity. The last is either an 
offence to God Qob; the ten righteous men who find less favour than 
the one repentant sinner) or to society, because the hero's personal 
scales of value deviate from the conventional. He must therefore either 
be an inspired fool, or play the fool to escape sanction, or suffer martyr- 
dom — 'The time is out ofjoint; O cursed spite, / That ever I was born 
to set it right!' Examples range from the Perceval legend and The Lay 
of the Great Fool, through Don Quixote, Ulenspiegel and The Good 
Soldier Schweik to Prince Mishkin in Dostoyevski's The Idiot, and 
Camus' U&ranger. 

Under the heading 'The Divided Heart' would fall, as sub-categories, 
conflicts between Love and Duty; between Self-Preservation and Self- 
Sacrifice; between Ends and Means; and between Faith and Reason. 

Puppets and Strings 

To end this pedantic — and yet very incomplete — catalogue, I must 
mention one of the most powerful archetypes, which appears in count- 
less variations in the history of literature: the Puppet on Strings, or 
Volition against Fate. In Oedipus Rex fate appears in the shape of 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



malevolent powers who trap the King into performing his disastrous 
deeds apparently out of his own free will. In all plots of the Appoint- 
ment in Samara type, apparent coincidences are the means by which 
destiny defeats the will of man (cf. coincidence in comedy, p. 78). In 
Christian theology, the ways of God become less arbitrary, but more 
inscrutable; man proposes, God disposes; original sin chokes his 
designs. In the Eastern religions he is tied to the wheel of rebirth; in 
Islam he carries his fate fastened round his neck. The great theological 
disputes between Calvinists and Lutherans, Jansenites and Jesuits 
turned mainly on the question of predestination, or more precisely, on 
the length of the rope left to man to hang himself. 

With the rise of Natural Philosophy, a change in the character of 
destiny began to take shape. Romeo and Juliet still die as a result of 
fatal misunderstandings ('One writ with me in sour misfortune's 
book*). But in Shakespeare's later works, destiny acts no longer only 
from outside but also from inside the personae; they are victims not 
so much of blind fate, but of their blind passions: 'the fault, dear Brutus, 
is not in our stars, but in ourselves'. These are great, brave words; but 
they did not solve the dilemma, they merely polished its horns. Divine 
predestination was transformed into scientific deterniinism, which left 
man even less scope than before for exercising his will and making free 
choices. The hairshirt of the penitent had allowed him some freedom 
of movement, but the laws of heredity and environment wove a 
strait-jacket so tight that it became indistinguishable from his living 
skin. Even the word Volition was banned from psychology as empty 
of meaning. Chromosomes and glandular secretions took over from 
the gods in deciding a man's fate. He remained a marionette on strings, 
with the only difference that he was now suspended on the nucleic 
acid chains determining his heredity, and the conditioned-reflex 
chains forged by the environment. 

The most explicit adoption of this schema for literary uses is found 
in the naturalist movement of the nineteenth century. Its programme 
was formulated in Zola's Le Roman Experimental inspired by the 
Introduction a Yitude de la medicine experimentale by the great Claude 
Bernard (who discovered the vaso-motor system of nerves, and the 
glucose-producing function of the liver). Zola urged his fellow writers 
to take a physiological view' of man as a product of nature devoid of 
free will and subject to the laws of heredity and environment. For- 
tunately, in spite of the naturalist vogue in Germany, Russia, and 
Scandinavia, writers accepted his views in theory only— as they are 



CHARACTER AND PLOT 



357 



wont to do. The creative mind knows how to draw on archetypal 
symbols without degrading them by misplaced concreteness. 

You can make an X-ray photograph of a face, but you cannot make 
a face from an X-ray photograph. You can show that underlying the 
subde and complex action of a novel there is a primitive skeleton, 
without committing Use majesti, or foolishly assuming that the plot 
makes the novel. There is only a limited number of plots, reairring 
down the ages, derived from an even more limited number of basic 
patterns — the conflicts, paradoxes, and predicaments inherent in man's 
condition. And if we continue the stripping game, we £md that all 
these paradoxes and predicaments arise from conflicts between in- 
compatible frames of experience or scales of value, iHuminated in con- 
sciousness by the bisociative art. In this final illumination Aristotle 
saw 'the highest form of learning' because it shows us that we are 'men, 
not gods'; and he called tragedy 'the noblest form of literature' because 
it purges suffering from its pettiness by showing that its causes lie in 
the inescapable predicaments of existence.* 



NOTES 

To p. 351. Hindu apologists would have us take Krishna's exhortations to 
belligerence as allegorical references to wars fought inside the human soul. The 
argument is as far-fetched as the Christian apologists* attempts to represent the 
Song of Songs as an allegory of Christ's love for His Church. 

Top. 352. Eric Newton (An Introduction to European Painting) actually uses 
the same metaphor. 

Top. 357. At least this seems the most plausible explanation of the cryptic 
remark in the Poetics that we take pleasure in tragedy because learning is pleasur- 
able, and tragedy involves learning. 



XX 



THE BELLY OF THE WHALE 
The Night Journey 

One archetype remains to be discussed, which is of special 
significance for the act of creation. It is variously known as 
the Night Journey, or the Death-and-Rebirth motif; but 
one might as well call it the meeting of the Tragic and the Trivial 
Planes. It appears in countless guises; its basic pattern can be roughly 
described as follows. Under the effect of some overwhelming ex- 
perience, the hero is made to realize the shallowness of his life, the 
futility and frivolity of the daily pursuits of man in the trivial routines 
of existence. This realization may come to him as a sudden shock 
caused by some catastrophic event, or as the cumulative effect of a 
slow inner development, or through the trigger action of some 
apparently banal experience which assumes an unexpected significance. 
The hero then suffers a crisis which involves the very foundations of 
his being; he embarks on the Night Journey, is suddenly transferred 
to the Tragic Plane — from which he emerges purified, enriched by 
new insight, regenerated on a higher level of integration. 

The symbolic expressions of this pattern are as old as humanity. 1 
The crisis or Night Journey may take the form of a visit to the under- 
world (Orpheus, Odysseus); or the hero is cast to the bottom of a well 
(Joseph), buried in a grave (Jesus), swallowed by a fish (Jonah); or he 
retires alone into the desert, as Buddha, Mahomet, Christ, and other 
prophets and founders of religions did at the crucial turn in their lives. 

I went down to the bottoms of the mountains: the earth with her 
bars was about me for ever. 

The journey always represents a plunge downward and backward 
to the sources and tragic undercurrents of existence, into the fluid 
magma, of which the Trivial Plane of everyday life is merely the thin 

35* 



THE BELLY OF THE WHALE 



359 



crust. In most tribal societies, the plunge is symbolically enacted in the 
initiation-rites which precede the turning points in the life of the 
individual, such as puberty or marriage. He is made to undertake a 
minor Night Journey: segregated from the community, he must fast, 
endure physical hardships and various ordeals, so that he may ex- 
perience the essential solitude of man, and establish contact with the 
Tragic Plane. A similar purpose is served by the symbolic drowning 
and rebirth of baptism; the institution of periods of retreat found in 
most religions; in fasts and other purification rituals; in the initiation 
ceremonies of religious or masonic orders, even of university societies. 
iUumination must be preceded by the ordeals of incubation. 

Freudians and Jungians alike emphasize the intimate relation between 
the symbolism of the Night Journey, and the unconscious craving for 
a return to the womb. The connection is no more far-fetched than our 
references to 'mother earth', 'mother ocean', or 'mother church'. 

Not only do we speak of 'Mother Church', but even of the 'womb 
of the Church', and in the ceremony of the 'benedictio fontis' of the 
Catholic Church the baptismal font is even called the 'immaculatus 
divini fontis uterus' (the immaculate uterine font of divinity). . . . 2 

The maternal aspect of the church is impersonated in the Virgin 
Mary. In Donne's 'Annunciation', the Angel greets her with: 

That All, which alwayes is All every where, 
Which cannot sinne, and yet all sinnes must beare, 
"Which cannot die, yet cannot chuse but die, 
Loe, faithfull Virgin, yeelds himselfe to lye 
In prison, in thy wombe; . . . 

. . . yea thou art now 
Thy Makers maker, and thy Fathers mother; 
Thou 'hast light in darke; and shutst in little roome, 
Immensity cloystered in thy deare wombe. 

The craving for the womb, for the dissolution of the self in a lost, 
vegetative oneness — Freud's Nirvana principle — is further symbolized 
in the image of mother ocean in whose calm depths all life originates. 
Mythology is full of these symbols— the metaphors of the collective 
unconscious. However bewildering they may appear to the waking 
mind, they are familiar to the dreamer, and recur constantly in the 



360 THE ACT OF CREATION 

sleep of people who have nothing else in common. The Night Journey 
is the antipode of Promethean striving. One endeavours to steal the 
bright fire from the gods; the other is a sliding back towards the pulsa- 
ting darkness, one and undivided, of which we were part before our 
separate egos were formed. 

Thus the Night Journey is a regression of the participatory tendencies, 
a crisis in which consciousness becomes unborn — to become reborn in 
a higher form of synthesis. It is once more the process of reenter pour 
mieux sauter; the creative impulse, having lost its bearing in trivial 
entanglements, must effect a retreat to recover its vigour. 

Without our regular, minor night journeys in sleep we would soon 
become victims of mental desiccation. Dreaming is for the aesthetically 
underprivileged the equivalent of artistic experience, his only means of 
self-transcendence, of breaking away from the trivial plane and creating 
his own mythology. 

The Guilt of Jonah 

Among the many variations of the Night Journey in myth and folk- 
lore, one of the most forceful is the story of Jonah and the whale — 
perhaps because in no ancient civilization was the tension between the 
Tragic and Trivial planes more intensely felt than by the Hebrews. 
The first was represented by the endless succession of invasions and 
catastrophes, the exacting presence of Jehovah and of his apocalyptic 
prophets; the second by the rare periods of relatively normal life, 
which the over-strung spiritual leaders of the tribe condemned as 
abject. Jonah had committed no crime which would warrant his 
dreadful punishment; he is described as a quite ordinary and decent 
fellow with just a streak of normal vanity— for he is, justifiably, Very 
angry* when, in the end, God does not raze Nineveh as Jonah had 
prophesied at His bidding, and thus makes Jonah appear an impostor 
or fool. 

Now this very ordinary person receives at the beginning of the 
story God's sudden order to 'go to Nineveh, that great city, and cry 
against it'— which is a rather tall order, for Jonah is no professional 
priest or prophet. It is quite understandable that he prefers to go on 
leading his happy and trivial life. So, instead of responding to the call 
from the Tragic Plane, he buys a passage on a ship to Tarshish; and 
he has such a clean conscience about it, that while the storm rages and 
the sailors cry 'every-man unto his god' and throw the cargo into the 



THE BELLY OF THE WHALE 



sea, Jonah himself is fast asleep. And therein — in his normality, com- 
placency, in his thick-skinned triviality and refusal to face the storm, 
and God, and the corruption of Nineveh; in his turning his back on the 
tragic essence of life — precisely therein lies his sin, which leads to the 
crisis, to the Night Journey in the belly of the whale, in 'the belly of 
hell\ 

The waters compassed me about, even to the soul: the depth 
closed me round about, the weeds were wrapped about my head . . . 
yet hast thou brought up my life from corruption, O Lord my God. When 
my soul fainted within me I remembered the Lord: and my prayer 
came in unto thee. . . . They that observe lying vanities forsake their own 
mercy. 

The story sounds in fact like an allegory of a nervous breakdown and 
subsequent spiritual conversion. Jonah might serve as a symbol for 
Dimitri Karamazov, or any of the countless heroes of fiction who 
progress through crisis to awakening. For I must repeat that Jonah's 
only crime was to cling to the Trivial Jflane and to cultivate his litde 
garden, trying to ignore the uncomfortable, unjust, terrible voice 
from the other plane. Melville understood this when, in the great 
sermon in Moby Dick, he made his preacher sum up the lesson of 
Jonah and the whale in this unorthodox moral: 

Woe to him who seeks to pour oil upon the waters when God has 
brewed them into a gale! Woe to him who seeks to please rather 
than to appal! Woe to him whose good name is more to him than 
goodness! Woe to him who, in this world, courts not dishonour! 

And the author of the Jonah story himself must have been aware of 
its vast implications, of the impossibility of treating all men who 
lead an ordinary life as harshly as Jonah — for the story ends with an 
unusual act of clemency by the otherwise so vengeful desert-god, 
which comes as a curious anticlimax full of ironical tolerance for the 
inadequacy of man: 

Then said the Lord And should I not spare Nineveh, that great 

city, wherein are more than six score thousand persons that cannot 
discern between their right hand and their left hand: and also much 
cattle? 



The Root and the Flower 



Just as there is no mythology without some mention of the death and 
rebirth motif, so there is hardly any epoch in world literature without 
some variation of it. Maud Bodkin 8 has made an exhaustive study of 
its occurrence in works as wide apart as The Ancient Mariner, Morgan's 
The Fountain, Eliot's The Waste Land, and D. H. Lawrence's The 
Plumed Serpent and The Man Who Died. Even such an urbane novelist 
as E. M. Forster has in each of his five novels one central episode in 
which the hero or heroine, who previously walked with self-assurance 
on the smooth surface, seems to fall into a manhole with its lid off, 
and re-emerge as a changed character— like Mrs. Moore, after her visit 
to the primeval Marabar caves. With the great Russian novelists, 
crisis and conversion is a central theme; in German literature one can 
trace it from Faust II to The Magic Mountain. It pops up in such un- 
expected places as The Short Happy Life of Francis Macomber, or the last 
page of To Have or Have Not; and it was elevated to a philosophy in 
Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling and in Sartre's existentialist credo: 
man is what he makes out of his anguish, he becomes 'free' through the 
realization of his nothingness. 

Needless to say, not all great novels are — or should be — problem 
novels' aiming at us a constant heavy barrage of the tragic and the 
archetypal; if they were, literature would be very monotonous indeed. 
But indirectly and implicidy every great work of art has some bearing 
on man's ultimate problems. Yeats had a loathing for 'those learned 
men who are a terror to children and an ignominious sight in lovers' 
eyes'; because 'Art bids us to touch and taste and hear and see the world, 
and shrinks from what Blake calls mathematical form, from every 
abstract thing.' And yet he knew better— when, for instance, he evoked 
the purely sensual delight of Cleopatra dancing alone under her 'topless 
towers': 

'She thinks, part woman, three parts a child, 

That nobody looks: her feet 

Practise a tinker's shuffle 

Picked up on a street. 

Like a longAegged fly upon the stream 

Her mind moves upon silence. 9 

The refrain, recurring after each of the three stanzas of the poem, 
, connects (as the context clearly indicates) Cleopatra's meditations 

362 



THE BELLY OF THE "WHALE 



during her childish dance with the monumental archetype of the spirit 
of God moving upon the face of the waters. 

A flower, even if it is only a daisy, must have a root; and a work of 
art, however gay, precious, or serene, is in the last instance fed, how- 
ever indirectly, invisibly, through delicate capillary tubes, from the 
ancient substrata of experience. If it has a humorous message, it pro- 
duces a smile — a subdued laugh or sous-rire; if it is tragic, it produces a 
sous-pleurei, that rapt stillness and overflowing of emotion where, to 
quote Donne again, with a strong, sober thirst, my soule attends. 

The Tightrope 

The ordinary mortal in our urban civilization moves virtually all his 
life on the Trivial Plane; only on a few dramatic occasions— during 
the storms of puberty, when he is in love or in the presence of death — 
does he fall suddenly through the manhole, and is transferred to the 
Tragic Plane. Then all at once the pursuits of his daily routines appear 
as shallow, trifling vanities; but once safely back on the Trivial Plane, 
he dismisses the realities of the other as the products of overstrung 
nerves or adolescent effusions. Sudden catastrophes — famines, wars, and 
plagues — may shift a whole population from the Trivial to the Tragic 
Plane; but they soon succeed in banalizing even tragedy itsel£ and 
carry on business as usual among the shambles. During the Spanish 
Civil War, one of my fellow prisoners, a youth condemned to death 
by shooting, and suffering from appendicitis, was put on a milk diet 
two days before his execution. 

The force of habit, the grip of convention, hold us down on the 
Trivial Plane; we are unaware of our bondage because the bonds are 
invisible, their restraints acting below the level of awareness. They are 
the collective standards of value, codes of behaviour, matrices with 
built-in axioms, which determine the rules of the game, and make most 
of us run, most of the time, in the grooves of habit — reducing us to 
the status of skilled automata which Behaviourism proclaim s to be the 
only condition of man. What Bergson called 'the mechanical encrusted 
on the living' is the result of protracted confinement to the Trivial 
Plane. 

But, glory be, man is not a flat-earth dweller all the time— only 
most of the time. Like the universe in which he lives, he is in a state 
of continuous creation. The exploratory drive is as fundamental to his 



364. THE ACT OF CREATION 

nature as the principle of parsimony which tends towards the auto- 
matization of skilled routines; his need for self-transcendence as basic 
as the necessity of self-assertion; lastly, we shall see that the reenter 
pourmieux sauter of the creative act itself has its evolutionary precedents 
in the phenomena of organic regeneration and in the 'original adapta- 
tions' of which animals are capable in a crisis. 

Life on the Trivial Plane is a state of unnoticed confinement — but 
also a condition of social and intellectual stability. The belly of the 
whale cannot be made into a permanent residence. Neither emotionally, 
nor intellectually, can we afford to live for more than brief transition 
periods on the Tragic Plane, surrounded by archetypes and Ultimates. 
Emotionally, it would mean the journey of no return of Blake— or of 
the Yogi entering into final samadhi. Intellectually, it would mean the 
abdication of reason. For the entities encountered on that plane, the 
members of its matrix—eternity, infinity, mtimate causes, archetypal 
paradoxes— are irreducible absolutes which do not lend themselves to 
logical manipulation. They disrupt all rational operations, as the 
mathematical symbols for nought and the infinite do if introduced 
into a finite equation. Malraux's 'une vie ne vaut rien — mats rien ne 
vaut une vxe is a perfect expression of this. The physicist can deal with 
infinite space in an abstract symbol-language, but in ordinary ex- 
perience it is just the infinite, a thing that passeth understanding, and 
there the matter ends. 

Absolutes are too inhuman and elusive to cope with, unless they are 
connected with some experience in the tangible world of the finite. In 
fact, eternity is a pretty meaningless notion— unless it is made to look 
through the window of time. 'Immensity' is a bore— unless it is 
cloystered in thy deare wombe'. The absolute becomes emotionally 
effective only if it is bisociated with something concrete— dovetailed, 
as it were, into the familiar. The rain of manna on the children of 
Israel which lasted forty years was an act of incomprehensible divine 
largesse which, as we learn from Exodus, did not particularly impress 
them; the miracle of the loaves and fishes was a true miracle. 

Where the Tragic and Trivial Planes meet, the Absolute becomes 
humanized, drawn into the orbit of man, while the banal objects of 
daily experience are transfigured, surrounded by a halo as it were. 
The meeting may have the majesty of an incarnation where the logos 
becomes flesh; or the charm of Krishna's descent to dally with the 
shepherdesses. On a less awe-inspiring scale, the tragic and the trivial 
may meet in golden lads and chimney-sweeps; in the petrified boot 



THE BELLY OP THE WHALE 



365 



which the Pompeian boot-mender holds in his petrified hand; in the 
slice of pig's kidney which Bloom fingers in his pocket during the 
funeral service. Laplace regarded it as the ultimate aim of science to 
demonstrate from a single grain of sand the mechanics of the whole 
universe'. 

The locus in quo of human creativity is always on the line of inter- 
section between two planes; and in the highest forms of creativity 
between the Tragic or Absolute, and the Trivial Plane. The scientist 
discovers the working of eternal laws in the ephemeral grain of sand, or 
in the contractions of a dead frog's leg hanging on a washing-line. The 
artist carves out the image of the god which he saw hidden in a piece 
of wood. The comedian discovers that he has known the god from a 
plum-tree. 

This interlacing of the two planes is found in all great works of art, 
and at the origin of all great discoveries of science. The artist and 
scientist are condemned— or privileged — to walk on the line of inter- 
section as on a tightrope. At his best moments, man is 'that great and 
true amphibium, whose nature is disposed to live, not only like other 
creatures in divers elements, but in divided and distinguished worlds'. 



C. VISUAL CREATION 



XXI 

MOTIF AND MEDIUM 
Looking at Nature 

Kepler, contemplating a snow-crystal melting on his always 
sweaty palm, saw in it the harmony of the spheres reflected 
in miniature. Let a less romantically disposed person look for 
the first time at a snowflake under a microscope: he will catch his 
breath and wax equally lyrical: 'How strange—how beautiful — how 
clever is nature', et cetera. Yet the symmetrical pattern of hexagons 
thus marvellously revealed, loses all its magic when drawn on a 
drawing-board. It becomes aesthetically neutral for lack of a second 
context— the familiar sight of the feathery snowflake. It is the super- 
imposition of the two matrices — the trivial object revealing the mathe- 
matical regularity of its micro-cosmic architecture — which creates the 
impact, and gives rise to the aesthetic experience. 

"Whether Odysseus saw in the sky at dawn 'rosy-fingered Athene 
lift her golden ray*, or whether you share the sorrow of the weeping 
willow, there is inevitably a second frame of reference superimposed 
on the picture. Man always looks at nature through coloured glasses 
— through mythological, anthropomorphic, or conceptual matrices — 
even when he is not conscious of it and believes that he is engaged in 
'pure vision', unsullied by any meaning. The 'innocent eye' is a fiction, 
based on the absurd notion that what we perceive in the present can be 
isolated in the mind from the influence of past experience. There is no 
perception of 'pure form' but meaning seeps in, and settles on the 
image (though the meaning need not be expressed in verbal language, 
about which more later). 

The idea that looking at nature is self-rewarding, and that land- 
scapes devoid of action can give rise to aesthetic experiences, is of 
relatively recent origin; so is landscape painting.* Dr. Johnson regarded 
mountains as 'rather uncouth objects'; in the literature of the eighteenth 

$66 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



3<*7 



century precipices were branded as 'frowning* and 'horrid*. 1 The 
further we go back in time the less appreciation we find of the purely 
visual aspects of form and colour in inanimate nature: 

Considering the bulk and value of Greek literature, and the 
artistic brilliance of Athens, the feeling for nature . . . was but poorly 
developed among a people whose achievement in the dramatic and 
sculptural arts has been unsurpassed; it is seriously lacking in Homer, 
even when he refers to the sea or to the famous garden of Alcinous, 
and it can hardly be said to enter Greek drama save in the Oedipus 
at Colonnus and in some of the lyrical choruses of Euripides. Indeed, 
the continent of nature had to wait for a thorough and minute 
exploration until the romantic movement of the nineteenth century: 
Byron, Shelley, Wordsworth, Goethe, first brought the ocean, the 
rivers, and the mountain ranges into their own. . . . For primitive 
man earth and sea are simply the perennial source of those material 
goods on which life depends, and mountain peaks are uninteresting 
and unattractive because they are barren and bleak (Listowel) , 2 

The same could be said about the underprivileged classes and 
nations in our own time. The peasants in the alpine village where I 
live in summer never cease to marvel at the silliness of tourists who 
talk about the 'beauty* of the mountains— which to them means so 
much timber, pasture, and hay. Travelling in India one is amazed by 
the indifference, even among the educated classes, towards landscape 
and scenery, birds and plants. 

All this does not mean that earlier dvilizations derived no emotional 
experiences from nature. But they were derived from different sources: 
the supernatural powers and magic forces which animated the visible 
world. The Babylonians populated the starry heavens with Hons, vir- 
gins, and scorpions. The Sicilian straits were to the Greeks not a land- 
scape but the seats of Scylla and Charybdis. To Homer, a storm at sea 
signified the anger of Poseidon; to Mr. Babitt it signifies the majesty of 
nature, a vaguely personalized Power manifested in the spectacle before 
his eyes. There is always a second matrix active behind, or superimposed 
upon, the visual appearance. The beholder may be convinced that he is 
simply perceiving images on his retina, but he is in fact perceiving 
with the whole of his brain; and what he sees is modified by the 
perceptual codes which operate in it, resonances of his racial and 
personal past, floating images of touch and smell, even kinesthetic 



368 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



sensations or incipient muscular stresses. When an appearance gives 
rise to an aesthetic experience, it always represents or symbolizes or 
expresses something behind and beyond its retinal image — exactly as 
the pigment on a canvas always refers to something beyond its frame. 

A human face is also an object of nature, a landscape of live tissue. 
To evoke aesthetic feeling, it must point at something beyond itself 
in the beholder's mind. The analogue of the snow-crystal is here that 
scaffolding of perfect symmetry and proportions, whose geometrical 
laws the painters of Greece and the Renaissance tirelessly pursued. The 
golden section and other basic proportions were thought to be the 
ultimate constituents of organic form— as the Pythagorean scale of 
music was thought to regulate the heavenly motions, and as simple 
geometrical units, the architect's elementary 'modules', combined to 
make Gothic cathedrals. The philosophers of classicism, from Pliny to 
Leonardo and Durer, saw beauty wherever mortal flesh testified to 
the immortal axioms of Euclidean geometry. 

However, the ideal to which the bloated Venus of Willendorf testi- 
fies with her pendulous breasts and enormous hips, is not Euclid, but 
the goddess of Fertility. Our whole manner of perceiving the human 
frame depends on our ideas about its purpose or function — on the 
selective code which determines our criteria of significance and patterns 
our vision. I am using here the word 'fixnction' in the dictionary sense, 
as referring to a 'mode of action by which [a thing] fulfils its purpose*. 
The definition, of course, takes it for granted that we know what the 
purpose of the thing in question is. Now if the thing is a railway en- 
gine, the answer is clear; but the purpose of the thing called a human 
body is open to various interpretations. And according to the inter- 
pretation of human purpose which we accept, our ideas will change, 
and our manner of seeing the human body in its functional aspect will 
change accordingly. In the drawings of some lunatics, adolescents, 
lavatory artists, and tribesmen, the dominant functional aspect is 
shown by a huge genital part, while the remainder of the body is 
only indicated by a sketchy outline. On Egyptian wan-paintings and 
reliefs, conventionalized and schematized figures are shown function- 
ing as fishermen, hunters, builders, servants, or parts of a state pro- 
cession. The size of the figures is usually proportionate to their rank 
—not to bodily but to social stature; male skin is painted dark brown, 
female skin pale yellow; the code which provides the criteria of rele- 
vance is not visual but conceptual. For three thousand years the 
sculptors and painters of Egypt produced no original discoveries in 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 369 

the technique of visual representation. They had no visual curiosity. 
In its indifference to colour, movement, human anatomy, Egyptian 
painting was more single-mindedly functional than any before or 
after; but 'function was defined as social function, a person's rank and 
occupation in the social hierarchy. Apart from that, individuals are 
interchangeable, without personal identity, and their appearance de- 
void of interest. 

In the golden age of Greek art, the human body was seen in a 
totally different aspect, that of its physical function: in throwing a 
disc, tying a sandal, or simply lifting an arm; vision is attuned to geo- 
metrical proportion, to the play and co-ordination of muscles and 
joints; and by the criterion of a perfect physique, with facial expressions 
limited to types, the curve of the buttocks becomes as important and 
expressive as the curve of the brow. Again, in Byzantine painting the 
human body functions as an indifferent, and often awkward, shell of 
the spirit; and if the spirit commands the saint to bend his head back 
and gaze rapturously into the sky, the artist has no qualms in breaking 
his neck and letting the body float upward with all limbs out of joint. 
The Renaissance once more gave the body its due; and in the centuries 
that followed it became the carrier of an individual head, and hence 
of an expression and mood. For the courtiers of Louis XV, the prin- 
cipal function of human bodies was to play, suitably covered and un- 
covered, hide-and-seek between trees and bosquets, and to fall into 
each other's arms. For the impressionist painter, the function of the 
body is to demonstrate the impermanence of appearances in the 
luminous blurr of colours; for the cubist, to prove God's preference 
for cubes; and so on. 

"Which aspects of reality dominate the visual matrix of a culture or 
group depends dtimately on its conception of the purpose and mean- 
ing of existence. Accordingly, its norms of beauty will always reflect 
the archetype of some kind of functional perfection: the rigid dignity 
of Pharaoh, through whose eyes eternity looks in stony silence at 
time; the play of muscles in the Greek adolescent's perfect anatomy; 
the spirituality in the transfigured face of the Byzantine madonna; the 
harmonious resolution of the body into Euclidean forms, or a patch- 
work of coloured blobs. Whichever aspect is dominant, its matrix 
acts as a kind of optical polariscope, through which the particular 
appearance is seen as a thing of general significance, an embodiment 
of some universal law or meaning. 



Pigment and Meaning 



Abstract painting is a misnomer, a contradiction in terms as 'pictorial 
philosophy* would be. The concept of justice is an abstraction. The 
concept of a square is an abstraction. A picture of Solomon meting 
out justice is concrete. But the picture of a blue square on a yellow 
ground is equally concrete. 

'Non-representational art* and 'expressionist art' are serviceable 
labels for certain styles of painting; but if they are supposed to describe 
a philosophy or a programme, they are equally misleading and can 
create only confusion. A pattern of pigment on canvas always means, 
or expresses, or represents something which is not the canvas plus 
pigment. However, it does not represent objects or events, but the 
artist's mental experiences or imaginings of the nature, causes, shape, 
and colour of objects and events. It does not represent a model, but 
the artist's vision of the model; not a young lady called Lisa, but the 
way Leonardo saw his Lisa. It invites the spectator to share an ex- 
perience which the artist had; it provides him with an illusion — not the 
illusion of seeing a thing, but the illusion of seeing through the artist's 
eyes. Without that illusion there will be no response, and the spectator 
will behold the canvas through the eyes of a dead fish. 

Art was always expressionist' in the legitimate sense of the word: 
it expressed a subjective, biassed vision— even if the artist deluded him- 
self into believing that he was 'copying nature*. And pigment on 
canvas always 'represents* something outside its frame — for instance 
the impact of a green arrow on the blue square when placed next to 
it on the yellow ground. That impact does not take place on the can- 
vas, but in thcartist's mind, and in the beholder's mind. The pigment 
of the blue square remained static and unchanged. But in the be- 
holder's eye its colour, shape, and weight have undergone a dynamic 
change. To produce this illusionary change was the artist's intention; 
it is as if he were saying: Look what my green arrow can do to my 
blue square. The canvas expresses or represents an idea in the artist's 
head, and if all goes well it will cause a similar experience to occur in 
the beholder's head: he will read something in the picture which 
stricdy speaking is not there. Apologies for the pedantic demonstration, 
but one has to revert to elementary issues to escape the muddle created 
by the writings of some expressionists and anti-representationalists. 

Much of this confusion (as in other impassioned controversies in 
the past) is due to the fact that visual experiences cannot be traduced 

370 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



371 



into verbal statements without suffering major impoverishment and 
distortion. All verbal analysis tends to make implicit, part-conscious 
experiences explicit and fully conscious — and to destroy them in the 
process. There seems to exist a kind of biological rivalry between the 
eye and the vocal cords, epitomized by the painter puffing at his pipe 
in contemptuous silence while the garrulous art-critic is holding form. 
We always see a work of nature or art 'in terms of a selective matrix 
governed by this or that criterion of significance; but these 'terms' are 
not verbal terms, and if we attempt to verbalize them the result is 
unavoidably a gross 'dumsification — a medley of cliches and psycho- 
logical jargon. The matrix may carry emotive echoes of some arche- 
typal experience, but our vocabulary is extremely poor where emo- 
tions are concerned. If we say that it responds to the sight of the ocean 
with associations of eternity', 'infinity', and so forth, this sounds as 
if we were referring to verbal associations. Such words may present 
themselves to the mind, but words are the least important part of the 
experience, and detract from rather than add to its value. We cannot 
help using words in referring to processes which in the listener's mind 
are not crystallized into words. The alternative is to say a rose is a 
rose is a rose, and leave it at that. 

Another difficulty is that at moments of intense aesthetic experience 
we see not only with our eyes but with the whole body. The eyes 
scan, the cortex thinks, there are muscular stresses, innervations of the 
organs of touch, sensations of weight and temperature, visceral re- 
actions, feelings of rhythm and motion — all sucked into one integrated 
vortex. A literary narrative or a piece of music unfolds in stages, but 
in a still-life time is fore-shortened as it were, and by taking it in with 
a single sweep of the eye (or so it seems) this multitude of experiences 
blends into one near-simultaneous process, so that it is extremely dim- 
cult to sort out the various elements which went into its making. The 
trouble with explaining visual beauty, and also its fascination, is that 
so much is happening at the same time. 



The Two Environments 

What is happening is, put into our jargon, a series of bisociative pro- 
cesses involving the participatory emotions. 

At the base of the series we again find illusion — the magic transforma- 
tion of the carved tree into a god. The painted mask, the carved 



372 THE ACT OF CREATION 

idol, are perceived at the same time as what they are and what they 
represent The witch-doctor works his evil spell by sticking a needle 
into the rag-doll representing the victim; the cave-artist of Altamira 
made sure of a plentiful supply of meat by populating the rock with 
painted bison and wild horses. 

To those with naive tastes, illusion in itself is sufficient to evoke 
aesthetic experience, and 'life-likeness' is regarded as the supreme 
criterion of art. As mentioned before, even Leonardo wrote 'that 
painting is most praiseworthy which is most like the thing represented'. 
However, the 'most like' has an infinite number of interpretations — 
and that for two solid reasons: the limitations of the medium and the 
prejudices of vision. The range of luminosity in the painter's pigment 
is only a fraction of that of natural colours; the area on the canvas only 
a fraction of the visual field; its coarse grain can accommodate only 
a fraction of fine detail; it lacks the dimension of depth in space, and 
motion in time. (Even a photograph is far from being a true likeness; 
apart from its obvious limitations of colour and light = sensitivity, 
it increases the ratio of focal to peripheral vision about a hundredfold 
— which may be one of the reasons why nature is so much prettified 
on picture postcards.) Hence the painter is forced to cheat, to invent 
tricks, to exaggerate, simplify, and distort in order to correct the dis- 
torting effects of the medium. The way he cheats, the tricks he uses, 
are partly determined by the requirements of the medium itself— he 
must think 'in terms of stone, wood, pigment, or gouache — but 
mainly by the idiosyncrasies of his vision: the codes which govern the 
matrices of his perception. Whether Manet's impression of 'The Races 
of Longchamp' looks more 'life-like* than Frith's academically meticu- 
lous 'Derby Day' depends entirely on the beholder's spectacles. An 
artist can copy in plaster, up to a point, a Roman copy of a Greek 
bronze head; he cannot 'copy' on canvas a running horse. He can only 
create an appearance which, seen in a certain light, at a certain distance, 
in a certain mood, will suddenly acquire a life of its own. It is not a 
copy, but a metaphor. The horse was not a model, but a motif for his 
creation— in the sense in which the landscape painter looks for a 
romantic or pastoral motif. 

In the terminology of behaviourist psychology we would have to 
say that looking at the model constitutes the 'stimulus', and putting 
a dab of paint on the canvas the 'response' — and that is all there is to 
it. But the two activities take place on two different planes. The 
stimulus comes from one environment — the outer world: the response 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



373 



acts on a different environment: a square surface. The two environ- 
ments obey two different sets of laws. An isolated brush-stroke does 
not represent an isolated detail. There are no point-to-point corres- 
pondences between the two planes of the motif and the medium; 
they are bisociated as wholes in the artist's mind. 

Visual Inferences 

Once the artist has acquired sufficient technical skill to do with his 
material more or less what he likes, the question what he Ekes, i.e. 
what aspects of reality he considers relevant, becomes all-important. 
In other words, of the two variables I mentioned — the limitations of 
the medium, and the prejudiced eye beholding the motif, the first can 
be regarded, within a given school, as relatively stable, and we can 
concentrate our attention on the second. There can be no unprejudiced 
eye for the simple reason that vision is full of ambiguities, and all per- 
ception, as we saw, is an inferential construction which proceeds on 
various levels, and most of it unconsciously (cf. pp. 38-44). The visual 
constancies (p. 43) which enable us to perceive objects as stable in shape, 
size, colour, etc., in spite of their unstable, ever-changing appearances 
are a first step in the interpretation of our confusing, ambiguous retinal 
images. They are automatic skills, partly innate, mostly learned in 
early childhood. The process is reversed in some of the so-called optical 
illusions where the unconscious code governing preception draws the 
wrong inferences in an unusual situation. But even these primitive 
mechanisms, which normally function below the level of awareness, 
can suddenly become a problem in interpretation for the painter. I 
have mentioned (p. 43) that owing to the mechanism of brightness- 
constancy a black glove looks as black in sunlight as in the shade — 
until you look at it through a reduction screen in the experimental 
laboratory or through the impressionist painters crooked index-finger. 
The various constancies are unconscious inferences we draw to make 
sense of our sensations, to lend stability to the unstable flux of appear- 
ances. They transform what the eye sees so as to suit the requirements 
of reason, of what we know about the external world. Between the 
retina and the higher centres of the cortex the innocence of vision is 
irretrievably lost— it has succumbed to the suggestion of a whole series 
of hidden persuaders. 
Perceptual projection, which I have already mentioned (p. 295), is 



374 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



one of them: the unconscious mechanism which makes us project 
events, located in the brain, into a distance of yards or miles (as opposed 
to the dazzling flashes which are 'correctly' located on the retina). 
Foreshortening and perspective are consciously added twists to uncon- 
scious projection— like sensations in a phantom-limb: the flat canvas is 
the amputation stump. (The analogy is actually quite precise: pain, too, 
is located in the brain, but projected to the locus of the injury; the 
phenomenon of the phantom-limb is a secondary projection.) 

Projective empathy is another hidden persuader which I have briefly 
mentioned before (p. 296). Vernon Lee 3 regarded aesthetic experience 
as primarily derived from 'the attribution of our own moods of dy- 
namic experience, motor ideas, to shapes. We attribute to lines not 
only balance, direction, velocity, but also thrust, strain, feeling, inten- 
tion, and character.' Jaensch has been able to demonstrate in a fascina- 
ting series of experiments that the eidetic image (p. 346) of a straight 
horizontal line will expand considerably in length if a pull is exerted on 
the horizontally outstretched arms of the subject. 4 And vice versa, the 
sensation of the scanning motions performed by the eye, and of other 
subliminal muscle-impulses and stresses — not to mention Berenson s 
'tactile values*, the 'feel* of texture — all interfere with perception. 

Again, the painter can consciously exploit these unconscious pro- 
cesses, and give them an added twist. In Seurat's 'divisionist* theory, 
horizontal and gendy* ascending lines, as well as 'cool' colours convey 
a mood of calm and content, 'swift' and 'animated' lines and 'warm' 
colours make for gaiety, and so on. (The adjectives in quotes have 
become so current that we tend to overlook their synesthetic origin). 
Juan Gris, though certainly far removed from Seurat's neo-impres- 
sionism, talked in the same vein of expansive' and 'contractile' forms, 
of the physiological effects of various types of symmetry. 5 The theoriz- 
ings of the 'abstracts' are not at all new. Linear rhythm, chromatic 
harmonies, and their combined effects have always played, consciously 
or unconsciously, an important part. In non-figurative painting the 
motifs are, instead of a landscape and a human body, say blue squares 
and green arrows. But ultimately these too are derived from nature — 
the blue and the green, the square and the arrow. Let me invoke the 
authority of the greatest and most eclectic painter of our time: 

There is no abstract art. You must always start with something. 
Afterwards you can remove all traces of reality. There's no danger 
then anyway, because the idea of the object will have left an indelible 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



375 



mark. It is what started the artist off, excited his ideas, and stirred up 
his emotions. . . . When I paint a picture I am not concerned with 
the fact that two people may be represented in it. Those two people 
once existed for me but they exist no longer. My vision of them gave 
me an initial emotion, then little by little their presence became 
blurred; they became for me a fiction, and then they disappeared 
altogether, or rather they were transformed into all kinds of 
problems, so that they became for me no longer two people but 
forms and colours— forms and colours which nevertheless resume an 
experience of two people, and preserve the vibration of their life. 6 

I must add a word on a more primitive kind of attitude to colour. 
Some reactions to the 'temperature-values' of colours seems to be 
common to most people within the same culture circle; Rimbaud even 
tried to co-ordinate each vowel with a different colour. But the 
emotive associations of specific colours vary from person to person, 
and can be very strong. Wollberg 7 had a schizoid patient who reacted 
to red with intense anxiety, to blue with a feeling of elation; yet under 
deep hypnosis, Wollberg reversed these reactions. Valentine 8 quotes 
the case of a patient born blind who, after a successful operation, felt 
intense pleasure at his first sight of red, and was physically sick at the 
first sight of yellow. Man not only 'thinks with his hands', he quite 
often sees with his bowels. 

The visual constancies and illusions, perceptual projection, empathy 
and synesthesia form an ascending series of inferential processes. One 
step higher in the series we come to the phenomenon of the 'face 
hidden in the tree', the 'image in the cloud', the Rohrschach-blot: the 
projection of meaning into the ambiguous motif. Once more we have 
here an unconscious process which has been consciously exploited from 
antiquity to the expressionists. Pliny recounted the anecdote of an 
artist who tried in vain to paint the foam at a dog's mouth until, in 
exasperation, he threw a spongeful of paint at his canvas — and there 
was the foam. The story reappears in Leonardo's Treatise on Paintings 
— where he makes 'our Botticelli* say that if you just throw a sponge 
at a wall it will 'leave a blot where one sees a fine landscape*. There is 
an oft-quoted passage in that classic treatise which bears being quoted 
once more: 

You should look at certain walls stained with damp, or at stones of 
uneven colour. If you have to invent some backgrounds you will be 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



able to see in these the likeness of divine landscapes, adorned with 
mountains, ruins, rocks, woods, great plains, hills and valleys in 
great variety; and then again you will see there battles and strange 
figures in violent action, expressions of faces and clothes and an 
infinity of things which you will be able to reduce to their complete 
and proper forms. In such walls the same thing happens as in the 
sound of bells, in whose, stroke you may find every named word 
which you can imagine. 9 

This passage inspired the eighteenth-century English landscape 
painter Alexander Cozens to publish a book 10 recommending the use 
of random ink-blots 'from which ideas are presented to the mind', to 
serve as landscape motifs. It seems that Rohrschach's method of psy- 
chological testing by inviting subjects to interpret ambiguous blot- 
shapes was derived from Cozens — and thus from Leonardo, and thus 
from Pliny. Similar methods were used by Chinese artists from the 
eleventh century onwards. The bisociations of form and meaning are 
inexhaustible. 

In these cases the motif (the cloud, the patterned wallpaper, or the 
ink-blot) and also the meaning read into it, are both of a visual nature. 
But the matrix which provides the meaning can also be governed by 
non-visual conceptual codes — for instance, a verbal suggestion such as 
Hamlet uses on Polonius to make the cloud change from weasel to 
whale; or by the various notions entertained by Egyptian, Greek, and 
Byzantine artists on the function and purpose of the human body. In 
some forms of insanity, and in the experimental psychoses induced by 
drugs, the patient sees serpents, genitals, archaic creatures budding out 
of every curve of an ornamental design. The cubist's vocabulary 
consists of cylinders and cubes; the pointillist's of daub's; classical 
composition obeyed the grammar of harmony and balance; the 
Egyptian painter saw in stereotyped cliches; so does the Japanese Zen 
artist. 



Codes of Perception 

This leads us to the most powerful single factor among the many 
factors which enter into the processing of the visual input: the power 
of convention as a hidden persuader (p. 42 £). Perception is a part- 
innate, part-acquired skill of transforming the raw-material of vision 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



377 



into the 'finished product'; and every period has its conventional 
formulae and methods of interpretation for doing this. The ordinary 
mortal thitiWs most of the time in cliches — and sees most of the time in 
cliches. His visual schemata are prefabricated for him; he looks at the 
word through contact-lenses without being aware of it. 

The extreme example is ancient Egypt — but merely because it 
lasted so long; contemporary Zen painting and calligraphy, as already 
said, obeys almost as rigid rules of the game. The Egyptian painter 
unvaryingly represented the human figure with head in profile, eye 
frontally, legs in profile, chest frontally, and so on, showing each part 
in its most characteristic aspect. Whether the ordinary Egyptian per- 
ceived his fellow creatures this way we cannot tell, and— remembering 
that we perceive a tilted coin still as a circle, and not foreshortened 
into an ellipse — he probably could not tell either. But we do know that 
the moment he translated motif into medium, his vision became 
stereotyped. It is highly improbable that conformity was enforced on 
artists against their will for a full three thousand years. There exist 
exceptions to the rule, relief figures dating as far back as 2400 B.c., u 
which show foreshortening and dynamic motion; if there had been a 
taboo on such innovations, they would hardly have been preserved. 
But the exceptions became less, not more frequent as time went by; 
for reasons beyond our understanding, Egyptian art, as Egyptian 
society, remained static, and habit prevailed over originality. 

Greek art, between the sixth and fourth century B.C. was, compared 
with Egypt, in a state of permanent revolution, which carried it within 
no more than six or seven generations from the archaic style to the 
trompe Vail. Yet, although originality and innovation were valued as 
never before, it could not avoid developing its own cliches. 'After all,* 
wrote Gombrich, 'Greek art of the classical period concentrated on the 
image of man almost to the exclusion of other motifs, and even in the 
portrayal of man it remained wedded to types. This does not apply 
only to the idealized type of physique which we all associate with 
Greek art. Even in the rendering of movement and drapery the reper- 
toire of Greek sculpture and painting has turned out to be strangely 
limited. There are a restricted number of formulas for the rendering of 
figures standing, running, fighting, or falling, which Greek artists 
repeated with relatively slight variations over a long period of time. 
Perhaps if a census of such motifs were taken, the Greek vocabulary 
would be found to be not much larger than the Egyptian.* 18 

That vocabulary— and its Euclidean grammar of proportion — 



378 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



remained as indelibly printed on European art as the categories of 
Aristotle on European philosophy. The Byzantine painter and mosaic 
maker had given up the aspiration to copy nature, but he used the 
approved Greek stock-formulae to represent faces, hands, gestures, 
and draperies. Warburg 13 has shown that the artists of the Renaissance 
were prone to fall back on Greek models whenever they wanted to 
indicate emotion by a gesture or attitude: he called these emotive 
cliches Pathosformeln* 

'Even Dutch genre paintings that appear to mirror life in all its 
bustle and variety will turn out to be created from a limited number 
of types and gestures' — if for instance, one compares them with news- 
paper-photographs of crowd scenes. The quotation is again from 
Professor Gombrich, 14 whose Art and Illusion proved an invaluable 
source of illustrative examples. 

Skilled routine in perceiving as in thinking, has its positive and 
negative side. Without certain conventional rules of the game, which 
were acquired by learning but function unawares, we could not make 
much sense either of nature or of art. 'The art of seeing nature', 
Constable wrote, 'is a thing almost as much to be acquired as the art of 
reading Egyptian hieroglyphs.* 15 On the other hand, conventions tend 
to harden into rigid formulae — the matrix freezes up, and makes us 
ignore those aspects of reality which do not fit into the schema. The 
Greek sculptor is indifferent to individual expression, the Byzantine 
painter to anatomy, the Chinese to shadows, and so on. But there exist 
far more striking examples of the single-minded neglect by the eye of 
anything which the mind does not consider relevant. They are engrav- 
ings dating from the sixteenth to the nineteenth century, which show 
that even artists reputed for their meticulousness can be indifferent or 
blind to features which are considered irrelevant or offensive to the 
conventional rules of the game. One of them was Merian, an extremely 
skilful illustrator who obviously tried hard to make a faithful 'copy' — 
it looks actually like an architect's drawing — of the Cathedral of 
Notre-Dame. And what happened? *. . . As a child of the seventeenth 
century, his notion of a church is that of a lofty symmetrical building 
with large, rounded windows, and that is how he designs Notre-Dame. 
He places the transept in the centre with four large, rounded windows 
on either side, while the actual view shows seven narrow, pointed 
Gothic windows to the west and six in the choir/ 16 He could not go 
against the code which governed his visual perception. 

Nor could those medieval artists, who drew lions, elephants, and 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



379 



other exotic animals 'from life', but, incapable of visually digesting the 
startling appearance, produced monstrosities reminding one of Greek 
chimeras — creatures compounded of a lion's head, a goat's body and 
a serpent's tail. The reason is simple. The codification of experience 
into 'rules of the game* is as indispensable in perceptual skills as in 
manual or reasoning skills. The learning process starts in the cot and 
ends only when the artist has learned to forget what he has learned — 
but that is only for the chosen few. The medieval artist-— like the con- 
temporary amateur taking a correspondence course in draftsmanship 
— did not start by drawing from nature, but by learning, from drawing- 
books, the tricks and formulae of how to draw heads, hands, and feet, 
birds, stags, trees, and clouds. There were hundreds of such works 
published, from Villard de Honecourt's Album of Patterns in the first 
half of the thirteenth century to date — including such classics as 
Diirer's Dresden Sketchbook or Fialetti's The True Method and Order to 
Draw All Parts and Limbs of the Human Body — which seems to contain 
every conceivable shape and mis-shape of ears, eyes, and noses under 
the sun. To succeed in drawing an ear with an untutored eye requires" 
genius; even Diirer, so we are told, got the anatomy of the human eye 
wrong. 

To quote Constable again: an artist who is self-taught is taught by 
a very ignorant person indeed. He must acquire a vocabulary — not 
only to express himself, but to read meaning into appearances. The 
same Villard de Honecourt whose album of patterns contains the 
most admirably schematized swans, horses, ostriches, and bearded 
heads drew a lion 'from life', as he assures us — and produced a chimera. 
We do not know for how long he had the chance of looking at the 
lion or how coherent his sketch was. But it is evident that where he 
had to fill in features from memory, he could only do so by supplanting 
the forgotten details of the strange creature by parts of more familiar 
animals. He had certainly not intended to falsify deliberately — any 
more than Merian did in his drawings of Notre-Dame. But neither of 
them could digest the unfamiliar motif because it could not be re- 
solved into familiar schemata, pigeonholed, labelled, and confined to 
memory — or jotted down in shorthand, as it were, by means of a 
ready-made formula. They were in the same position as the subjects 
in the psychological laboratory who are made to witness an unex- 
pected sequence of events — and, when asked to relate what happened, 
give notoriously divergent, unreliable accounts. Their verbal re- 
production is jumbled, not because they lack the skill to express 



38o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



themselves, but because they were unable to take in a sequence of 
events which did not fit their scheme of things. 

Not only the medieval artist used formulae like recipes from a 
cookery-book. Camper, an eighteenth-century anatomist, wrote a 
book on The Connection Between the Science of Anatomy and the Arts 
of Drawing, Painting, Statuary, etc., in which he described the standard 
procedures of portraiture in his time: 'The portrait painters of the 
present day generally describe an oval upon their panel before the 
person to be painted sits to be drawn, make a cross in the oval, which 
they divide into the length of four noses and the breadth of five eyes; 
and they paint the face according to these divisions to which it must 
be accommodated, let the proportions themselves be ever so much at 
variance.' 17 The oval with its subdivisions represented the matrix with 
its fixed code; the ftlling-in of details was a matter of elastic strategy. 

Convention and Creation 

Regardless of the period at which we look, every work of art betrays 
the prejudiced eye, governed by selective codes which lend coherence 
to the artist's vision, and at the same time restrict his freedom. The 
ensemble of these codes provides the 'rules of the game', the routine 
aspect of his work; while his 'strategy' must be adapted to the double 
environment of motif and medium. The greatness of an artist rests in 
creating a new, personal idiom — an individual code which deviates 
from the conventional rules. Once the new idiom — a new way of 
bisociating motif and medium — is established, a whole host of pupils 
and imitators can operate it with varying degrees of strategic skill. 

It does not mean belittling the creative mind to point out that every 
artist has his cookery recipes for the basic ingredients of the dishes he 
serves. But we must distinguish between true creativity — the invention 
of a new recipe, on the one hand, and the skilled routine of providing 
variations of it. The whole, vexed question of the artistic value oforilliant 
forgeries and copies hinges on this distinction (see Chapter XXIV). 

But whether the rules of the game were imposed by convention or 
originally designed by the artist, they have an equal sway over him. 
Rubens' puttis sometimes look mass-produced, and even some of the 
portraits of his children seem to obey the same formula; similar blas- 
phemies could be uttered about Renoir's pneumatic nudes, Henry 
Moore's convexities and concavittes-wira-a-hole, or Bernard Buffet's 



MOTIF AND MEDIUM 



381 



obsessive angularities. One cannot help feeling that artists who spend 
the rest of their lives exploring the possibilities of a single formula 
which they discovered in their truly creative period, resemble the 
'one-idea-men' in the history of science. The difference is that the 
concrete language of the painter's brush permits endless variations on 
a single theme without losing its enchantment-— which the abstract 
symbol-language of science does not. 

The reader may have felt, in following the last few pages, an uneasy 
suspicion that I was deliberately confusing the tricks and formulae 
for drawing a pussycat with the artist's vision of the pussycat, and the 
history of painting with a history of seeing. But in fact the two interact 
so intimately in the artist's mind (and in the responsive beholder's 
mind) that they cannot be separated. Take seeing first; already Pliny 
knew (what Behaviourist psychology managed to forget) that 'the 
mind is the real instrument of sight and observation' and the eyes merely 
act 'as a kind of vehicle, receiving and transmitting the visual portion 
of consciousness'. 18 But the mind is also the real instrument of manual 
dexterity, in a much deeper sense than we generally realize, including 
those quirks of manner and style which can be 'left to the muscles' to 
be taken care of. Renoir, when his ringers became crippled with 
arthritis, painted with a brush attached to his forearm, yet his style 
remained unchanged. It would be psychologically just as absurd to 
assume the reverse — that a pattern of expression so deeply ingrained 
should have had no effect on his pattern of perception, as it would be 
to assume that his perception had no influence on what his hand was 
doing. The two activities are bisociated; in the terminology of the 
communication engineer, the medium 'in terms of which the artist 
must think, influences by feed-back his pattern of vision. 

An obvious example is provided by the way in which the study 
of anatomy— even if merely demonstrated by a lay-figure — trans- 
forms the artist's perception of the human body. A less obvious 
example is the following — which I again owe to Gombrich. Cozens, 
the eighteenth-century painter who advocated the ink-blot technique 
to inspire his pupils to paint 'Rohrschach' landscapes, also drew for 
their benefit a series of schemata of various types of cloud-formation — 
as Guercino had given recipes for drawing various types of ears. 
Constable studied and faithfully copied these crude schematizations of 
'streaky clouds at the top of the sky' or 'bottom of the sky' or clouds 
'darker at the top than the bottom'. By learning to distinguish different 
types of cloud-formation — acquiring an articulate cloud-vocabulary as 



382 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



it were— he was able to perceive clouds, and to paint clouds, as nobody 
had done before, His brush, like the poet's pen, 'turned them into 
shapes, and gave to airy nothing a local habitation and a name'. The 
result is that Constable addicts see real clouds in Constable's terms, as 
Van Gogh addicts see the fields of Provence in Van Gogh's terms— 
and in either case much to their benefit. Some French authors — Lalo, 
I believe was the first, and among contemporaries, Malraux— have 
proposed that our aesthetic appreciation of nature is derived from 
having seen landscapes in paint. That may be the case with many of us, 
but it only means — as suggested already at the beginning of this chapter — 
that man has always looked at nature through a frame. Through the 
painter's frame, or the frame of mythology, or the frame of science; 
through half-closed eyes or eye glued to the lens of the telescope. 
Constable called landscape painting an inquiry into the laws of nature; 
and Richardson, discovering that the difficulties of his pupils were 
caused as much by their unskilled eye as by their unskilled fingers, 
drew the conclusion: 

For it is a certain maxim, no man sees what things are, that knows 
not what they ought to be. That this maxim is true, will appear by 
an academy figure drawn by one ignorant in the .structure, and 
butting of the bones, and anatomy, compared with another who 
understands these thoroughly . . . both see the same life, but with 
different eyes. 10 

NOTES 

To p. 366. I am speaking of Europe: landscape painting in China has a 
much older tradition. 

To p. 378. Incidentally, there is a bridge waiting to be' built between art 
criticism and the physiology of gesture. To give an example: the neurologist 
Kurt Goldstein (1947) has made a study of the way in which people point with 
their arms at an object. If the object is to the front and to the right, the person 
will point with the extended arm, which will form with the frontal plane of the 
body an angle of approximately forty-five degrees. If the object is moved further 
to the right, the person will start turning his trunk to the right, so that the angle 
between body and arm remains 45 degrees. But if the object is placed straight 
in front ofhim, he will turn his body to the left and the angle will still be the same. 
There are obvious anatomical reasons for this. But if you make your figure point 
an musing finger straight ahead, fully racing his adversary, you get a 'pathos- 
formula*. 



XXII 

IMAGE AND EMOTION 



The trouble with putting into words the aesthetic experience 
aroused by a picture is, as we saw, that so much is happening 
at the same time; that only a fraction of it becomes conscious, 
and an even smaller fraction verbalized. 'The forceps of our minds', to 
quote H. G. Wells again, 'are clumsy things, and crush the truth a 
little in the course of taking hold of it.' Wells was talking of the 
difficulties of putting ideas into words; when it comes to putting aesthe- 
tic experiences into words, nothing short of a caesarian will help. The 
surgical tool that I proposed was 'bisociation; and the operation con- 
sisted in disentangling the various bisociative, or bifocal, processes 
which combine in the experience. I have mentioned a number of 
these; I shall have to mention one or two more, and discuss briefly the 
emotional reactions which they call forth. 

Virtues of the Picture Postcard 

The essence of the aesthetic experience consists, as I have tried to show, 
in intellectual illumination — seeing something familiar in a new, signifi- 
cant light; followed by emotional catharsis — the rise, expansion, and ebb- 
ing away of the self-transcending emotions. But this can happen only 
if the matrix which provides the 'new light* has a higher emotive 
potential or 'calory value' (pp. 321-31); in other words, the two 
matrices must lie on an ascending gradient. 

Let us see in what manner the various bisociative patterns mentioned 
earlier on fulfil this requirement. Take illusion once more, which 
enters art in a variety of guises and disguises, on its most naive level: 
the discovery that something can be itself and something else at the 

383 



384 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



same time. A small child, fascinated by dad's amateur efforts as a 
draftsman, will beg 'make me a donkey', 'make me an elephant', thus 
unconsciously evoking Pygmalion's power. I shall not hark back to 
Altamira and the witch-doctor — merely dot my i's by pointing out 
that the gradient leads in that direction. 

Or take the simplest illusion of space: the delighted shock of looking 
for the first time through fieldglasses, and seeing the distant church- 
spire leap to within grasp. Here again unconscious analogies, echoes of 
sorcery enter into play: the power to be in two places at once; the 
conquest of space by magic carpet; action-at-a-distance. The reverse 
experience is the illusion derived from a perspective landscape — or a 
Chinese silk painting which, with a few brushstrokes, makes the 
horizon recede into infinity. To call perspective and trompe Vceil 
'magic* is a cliche, because their genuine magic has succumbed to the 
law of diminishing returns; but to the unsophisticated eye the hole in 
the wall through which it looks into a different world has the dream- 
like quality of Alice stepping through the looking-glass; dream-like, 
because the creation and annihilation of space is a favoured game of 
the underground. 

I have made a slighting mention of the 'petrification' of nature on 
picture postcards, which bring the whole scenery within the range of 
focal vision. But there is a genuine appeal to the emotions in the fact 
that a landscape painting can be taken in almost at a glance, without 
the half-conscious, constant scanning which the real scenery requires. 
To have it all there simultaneously laid out before his view, gives the 
beholder a kind of naive Olympian feeling, a sense of power entirely 
harmless, since his only aim is passive contemplation; enhanced by 
the cfrcumstance — and here the next bisociation enters into the process 
— that he is looking at the scenery not through his own, but through 
Claude's or Courbet's eyes. 

Another facet — or pair of facets—of the many-sided experience of 
looking at a picture is synesthesia (p. 321). Berenson's dictum 'the 
painter can accomplish his task only by giving tactile values to retinal 
impressions' does not only mean that the bisociation of vision with 
touch lends an added dimension to experience and more solidity to 
illusion. Berenson's emphasis on tactile values also indicates that the 
sense of touch had a special appeal to him — as it had to Keats (p. 321). 
But neither of them was exceptional in this respect; after all, the 
adjective 'touching* — that is, emotionally moving — is derived from 
touch; and 'touching' in the verbal sense is a primary impulse not 



IMAGE AND EMOTION 



385 



only among lovers; the texture of silk or polished stone also provides 
minor pleasures. The brocade fineries of Van Eyck's figures have a 
strong tactile appeal; the impact of the gangrened flesh of Christ in 
Griinewald's Isenheim altar is one of horror redeemed by pity. It is- 
perhaps only matched in power by Flaubert's rendering of the legend 
of St. Julian sharing his bed with the leper. 

Taste and Distaste 

This brings us to a subject which I have not mentioned so far, although 
it used to play an important part in aesthetic theories of the hedonistic 
type, and was a wonderful source of confusion: I mean the polarity 
of agreeable and disagreeable, attractive and repellent sense-impressions. 

The first necessity, if we wish to avoid similar confusion, is to make 
a clear distinction between tastes and distastes directly affecting the 
senses (the tongue, the nose, the ear); and the pleasure-unpleasure tone 
of complex emotional states mediated by the autonomous nervous sys- 
tem. The distinction may seem pedantic, and a sharp line cannot always 
be drawn, because the different levels in the nervous system interact 
with each other; the palate can be Educated* to delight in rotten 
Chinese eggs, and the smell of honeysuckle can become nauseating to 
the rejected lover. Whether the selective codes which govern our 
spontaneous reactions of taste and distaste are inborn or acquired in early 
childhood is irrelevant in this context; and the fact that these reactions 
can be altered in later life does not affect the argument. What matters 
is to distinguish between the aesthetic experience — or the experience 
of beauty if you like — on the one hand, and sensory gratification on the 
other; and to get away from such definitions as the Concise Oxford's 
of beauty: 'Combination of qualities . . . that delights the sight; com- 
bined qualities delighting the other senses', etc. Evidently, by these 
criteria not only Grunewald, but the vast majority of works of art 
would be beyond the pale of beauty and could never give rise to 
aesthetic experience— defined by the Concise Oxford Dictionary as 
'the appreciation of the beautiful*. 

I do not mean to flog the dead horse of hedonist aesthetics but to 
emphasize the difference between sensory gratification and aesthetic 
satisfaction — a difference of levels deriving from the hierarchic organi- 
zation of the nervous system (Chapter XIII and Book Two). Take 
an obvious example from music. Periodic sounds — musical tones — 



386 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



are more pleasing to the ear than a-periodic noises; and some screeching 
noises — rubbing a blackboard with a dry sponge for instance — are 
so offensive that they give gooseflesh to some people. Again, among 
musical chords, the octave, fifth, and major third are more agreeable 
to the European ear than others; and some dissonances, heard in 
isolation, can put one on edge. But the flattery or ofFensiveness of 
individual chords has only an indirect bearing on the emotional 
effect of a string quartet as a whole. There is no numerical relation 
between the number of consonances and our aesthetic appreciation. 
The pattern of alternation between sweet and bitter sounds is merely 
one among several relevant patterns interacting with each other in 
the multi-dimensional experience. 

Sensory preferences — the dismrnmation between sensory stimula- 
tions which 'agree', and those which 'disagree* with our innate or 
acquired dispositions — do not provide the clue to the nature of aesthetic 
experience, but they provide one of the clues: particularly those pre- 
ferences which are part of the human heritage, and shared by all. The 
Chinese taste for music differs from ours considerably; but all men 
are subject to the pull of gravity and prefer keeping their balance to 
losing it. A leaning tower, or a big head on a thin neck give rise to dis- 
agreeable sensations mediated by projective empathy (p. 296). But 
this again is only part of the story. Inverted, top-heavy, disturbing 
forms may combine in the picture with forms in repose, creating a 
total pattern with a balance of a higher order— in which the parts 
with positive and negative balance play the same role as con- 
sonant and dissonant chords, or beats and missed beats in a metric 
stanza. 

One of the most haunting pictures in this particular respect is 
Pollaiulo's 'Martyrdom of St. Sebastian , (in the London National 
Gallery). The saint stands with his naked feet on the sawn-off stumps 
of two branches of a dead tree, his hands tied behind his back, looking 
as if he were bound to topple over any moment. He is held up by 
another, hardly visible, branch of a tree which rises behind him, and 
to which his hands are presumably tied; but even so he is bound to 
fall. What prevents him, in the beholders eye, from falling is a trick 
in the composition of the picture: the figure of the saint forms the 
apex of a solid, well-balanced triangle. The sides of the triangle are 
six figures in symmetrical poses, performing symmetrical gestures. 
The imbalance of the part is redeemed by the balance of the whole, 
by the triangle which lends unity to diversity. The fact that the 



IMAGE AND EMOTION 



387 



figures are the saint's executioners, shooting their murderous arrows 
into him, belongs to a different level of awareness. 

Empathy projects our own dynamic experiences of gravity, balance, 
stress, and striving into the pigment on the canvas representing human 
figures or inert shapes. Thus vertical and horizontal lines acquire a 
special eminence; a vertical line looks longer than a tilted line of the 
same length, and right angles are so much singled out, that an angle 
of, say, ninety-five degrees is seen as an imperfect, 'bad' angle of ninety 
degrees. Patients with brain lesions sometimes give freer rein than 
normal people to the hedonistic bias of their eyes, and do not notice 
deviations up to ten degrees from the horizontal or vertical. They 
indulge in 'wishful seeing' as others in wishful thinking. And to a 
lesser extent that is true of all of us. Goethe knew that after-images 
which appear on the retina tend to reduce irregularities and asym- 
metries, and to transform squares into circles. The Gestalt school has 
shown that the raw material of the visual input is subjected to yet 
other kinds of processing than those I have mentioned: the 'closure 
principle' makes us automatically fill in the gaps in a broken outline; 
'Pragnanz' (conciseness), 'good continuation , symmetry, simplicity 
are further built-in criteria of excellence which prejudice our per- 
ceptions. But once again, it can hardly be maintained that the delights 
of looking at a perfect circle with a closed circumference, and the 
disgust with circles marred by a bulge, enter directly into the aesthetic 
experience. If that were the case, the perfect picture would be a perfect 
circle with a vertical and a horizontal line intersecting in its centre; all 
hedonistic principles and Gestalt-criteria would be satisfied by it. The 
innate bias in our taste-buds in favour of sweet compared with acid 
stimuli is a fact which every theory of culinary aesthetics must take 
into account; but it does not make syrup the ideal of culinary per- 
fection. Symmetry and asymmetry, closure and gap, continuity and 
contrast, must combine, like consonances and dissonances, into a 
pattern on a higher level of the perceptual hierarchy — as far removed 
from Freud's pleasure-principle as from the Oxford Dictionary's defini- 
tion of beauty. 

Motion and Rest 

That pattern is in fact our old friend, unity-in-diversity ; or rather unity 
implied in diversity, for here the 'law of infolding' asserts itself with a 
vengeance. If a work of art strikes one as hopelessly dated, it is not 



388 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



because its particular idiom dates from a remote period, but because 
it is spelt out in a too obvious, explicit manner. The Laocoon group is 
more dated than the archaic Apollo of Tenea in spite of the vasdy 
superior representational skill of the Hellenistic period—which the 
sculptor displays with such self-defeating ostentation. Pollainolo's delight 
in the recendy discovered laws of perspective, and the resulting over- 
emphasis on geometrical structure has a somewhat chilling effect; 
the same could be said of Uccello's 'The Rout of San Romano*. Again 
(as Eric Newton has pointed out), the triangular scaffolding in 
Raphael's treatment of the Madonna and Child theme is a shade too 
obvious. To discover the principle of unity hidden in variety must be 
left to the beholder's imagination. Leonardo has given a 'formula' how 
to draw trees: if you draw a circle round the crown of a tree, the 
sections of all the twigs must add up to the thickness of the stem; the 
bigger the radius of the circle, the more twigs it will cut, but because 
the sections get thinner, the result is the same. Though the law is not 
exact, it holds the secret which lends unity to the tree drawn in its 
full foliage, and implied symmetry to its irregularly shaped branches 
and twigs. 

Unity-in-variety can be debased to a formula: the portrait painter 
drawing his oval and dividing it into the length of four noses; it can 
also be a peephole to eternity. 'Motion or change/ wrote Emerson, 
*and identity or rest, are the first and second secrets of nature: Motion 
and Rest. The whole code of her laws may be written on the thumb- 
nail or the signet of a ring. The whirling bubble on the surface of a 
brook, admits us to the secrets of the mechanics of the sky. Every 
shell on the beach is a key to it. A little water made to rotate in a cup 
explains the formation of the simpler shells; the addition of matter 
from year to year, arrives at last at the most complex form; and yet so 
poor is nature with all her craft, that, from the beginning to the end 
of the universe, she has but one stuff—but one stuff with its two ends, 
to serve up her dream-like variety. Compound it how she will, star, 
sand, fire, water, tree, man, it is still one stuff, and betrays the same 
properties/ 

I owe this quotation from Emerson's essay on 'Nature' to G. Kepes* 
The New Landscape — one of the most remarkable books on art in 
recent years. It opens up a world as unattainable to the limited range 
of our senses — the narrow biological filter of perception — as light and 
colour are unattainable to the blind. 'Of the total stimuli flooding the 
world with potential messages, the visible and audible ranges acces- 



IMAGE AND EMOTION 



389 



sible to our bodies represent a tiny segment/ 1 But it has now become 
possible to decipher these signals and bring their message into visible 
focus by instruments which expand and compress events in time, 
penetrate space near to the border where granules of matter are revealed 
as patterns of concentrated energy, and enable the eye to see 'in terms 
of ultra-violet and infra-red radiations. All of us have seen an occa- 
sional photograph of a spiral nebula or a snow-crystal, but these are like 
early daguerreotypes compared with the new landscapes seen through 
the electron-microscope. They show the ultra-structure of the world 
— electric discharges in a high voltage arc which look like the most 
elaborate Brussels lace, smoke molecules of magnesium oxide like a 
composition by Mondrian, nerve-synapses inside a muscle suspended 
like algae, phantom-figures of swirling heated air, ink molecules 
travelling through water, crystals like Persian carpets, and ghostly 
mountains inside the micro-structure of pure Hafnium, like an illus- 
tration to Dante's Purgatorio. What strikes one is that these land- 
scapes, drawn as it were in invisible ink, possess great intrinsic beauty 
of form. The aesthetic experience derived from them seems to be 
directly related to what Emerson called the first and second secrets of 
nature: 'Motion or change, and identity or rest' — and also to the 
fact that the universe is made of only one stuff with a finite set 
of basic geometrical patterns in an infinite number of dynamic 
variations. 

'There are two basic morphological archetypes,' wrote Kepes, 
'expression of order, coherence, discipline, stability on the one hand; 
expression of chaos, movement, vitality, change on the other. 
Common to the morphology of outer and inner processes, these are 
basic polarities recurring in physical phenomena, in the organic 
world and in human experience.' They are 'the dynamic substance of 
our universe, written in every corner of nature'. . . . "Wherever we 
look, we find configurations that are either to be understood as 
patterns of order, of closure, of a tendency towards a centre, co- 
hesion and balance, or as patterns of mobility, freedom, change, or 
opening. We recognize them in every visible pattern; we respond 
to their expression in nature's configurations and in human utter- 
ances, gestures, and acts. Cosmos and chaos ... the Apollonian 
spirit of measure and the Dionysian principle of chaotic life, organiza- 
tion and randomness, stasis and kinesis ... all these are different 
aspects of the same polarity of configuration/ 2 



390 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Thus the cliche about unity-in-variety represents one of the most 
powerful archetypes of human experience — cosmos arising out of 
chaos. "We have seen it at work in the scientist's search for universal 
law; and when we see it reflected in a work of art, or in any corner of 
nature, however indirectly, we catch a faint echo of it. 

Ascending Gradients 

When I compared the landscape of the smoke micrograph to a Mon- 
drian composition, I was not merely indulging the metaphoric con- 
sciousness; for another strange thing about these shapes not meant for 
the human eye is that they all look like something else. But not in the 
same way as the ink-blot which serves as a passive receptacle for our 
projections; they are so precise and well-defined that they seem to 
ask for an equally definite meaning. The electric discharge does look 
unmistakably like lace-work, the various unexpected shapes which a 
water-drop assumes during its fall through the air look unequivocally 
like a chain of semi-precious stones; and when no concrete interpreta- 
tion presents itself, some painter's work comes to mind. To be told 
that die Brussels lace is actually the 'portrait of an alternating current 
reversing its direction a hundred and twenty times per second' pro- 
vides an additional shock: the sudden substitution of a new matrix, 
a different contact-lens has the effect of a sudden iUurnination. The 
sparkling electric discharge still looks like lacework, and the Hafnium 
crystal still looks like a mountain in Hades, but the original interpreta- 
tion has now become a metaphor, which supplies an additional 
dimension, and feeds more calories to the experience. 

The mind is insatiable for meaning, drawn from, or projected into, 
the world of appearances, for unearthing hidden analogies which 
connect the unknown with the familiar, and show the familiar in an 
unexpected light. It weaves the raw material of experience into pat- 
terns, and connects them with other patterns; the fact that something 
reminds me of something else can itself become a potent source of 
emotion. Girls fall in love with men who remind them of father; 
men get infatuated with a reflection of Botticelli in a vacuous profile; 
every face is a palimpsest. The willow's shoulders droop, limp like a 
mourning widow's; the ripples on the lake reflect the Pythagorean 
harmonies; the whirlpool on the surface of die brook 'admits us to 
the mechanics of the sky'. When a painting is said to represent nothing 



IMAGE AND EMOTION 



391 



but 'significant form' — to carry no meaning, no associative connec- 
tions, no reference to anything beyond itself— we can be confident 
that the speaker does not know what he is talking about. Neither the 
artist, nor the beholder of his work, can slice his mind into sections, 
separate sensation from perception, perception from meaning, sign 
from symbol. 

The difficulty of analysing the aesthetic experience is not due to its 
irreducible quality, but to the wealth, the unconscious and non- 
verbal character of the matrices which interlace in it, along ascending 
gradients in various dimensions. Whether the gradient is as steep and 
dramatic as in a Griinewald or El Greco, or gently ascending through 
green pastures, it always points towards a peak — not of technical per- 
fection, but of some archetypal form of experience. We thus arrive at 
the same conclusion as in our discussion of literature: a work of art 
is always transparent to some dim outline of ultimate experience — 
even if it is no more than the indirect reflection of a reflection, the 
echo of an echo. Those among the great painters who had a taste for 
verbal theorizing, and the articulateness of translating their vision into 
words, almost invariably evoked absolutes and ultimates — the tragedy, 
or glory of man's condition, the wrath or mercy of divinity, the uni- 
versal laws of form and colour harmony, the norms of beauty hidden 
in the mysteries of the golden section or anchored in Euclid's anxioms. 
Everything has two aspects,' wrote Chirico, 'the current aspect, 
which we see nearly always and which ordinary men see, and the 
ghostly and metaphysical aspect, which only rare individuals may see 
in moments of clairvoyance and metaphysical abstraction. A work of 
art must narrate something that does not appear within its outline/ 

Regardless of the site we choose for our excavation, we shall always 
hit at the same ancient underground river which feeds the springs of 
all art and discovery. 

Summary 

The aesthetic experience aroused by a work of art is derived from a 
series of bisociative processes which happen virtually at once and 
cannot be rendered in verbal language without suffering impoverish- 
ment and distortion. At the base of the series we once more find 
illusion. But 'life-likeness* is a matter of interpretation, dependent on 
the limitations of the medium and the prejudices of vision. Perception 



392 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



is loaded with unconscious inferences, from the visual constancies, 
through spatial projection, empathy, and synesthesia, to the projection 
of meaning into the Rohrschach blot, and the assigning of purpose and 
function to the human shape. The artist exploits these unconscious 
processes by the added twists of perspective, rhythm and balance, con- 
trast, 'tactile values', etc. The conventions of a period or school lend 
coherence to its vision, but also tend to crystallize — as in all domains 
of science and art— into fixed 'rules of the game': into formulae, 
stereotypes, visual cliches; these may be so firmly established that the 
artist becomes snowblind to aspects of reality which do not fit into 
them. The originality of genius, here as elsewhere, consists in shifts of 
attention to aspects previously ignored; in seeing appearances in a new 
light; in discovering new relations and correspondences between 
motif and medium. 

Tastes and distastes on the sensory level play, like consonances and 
dissonances, only a subordinate role in the aesthetic experience, as one 
among many patterns of unity-in-variety. The pre-condition of the 
experience to occur is once more that the emotive potentials of the 
matrices participating in it should form an ascending gradient, and 
provide a hint, however tentative or teasing, of some hidden reality in 
the play of forms and colours. 



XXIII 

ART AND PROGRESS 



In the discussion which followed a lecture at an American univer- 
sity on the subject of this book, one of the 'resident painters* 
remarked angrily: 

'I do not "bisociate". I sit down, look at the model, and paint it/ 
In a sense he was right. He had found his 'style', his visual vocabulary, 
some years earlier and was quite content to use it, with suitable varia- 
tions, to express everything he had to say. The two planes of motif and 
medium had become firmly welded together at a fixed angle, and the 
original bisociative act had become stabilized into a skilled routine — 
highly flexible, but governed by a fixed code. It would be very foolish 
to underestimate the achievements of which skilled routine is capable. 
By working tirelessly to improve his technique, the pupil or imitator 
may — as the history of doubtful attributions and outright forgeries 
proves — equal and sometimes surpass the master in technical perfection. 
But technical virtuosity is one thing, creative originality another. 



Cumulative Periods 

Original discoveries are as rare in art as in science. They consist in 
finding new ways of bisociating motif and medium. Art historians who 
lived in periods of rapid transition, considered 'progress* in terms of 
discoveries of new techniques: Pliny called each innovator a heuretes — 
a 'finder' entitled to utter Archimedes' triumphant shout. The inno- 
vations which he and Qumtilian listed as quasi-scientific discoveries 
were feats such as rendering difficult, contorted motions; making the 
first statue with an open mouth; showing the course of the veins; 
paying attention to light and shadow. They regarded each discovery 

393 



394 THE ACT OF CREATION 

as a landmark on the road towards the mastery of reality; and during 
the second great awakening, the Renaissance, Vasari, Leonardo, and 
Durer took a similar attitude. Vasari described the triumphant ad- 
vance of painting from Giotto to the sixteenth-century masters in 
terms almost comparable to a history of sea-farers, where each of the 
great captains puts a new continent on the map. Leonardo thought in 
all seriousness that it was a wretched pupil who did not surpass his 
master; and if we recall that less than two centuries, or six generations, 
separate Giotto and Duccio on the one hand, from Raphael and Titian 
on the other, we can appreciate his point of view. Greek sculpture, 
from Polymedes of Argos to Praxiteles (also a span of about six 
generations), and Italian art from the early fourteenth to the early 
sixteenth century, advanced indeed in a cumulative way — each genius 
'stood on the shoulders of giants' and could look a little further than 
his predecessors. 

But here a dangerous misunderstanding might arise. 'Cumulative 
progress' means in this context merely that each painter could make 
use of the discoveries of his predecessors without having to make them 
again. Foreshortening, perspective, anatomy, a whole series of steps 
in the rendering of light and colour, of textures, movements, expres- 
sions; these and many other innovations in the treatment of the 
medium and the perception of reality, once made, could be easily 
absorbed by pupils and imitators. When Leonardo spoke of the 
pupil's duty to 'surpass* his master, he meant only this— that the pupil 
was free to incorporate at his ease the discoveries of his elders into his 
repertory and to look for new pastures. But neither he nor Vasari 
meant that those who came later were better painters in an absolute 
sense than those on whose shoulders they stood. Moreover, Leonardo 
knew that the pupil was free not only to accept, but also to reject 
the discoveries of his elders. The deliberate distortions and asymmetries 
in the face of Mona Lisa, and the equally deliberate ambiguities of 
contour in the corners of mouth and eyes, are deviations from the 
canon; but they were based on a knowing rejection of certain aspects 
of 'scientific realism* in painting— not on naive ignorance. In this 
sense the achievements of art are indeed cumulative and irreversible, 
as those of science are. The artist can decide to go against them, but 
he cannot ignore them. 

'Florentine pafoting', wrote Eric Newton, 1 'starts, like a sprint, 
with a pistol shot, hi 1280 it hardly exists. By 1300 it is racing ahead.' 
Quite a number of modern art-historians share, with Pliny and 



ART AND PROGRESS 



395 



Vasari, a belief in the cumulative progress of art* Ruskin and Roger Fry 
thought the history of painting from ancient days was a progressive 
shedding of prejudices and the recovery of our lost 'innocence of the 
eye'. 'It has taken from Neolithic times till the nineteenth century to 
perfect this discovery,' wrote Fry, 'European art from the time of 
Giotto progressed more or less continuously in this direction, in 
which the discovery of linear perspective marks an important stage, 
whilst the full exploration of atmospheric colour and colour perspec- 
tive had to await the work of the French impresaonists/ 2 Eric Newton 
sees the development of European art 'as a great river system in which 
many tributaries are gradually drawn together'; 8 and his diagram of the 
outstanding artists and trends from 1300 to 1940 is a map of branches 
and confluences representing 'the cycle of realism that had begun with 
Giotto and ended with Cezanne'. Lastly Gombrich, though puzzled 
by the representational skill of the prehistoric cave-painters, agrees that 
'all representations can be somehow arranged along a scale which 
extends from the schematic to the impressionist'. 



Stagnation and Cross-Fertilization 

On the other hand, it is easy to match, in the history of every culture 
or country, the relatively brief periods of rapid cumulative advances 
with much longer periods of stagnation, onesidedness, mannerism and 
estrangement from reality. The parallel between the dizzy zig-zag 
curves in the development of the sciences and arts is obvious; and so 
is the kinship between the defenders of scientific and of artistic ortho- 
doxy — the phalanxes of inertia. 'The more we become aware of the 
enormous pull in man to repeat what he has learned, the greater will 
be our admiration for these exceptional beings who could break this 
spell and make a significant advance on which others could build.'* 

Because visual discoveries are so difficult to verbalize, we have 
hardly any introspective records of the painter's 'moment of truth* 
which could be compared to the accounts left by scientists; we do not 
know how the games of the underground enter into the picture. But 
if we consider the history of art as a whole — in its aspect of a collective 
enterprise, as Vasari saw it— we shall find that the great innovators all 
stand at draughty corners of world-history, where air-currents from 
different ailture-climates meet, mix, and integrate. The Greek awaken- 
ing in the sixth century B.C. probably started under the impact of the 



39<S 



THB ACT OF CREATION 



seemingly incompatible Egyptian, Oriental, and Cretan art forms on 
the tribes of northern origin— when they became sufficiently settled to 
take an interest in these matters. Later Alexander reversed the process: 
in the wake of his conquests, Hellenistic art invaded Egypt, the Middle 
East, and India; even the Buddha was made to put on a Greek smile. 
Gothic art originates in the p?rticularly draughty climate of the 
migrations and incursions from the north, and led to the integration of 
pagan and Roman-Christian traditions. Another great synthesis, of the 
Byzantine and the Gothic, started the chain-reaction in Sienna and 
Florence; the rediscovery of Greek statuary gave it a further boost. 
Brunelleschi married the Gothic invention of vaults carried by pillars 
and ribs with the columns and pillasters of classic Roman architecture 
— and created that wonderful hybrid, the Renaissance style. And so it 
goes on — to Chinese Chippendale, the impact of Japanese colour- 
prints on Manet and Degas, and of primitive African sculpture on the 
moderns. Equally important were cross-influences from not directly 
related fields: the discovery of the laws of perspective, and the re- 
discovery of Apollonius' work on conic sections; the revival of anatomy 
(Leonardo himself dissected more than thirty corpses); the invention 
of oil-paint, of the woodcut, of lithography, and photography; the 
evolution of colour-theory in physics. 

To sum up: it seems to be undeniably true, as Pliny was the first to 
suggest, that art evolves, like science, in a cumulative manner — but only 
for a while, and within limits, until all that can be done has been done 
along that particular line; at the great turning points, however, which 
initiate a new departure along a new line, we find bisociations in the 
grand style — cross-fertilization between different periods, cultures, and 
provinces of knowledge. 

Statement and Implication 

I have compared (p. 72 f.) the cartoonist's technique of reducing a face 
to its bare essentials, to the scientist's technique of representing a 
process by a diagram, schema, map, or model. In the third panel of our 
tryptich, the artist applies similar techniques. He too is engaged in 
making models of phenomena in his particular medium, using a par- 
ticular set of formulae, and concentrating on those aspects of reality, to 
the detriment of others, which are significant to him, or to the fashions 
and conventions of his time. (Let me repeat, though, that the reality 
which he represents need not be a tangible object in three-dimensional 



ART AND PROGRESS 



397 



space any more than the elusive 'objects* represented in the physicist's 
equations.) Thus unavoidably, artist, scientist, and caricaturist alike 
must use the techniques of selective emphasis, exaggeration, and simpli- 
fication, to underline those aspects or features which seem relevant 
to them. 

They must also observe the rules of economy. As the laws of physics 
become more universal in character, the symbols which represent them 
become more elusive and implicit. In the history of art we can trace 
the effects of the 'law of infolding' in every period. On Egyptian tomb- 
paintings, each part of the body is still shown explicitly, in its most 
characteristic aspect; but the young girl picking flowers on a famous 
wall-painting in Stabiae impertinently turns her back on us. What we 
see of her face is only the merest hint of a profile, leaving it to us to 
extrapolate her lovely features. The deliberate return of Byzantine 
art to pre-HeUenistic rigidity and 'naivety', expressed a rejection of 
worldly realism in favour of a more implicit manner of conveying its 
message. Much the same could be said of the deliberate simplicity and 
discreet, almost apologetic, use of perspective by Fra Angelico; and of 
all the later, unceasing attempts by artists to escape saturation, evade 
the obvious, and appeal to the beholder's imagination. It was Leonardo 
who invented sfumato — the smoke-screen of ambiguous shadows, the 
blurred contours at the corners of Mona Lisa's eyes, which kept people 
guessing through four centuries; and it was Titian who in his later 
years invented the technique of the bold and 'rough* brushstroke, those 
'crudely daubed strokes and blobs' — as Vasari admiringly described 
them — which, looked at from close quarters, make no sense at all. A 
similar progression from the neat and meticulous to the loose and 
evocative brush can be seen in Rembrandt's rendering of textiles and 
embroideries: the law of infolding asserts itself both in the evolution 
of individual artists and in the historic development of any particular 
form of art. A striking example of the latter are the two views of the 
same Venetian motif (the Campo San Zanipolo) by Canaletto in 1740, 
and by Guardi in 1782 — the first neat and explicit like a photograph, 
the second suggestive, impressionistic, and 'modern'. 

One can hardly accuse Reynolds of exaggerated modernism; some 
of his nice little girls hugging their nice little doggies have precisely 
that sweet-and-sticky quality which, by its over-explicit attack on the 
emotions, defeats its own purpose. But as he was an accomplished 
master of his craft, he was capable of seeing the reverse of the medal; 
and in his 'Discourse' commemorating the work of Gainsborough, 



398 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



there is a surprising passage: *I have often imagined that this un- 
finished manner contributed even to that striking resemblance for 
which his portraits are so remarkable. Though this opinion may be 
considered as fanciful, yet I think a plausible reason may be given, why 
such a mode of painting should have such an effect. It is presupposed 
that in this undetermined manner there is the general effect; enough 
to remind the spectator of the original; the imagination supplies the 
rest, and perhaps more satisfactorily to himself, if not more exacdy, 
than the artist, with all his care, could possibly have done/ 

From the middle of the nineteenth century onwards, the trend to- 
wards me implicit, the oblique hint, the statement disguised as a riddle 
kept gathering speed and momentum — so much so that it sometimes 
gave the impression of art not merely 'folding in but folding up. In im- 
pressionist painting, Gombrich remarked, 'the direction of the brush- 
stroke is no longer an aid to the reading of forms. It is without any 
support from structure that the beholder must mobilize his memory of 
the visible world and project it into the mosaic of strokes and dabs on 
the canvas before him. The image, it might be said, has no firm anchor- 
age left on the canvas — it is only "conjured up* in our minds"/ 5 From 
here it was only a step to cutting the anchor and doing away with 
illusion as something altogether too obvious. Picasso's women shown 
part en face and part in profile, sometimes with a third eye or limbs 
shuffled around, rely on the beholders knowledge of the female form 
and on his willingness to participate in the master's experiments with 
it; like Leonardo's experiments with his chimeras, they are a challenge 
and an invitation to explore the possible worlds implied in the visible 
world. At the opposite extreme of the scale we find the meticulous 
realism of a series of great portrait painters — from Holbein to, say, 
Fantiii Latour. From a purely optical point of view they seem to be 
completely explicit statements; and yet they contain a mystery in 
another dimension — the mystery of character and personality summed 
up in a single expression, breathing through the pigment of the canvas. 
A photograph can convey the truth of a moment; a portrait can inti- 
mate the truth of a whole life. 

Thus there exist various dimensions of infolding — various direc- 
tions in which the beholder must exert his imagination and complete 
the hint. One is reflected in the development which started with the 
veiled sfumato and the loose, evocative brush— with Eastlake's judicious 
unfinish of the consummate workman' — and ends, for the time being, 
with the baffling challenges offered by contemporary art. Another is 



ART AND PROGRESS 



399 



the avoidance of any too overt appeal to the emotions — whether in a 
human face or in a Neopolitan sunset. The less there is left to divine, 
the quicker the process of saturation sets in, which rejects any further 
oifer of the mixture as before as sentimental, melodramatic, porno- 
graphic, or just slushy kitsch. Rembrandt's famous warning to the 
spectator to keep his distance — 'don't poke your nose into my pictures, 
the smell of paint will poison you — could be reversed: 'don't turn your 
canvas into flypaper to catch my emotions, I can't bear the feel of it/ 
Even patterns of unity-in-diversity, for all their archetypal echoes, 
become boring if they are too obvious — as rhythm becomes monotonous 
unless its pulsation is perceived beneath the surface only of a complex 
musical or metric pattern. 

The Japanese have a word for it: shibuyu The colour-scheme of a 
kimono so discreet, subdued, and apparently dull that there seems to be 
no scheme at all, is shibuyi. A statue whose grace is hidden by a rough, 
unpolished, seemingly unfinished surface, is shibuyu So is the delicious 
taste of raw fish, once the acrid tang which hides it is overcome. The 
Chinese, however, discovered the law of infolding much earlier on. A 
seventeenth-century manual of painting advocates the technique of 
'leaving out', illustrated by drawings-of the familiar kind where the 
simple outline of a face, minus features, serves as a surprisingly ex- 
pressive formula: 'Figures, even though painted without eyes, must 
seem to look; without ears, must seem to listen. There are things which 
ten hundred brushstrokes cannot depict but which can be captured by 
a few simple strokes if they are right. That is truly giving expression 
to the invisible.'* 

But economy of means and avoidance of the obvious should not be 
misinterpreted as lack of spontaneity or a tendency towards modera- 
tion. Sesshu, perhaps the greatest of Japanese painters (a contemporary 
of Leonardo's), was a master of the leaving-out technique; yet he used 
not only his brush, but fistfuls of straw dipped in ink to impart to his 
landscapes their powerful and violent sense of motion. Goya's 'Disasters' 
combine a maximum of economy with a maximum of horror. On 
the other hand, Royal Academy portraits in the approved tradition 
display all the virtues of moderation, yet in their pedestrian ^^licit* 
ness 'deprive the mind*, to quote Mallarme once more, 'of that 
delicious joy of imagining that it creates*. 

The artist's aim, we saw at the beginning of this book, is to turn his 
audience into his accomplices. Complicity does not exclude violence — 
but it must be based on a shared secret. 



XXIV 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 

The Aesthetics of Snobbery 1 

In 1948, a German art restorer named Dietrich Fey, engaged in 
reconstruction work on Lubeck's ancient St. Marien Church, 
stated that his workmen had discovered traces of Gothic wall- 
paintings dating back to the thirteenth century, under a coating of 
chalk on the church walls. The restoration of the paintings was en- 
trusted to Fey V assistant, Lothar Malskat, who finished the job two 
years later. In 1950 Chancellor Adenauer presided over the ceremonies 
marking the completion of the restoration work, in the presence of 
art experts from all parts of Europe. Their unanimous opinion, voiced 
by Chancellor Adenauer, was that the twenty-one thirteenth-century 
Gothic saints on the church walls were 'a valuable treasure and a 
fabulous discovery of lost masterpieces'. 

None of the experts on that or any later occasion expressed doubt as 
to the authenticity of the frescoes. It was Herr Malskat himself who, 
two years later, disclosed the fraud. He presented himself on his own 
initiative at Liibeck police headquarters, where he stated that the 
frescoes were entirely his own work undertaken by order of his boss, 
Herr Fey; and he asked to be tried for forgery. The leading German 
art experts, however, stuck to their opinion; the frescoes, they said, 
were without doubt genuine, and Herr Malskat was merely seeking 
cheap publicity. An official Board of Investigation was appointed, 
and came to the conclusion that the restoration of the wall-paintings 
was a hoax— but only after Herr Malskat had confessed that he had 
also manufactured hundreds of Rembrandts, Watteaus, Toulouse- 
Lautrecs, Picassos, Henri Rousseaus, Corots, Chagalls, Vlamincks, 
and other masters, and sold them as originals — some of which were 
actually found by the police in Herr Fey's house. Without this corpus 
delicti, it is doubtful whether the German experts would ever have 
admitted having been fooled. 

400 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 



401 



My point is not the fallibility of the experts. Herr Malskat's exploit 
is merely one of a number of similarly successful hoaxes and forgeries 
— of which the most fabulous were probably van Megeeren's faked 
Vermeers. The disturbing question which they raise is whether the 
Liibeck saints are less beautiful, and have ceased to be 'a valuable 
treasure of masterpieces', simply because they had been painted by 
Herr Malskat and not by somebody else? And furthermore, if van 
Megeeren can paint Vermeers as good as Vermeer himself, why 
should they be taken off the walls of the Dutch and other National 
Galleries? If even the experts were unable to detect the difference, then 
surely the false Vermeers must procure as much aesthetic pleasure to 
the common run of Museum visitors as the authentic ones. All the 
curators would have to do is to change the name on the catalogue 
from Vermeer to van Megeeren. 

There are several answers to this line of argument, but before going 
into them I want to continue in the part of the devil's advocate by 
considering an example of a forgery in a different field: Macpherson's 
Ossian. The case is so notorious that the facts need only be briefly 
mentioned. James Macpherson (173 6-1796), a Scottish poet and 
adventurer, alleged that in the course of his wanderings in the High- 
lands he had discovered some ancient Gaelic manuscripts. Enthusiastic 
Scottish litterateurs put up a subscription to enable Macpherson to 
pursue his researches, and in 1761 he published Fingal, an ancient Epic 
Poem in Six Books, together with several other poems composed by Ossian, 
the Son of FingaL Ossian is the legendary third-century hero and bard 
of Celtic literature. Fingal was soon followed by the publication of a 
still larger Ossianic epic called Temora, and this by a collected edition, 
The Works of Ossian, The authenticity of Macpherson s text was at 
once questioned in England, particularly by Dr. Johnson (whom 
Macpherson answered by sending him a challenge to a duel), and to 
his death Macpherson refused, under various unconvincing pretexts, 
to publish his alleged Gaelic originals. By the turn of the century the 
controversy was setded; it was established that while Macpherson had 
used fragments of ancient Celtic lore, most of the 'Ossianic texts' 
were of his own making. 

Yet here again the question arises whether the poetic quality of the 
work itself is altered by the fact that it was written not by Ossian the 
son of Fingal, but by James Macpherson? The Ossianic* texts were 
translated into many languages, and had a considerable influence on 
the literature and cultural climate of Europe in the late eighteenth and 



402 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



early nineteenth centuries. This is how the Encyclopedia Britannica sums 
up its evaluation of Macpherson (rny italics): 

The varied sources of his work and its worthlessness as a transcript 
of actual Celtic poems do not alter the fact that he produced a work 
of art which . . . did more than any single work to bring about the romantic 
movement in European, and especially in German, literature . . . Herder 
and Goethe . . . were among its profound admirers. 

These examples could be continued indefinitely. Antique furniture, 
Greek tanagra figures, Gothic madonnas, old and modern masters 
are being forged, copied, counterfeited all the time, and the value we 
set on the object is not determined by aesthetic appreciation and 
pleasure to the eye, but by the precarious and fallible judgement of 
experts. And it will always be fallible for the good and simple reason 
that genius consists not in the perfect exercise of a technique, but in its 
invention; once the technique is established, diligent pupils and 
imitators can produce works in the masters idiom which are often indis- 
tinguishable, and sometimes technically more accomplished than his. 

Some years ago, at a fancy-dress ball — in Monte Carlo, I believe — 
a competition was held to decide which among the dozen or so guests 
masquerading as Charlie Chaplin came nearest to the original. Chaplin 
himself happened to be among them— and got only the third prize. 
In 1962, the Fogg museum of Harvard arranged a private exhibition 
for connoisseurs, where some of the exhibits were fakes, others genuine; 
the guests were to decide which was which. Included were, among 
other items, an original portrait by Annibale Carracci, one of the most 
influential painters of the Italian baroque, and a contemporary copy 
thereof; also an original Picasso drawing of a Mother and Child, and 
two forgeries thereof. The result was similar to that of the Chaplin 
competition; among those who plumped for one of the forgeries were 
the chairman of Princetons Art Department and the Secretary of 
the Fogg; the director of the Metropolitan Museum refused to submit 
to the test, while other experts 'scored themselves on sheets of paper, 
compared their verdicts with the officially announced facts, and quietly 
crumpled their papers'. 2 

Let me repeat; the principal mark of genius is not perfection, but 
originality, the opening of new frontiers; once this is done, the con- 
quered territory becomes common property. The fact that even pro- 
fessional experts are unable to point out the difference in artistic 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 



403 



merit between the true and the false Picasso, Caracci, or Vermeer, is 
conclusive proof that no such difference can be registered by the lay- 
man's eye. Are we, then, all snobs to whom a signature, an expert 
testimony based on X-ray photography, or the postmark of a period 
is more important than the intrinsic beauty of the object itself? And 
what about the contested works of Shakespeare and Johann Sebastian 
Bach? Are their dramatic and poetic and harmonic qualities dependent 
on the technical controversies between specialists? 

The answer, I believe, can be summed up in a single sentence: our 
appraisal of a work of art or literature is hardly ever a unitary act, 
and mosdy the result of two or more independent and simultaneous 
processes which interfere with and tend to distort each other. Let me 
illustrate this by a story which I have told elsewhere at greater length.* 

A friend of mine, whom I shall call Catherine, was given as a present 
by an unobtrusive admirer a drawing from Picasso's classical period; 
she took it to be a reproduction and hung it in her staircase. On my 
next visit to her house, it was hanging over the mantelpiece in the 
drawing-room: the supposed reproduction had turned out to be an 
original. But as it was a line-drawing in ink, black contour on white 
paper, it needed an expert, or at least a good magnifying lens, to show 
that it was the original and not a lithograph or reproduction. Neither 
Catherine, nor any of her friends, could tell the difference. Yet her 
appreciation of it had completely changed, as the promotion from 
staircase to drawing-room showed. I asked her to explain the reason 
for her change of attitude to the thing on the wall which in itself had 
not changed at all; she answered, surprised at my stupidity, that of 
course the thing had not changed, but that she saw it differently since 
she knew that it was done by Picasso himself and 'not just a repro- 
duction . I then asked what considerations determined her attitude to 
pictures in general, and she replied with equal sincerity that they were, 
of course, considerations of aesthetic quality — 'composition, colour, 
harmony, power, what have you. She honesdy believed to be guided 
by purely aesthetic value-judgements based on those qualities; but if 
that was the case, since the qualities of the picture had not changed, how 
could her attitude to it have changed? 

I was labouring a seemingly obvious point, yet she was unable to 
see that she was contradicting herself. It proved quite useless repeating 
to her that the origin and rarity-value of the object did not alter its 
qualities — and, accordingly, should not have altered her appreciation 
of it, if it had really been based on purely aesthetic criteria as she 



404 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



believed it to be. In reality, of course, her attitude was determined not 
by those criteria, but by an accidental bit of information—which 
might be right or wrong, and was entirely extraneous to the question 
of aesthetic value. Yet she was by no means stupid; in fact there is 
something of her confusion in all of us. We all tend to believe that 
our attitude to an object of art is determined by aesthetic considerations 
alone, whereas it is decisively influenced by factors of a quite different 
order. "We are unable to see a work of art isolated from the context 
of its origin or history; and if Catherine were to learn that her Picasso 
was after all a reproduction, her attitude would again change accord- 
ing to the changed context. Moreover, most people get quite indignant 
when one suggests to them that the origin of a picture has nothing to' 
do with its aesthetic value as such. For, in our minds, the question of 
period, authorship, and authenticity, though in itself extraneous to 
aesthetic value, is so intimately mixed up with it, that we find it well- 
nigh impossible to unscramble them. The phenomenon of snobbery, 
in all its crude and subtle variants, can always be traced back to some 
confusion of this type. 

Thus Catherine would not be a snob if she had said: 'A reproduction 
of this line-drawing is to all practical purposes indistinguishable from 
the original, and therefore just as beautiful as the original. Nevertheless, 
one gives me a greater thrill than the other, for reasons which have 
nothing to do with beauty/ But alas, she is incapable of disentangling 
the two different elements which determine her reactions, and to a 
greater or lesser extent we are all victims of the same confusion. The 
change in our attitude, and in the art dealer's price, when it is discovered 
that a cracked and blackened piece of landscape displaying three sheep 
and a windmill, bears the signature of Broeckendael the Elder, has 
nothing to do with beauty, aesthetics, or what have you. And yet, 
God help us, the sheep and the mill and the brook do suddenly look 
different and more attractive — even to the hard-boiled dealer. What 
Happened was that a bit of incidental information cast a ray of golden 
sunlight on those miserable sheep; a ray emitted not by the pigment 
but by the cerebral cortex of the art-snob. 



The Personal Emanation 



Let me now present the case for the defence. The appraisal of a work 
of art is generally the result of two or more independent processes 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 



405 



which interact with each other. One complex process constitutes the 
aesthetic experience as such, which has been discussed in previous chap- 
ters; it implies a system of values, and certain criteria of excellence, on 
which we believe our judgement to be based. But other processes 
interfere with it, with their different systems of values, and distort our 
judgements. I shall mention two types of such interfering systems. 

The first is summed up in the statement of a little girl of twelve, 
the daughter of a friend, who was taken to the Greenwich Museum, 
and when asked to name the most beautiful thing she had seen there, 
declared without hesitation: 'Nelson's shirt.' "When asked what was 
so beautiful about it, she explained: 'That shirt with blood on it was 
j oily nice. Fancy real blood on a real shirt which belonged to somebody 
really historic.' 

Her sense of values, unlike Catherine's, was still unspoilt. The 
emotion that she had experienced was derived from the Same kind of 
magic that emanates from Napoleon's inkpot, the relic of the saint 
carried in the annual procession, the rope by which a famous 
murderer was hanged, the galley-proof corrected by Tolstoy's hand. 
Our forbears believed that an object which had been in the possession 
of a person became imbued with his emanations, and in turn emanated 
something of his substance. 'There is, I am sure,' a columnist wrote in 
the Daily Express, 'for most of us a special pleasure in sinking your 
teeth into a peach produced on the estate of an Earl who is related to 
the Royal Family.' 4 You might even come to feel that you are a 
member of the family if you persist long enough in this somewhat 
indirect method of transubstantiation. 

We can no more escape the pull of magic inside us than the pull of 
gravity. Its manifestations may take a more or less dignified form; but 
the value we set on the peach from the Earl's estate or the splinter from 
the saint's bone, on Dickens's quill or Galileo's telescope, is derived 
from the same source of sympathetic magic. It is, as the little girl said, 
jolly nice to behold a fragment of a marble by Praxiteles — although it 
has been battered out of human shape, with a leper's nose and broken 
ears. The contact with the master's hand has imbued it with a kind 
of effluvium which has lingered on, and emanates the same thrill 
as the real blood on Nelson's shirt — or the real ink from Picasso's 
pen. 

The inordinate importance that we attribute to the original and 
authenticated, even in those borderline cases where only the expert 
can decide on questions of authenticity, has its unconscious roots in 



406 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



this particular kind of fetish-worship. Hence its compelling power — 
who would not cherish a lock from an Egyptian mummy's head? Yet, 
as every honest art dealer will admit, borderline cases are so frequent 
as to be almost the rule. I am no longer referring to forgeries, but to 
the classical practice of the master letting his pupils, apprenticed to his 
workshop, assist in the execution of larger undertakings; and 'assis- 
tance* could mean anything from the filling in of background and 
minor details, to the painting of a whole picture after the master's 
sketch. We are made to realize how common this practice was by 
the emphasis which Michelangelo's admiring contemporaries put on 
the fact that he painted the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel 'alone and 
unaided'. If we remember that even the experts were at a loss to tell the 
Caracci portrait from its contemporary copy—probably by a pupil 
— we must conclude that for the great majority of mortals, including 
connoisseurs, the difference between an authenticated masterpiece, a 
doubtful attribution, and a work 'from the school of, is in most cases 
not discernible. But the fact remains that an 'attribution', perfect in 
its genre but not authenticated, is held in lower esteem than a work of 
lesser perfection, guaranteed to have come from the ageing master's 
hand. It is not the eye that guides the museum visitor, but the magic of 
names. The English nation forked out a million pounds to prevent the 
sale to America of a Leonardo sketch to which it had never paid any 
attention; and the hundreds of thousands of good citizens who queued 
to see it could not have told it from a page in an art-student's sketch- 
book; they went to see Nelson s shirt. 



The Antiquarian Fallacy 

The second 'interfering system' is period consciousness. A Byzantine 
icon, or a Pompeian fresco is not enjoyed at its face value, but by a part- 
conscious attunement of the mind to the values and techniques of the 
time. Even in paintings from periods whose idiom is much closer to 
ours — a Holbein portrait, for instance—such externals as costume and 
headdress drive it mercilessly home to us that the man with the un- 
forgettable, timeless face belonged to the court of Henry VHL The 
archetypal quality is there, but period-consciousness intrudes; and the 
danger is that it may dominate the field. 

Thus we look at an old picture through a double frame: the solid 
gilt frame which isolates it from its surroundings and creates for it a 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 



407 



hole in space; and the period-frame in our minds which creates for it 
a hole in time, and assigns its place on the stage of history. Each time 
we think we are making a purely aesthetic judgement according to our 
lights, the stage-lights interfere. "When we contemplate the Gothic 
wall-paintings on the church in Liibeck for the first time, believing 
them to be authentic, and then -a second time, knowing that they were 
made by Herr Malskat, our experience will indeed be completely 
changed, although the frescoes are the same as at the time when they 
were hailed as masterpieces. The period-frame has been changed, and 
with it the stage-lights. 

Apart from being unavoidable, this relativism of aesthetic judgement 
has its positive sides: by entering into the spirit and climate of the 
period, we automatically make allowances for its crudities of tech- 
nique, for its conventions and "blind spots; we bend over the past with 
a tender antiquarian stoop. But this gesture degenerates into anti- 
quarian snobbery at the point where the period-frame becomes more 
important than the picture, and perverts our scale of values. The 
symptoms are all too familiar: ^discriminate reverence for any- 
thing classified as Italian Primitive or Austrian Baroque (including its 
mass-produced puffy, chubby, winged little horrors); collective shifts 
of period-consciousness (from anti-Victorian to pro-Victorian in 
recent years); the inanities of fashion (Fra Angelico is 'in', Botticelli is 
out'). 

The Comforts of Sterility 

The mechanism responsible for these perversions is the same as dis- 
cussed previously, and provides us with a handy definition: snobbery 
is the result of a mix-up between two frames of reference, A and B t with 
different standards of value; and the consequent misapplication of standard A 
to value-judgements referring to B. The art-snob's pleasures are derived 
not from the picture, but from the catalogue; and the social snob's 
choice of company is not guided by human value, but by rank or 
celebrity value catalogued in the pages of Who's Who. The confusion 
may even affect his biological drives — his taste and smell preferences, 
his sexual inclinations. A hundred years ago, when oysters were the 
diet of the poor, the snob's taste-buds functioned in a different manner. 
In the days before Hitler there was a young woman in Berlin who 
worked for a publisher and was well known in the literary world for 
a certain peculiarity: she had carried on a number of affairs with 



408 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



authors, regardless of age or sex— but only with those whose 
books had sold more than 20,000 copies. Her own explanation was 
that with less successful authors she was unable to obtain physical 
satisfaction. 

It is a depressing anecdote because it has a ring of clinical authen- 
ticity; at the same time it displays the familiar pattern of the comic: 
the clash of two incompatible contexts. But to the poor heroine of the 
story it was no joke, because she could not see their incompatibility; 
the Kama Sutra and the best-seller list were hopelessly mixed up in 
her mind. The reader may have wondered why I have devoted a 
whole chapter of this book on human creativity to the seemingly 
trivial subject of snobbery. The answer is in the question: snobbery 
is, I believe, by no means a trivial phenomenon, but a confusion of 
values which, in various forms, permeates all strata of civilized 
societies, present and past (see, for instance, Petronius's Banquet of 
Trimalchio); and it is in many respects a negation of the principle 
of creativity. 

We have seen how laughter is sparked off by the collision of 
matrices; discovery, by their integration; aesthetic experience by their 
fuxtaposition. Snobbery follows neither of these patterns; it is a 
hotchpotch of matrices, the application of the rules of one game to 
another game. It uses a clock to measure weight, and a thermometer 
to measure distance. The creative mind perceives things in a new 
light, the snob in a borrowed light; his pursuits are sterile, and his 
satisfactions of a vicarious nature. He does not aim at power; he merely 
wants to rub shoulders with those who wield power, and bask in their 
reflected glory. He would rather be a tolerated hanger-on of an envied 
set than a popular member of one to which by nature he belongs. 
What he admires in public would bore him when alone, but he is 
unaware of it. When he reads Kirkegaard, he is not moved by what 
he reads, he is moved by himself reading Kirkegaard— but he is 
blissfully unaware of it. His emotions do not derive from the object, 
but from extraneous sources associated with it; his satisfactions are 
pseudo-satisfactions, his triumphs self-delusions. He has never travelled 
in the belly of the whale; he has opted for the comforts of sterility 
against the pangs of creativity. 

One cannot discuss the act of creation without devoting at least a 
few pages to the act of desecration. Snobbery is a poor word with too 
specifically modern connotations for that benightedness, due to the 
confusion of values, which is one of the leitmotifs of the history of 



CONFUSION AND STERILITY 



409 



man; he always seems to be groping his way through a labyrinthine 
world, armed with a compass which always points in the wrong 
direction. The symbol of creativity is the magic wand which Moses 
used to make water come out of the rock; its reverse is the faulty 
yardstick which turns everything it touches into dust. 



BOOK TWO 
HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



INTRODUCTION 



So far I have discussed creativity in science and art, that is to say, 
the highest forms of mental activity, with only occasional 
references to the humbler routines of existence. I started at the 
roof, as it were — what remains to be done is to build up the walls which 
support it. 

The main purpose of this somewhat perverse procedure was to deal 
first with those subjects which are of primary interest to the general 
reader and to establish a wider theoretical framework afterwards. But 
there exist additional considerations to justify this reversal of order. 
At the Hixon Symposium in 1948 K. S. Lashley quoted with approval 
a French author writing in 1887. 'The study of comparative grammar/ 
Lashley said, 'is not the most direct approach to the physiology of the 
cerebral cortex, yet Fournie has written, "Speech is the only window 
through which the physiologist can view the cerebral life." The word 
'only* is, of course, an unwarranted exaggeration, but perhaps no more 
unwarranted than the opposite claim, that the 'only' legitimate window 
is that through which we watch the workings of the salivary reflex in 
dogs or the behaviour of rats in mazes. To repeat an argument from 
the Preface to Book One: in the history of most sciences we find 
alternations between the downward approach from roof to basement, 
from the complex to the elementary, and the upward approach from 
the elementary to the complex; until the two finally merge. It was the 
study of complex electro-magnetic phenomena which provided the 
clue to sub-atomic structures. Torn out of the larger context in which 
the 'elementary part' functions, it ceases to be a true elementary part 
— whether we speak of electrons, tissue-cells, or 'elements of behaviour'. 
Genetics started with morphological classifications and comparisons of 
whole organisms long before anything was known about chromo- 
somes, genes, and nucleic acids. The use of undefined, *dirty* concepts 
as black boxes in theory-making has led into many cul-de-sacs in the 
history of science, but was nevertheless indispensable for its progress. 

413 



414 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



In experimental psychology the pendulum oscillated in the course 
of the last century between the upward* and the 'downward' approach: 
from the atomism of the English associationists to the introspec- 
tionism of the Wurzburg school; from the chain-reflex theory of 
Watsonian behaviourism to the Holism of Gestalt, and back again to 
the more sophisticated behaviourism of the forties and fifties. But 
there are signs which indicate that the controversies between 'cog- 
nitive* versus 'stimulus-response' theories of behaviour have become 
sterile, and that a new synthesis is in the making. 

So much by way of justification for the order of the two parts of 
this book. The methodological approach of the second is meant to be 
the reverse of the first. It starts 'from the bottom' with some ele- 
mentary considerations which are non-controversial. Yet gradually, 
I hope, a structure will emerge which makes contact with and lends 
support to the controversial theories of creative activity outlined in 
Book One. 



I 



PRENATAL SKILLS 

Organic life, in all its manifestations, from embryonic develop- 
ment to symbolic thought, is governed by 'rules of the 
game* which lend it coherence, stability, and an appearance 
of purpose (or 'goal-directedness' if you prefer that term). These 
rules or codes, whether phylogenetically or ontogenetically acquired, 
function on all levels of the hierarchy, from the chromosomes to the 
neuron-circuits responsible for verbal thinking. Each code represents 
the fixed, invariant aspect of an adaptable skill or matrix of behaviour. 
I shall take the stylistic licence of using the word 'skill' in a broad 
sense, as a synonym for 'matrix', and shall speak of the morphogenetic 
skills which enable the egg to grow into a hen, of the vegetative 
skills of maintaining homeostasis, of perceptual, locomotive, and 
verbal skills. 

We shall find as a fundamental characteristic of codes on all levels 
that they function on the trigger-release principle, so that a relatively 
simple signal releases pre-set, complex action patterns. The signal may 
be mechanical, as in artificial parthenogenesis induced by a pin-prick; 
chemical (e.g. inducers and evocator substances); or neural (Tin- 
bergen and Lorenz's Internal Releasive Mechanisms). But the pre-set 
action pattern activated by the code is generally an elastic pattern, not 
a rigid automatism (such as suggested, for instance, in Tinbergens 
schema). Skills have varying degrees of flexibility. The restraints im- 
posed by the code do not exhaust the degrees of freedom possessed by 
the matrix; there are usually various alternative choices left to provide 
for a flexible strategy according to the 'lie of the land' — i.e. guided by 
feedback from the environment. Matrices thus function under the 
dual control of an invariant code and a variable environment. These 
two factors jointly determine which members of the matrix should 
enter into action and in what order. 

415 



4X6 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



The members of the matrix are sub-matrices governed by their 
sub-codes. Facing 'upward* and 'inward' in the organismic hierarchy, 
they act as dependent parts; facing 'downward* and 'outward', they 
act as relatively autonomous sub-wholes. On every level of structure 
and function in the living organism we find the same phenomenon of 
Janus-faced entities which behave partly as wholes, yet wholly as 
parts, as it were. The 'irreducible, elementary particle' has turned out 
to be a will-o'-the-wisp, even in inorganic chemistry; in the organism, 
the firing of a single nerve-cell turns out to be not an event, but a 
complex, autonomous pattern of events. 

Structure and Function 

I shall take as my starting point two complementary aspects of the 
evolutionary process: differentiation of structure and integration of 
function. Regardless of what causal theory one adopts to account for 
the evolution of higher forms of life, the means by which progress is 
achieved is the development of more complex and specialized bodily 
structures and of more elaborate ways of co-ordinating their function. 
These are two aspects of a unitary process, not two processes. In fact 
both terms, 'structure* and 'function', are abstractions derived from 
imaginary cross-sections along the spatial or temporal axis of indivisible 
spatio-temporal events. 

Structure is a static concept of a process frozen in the specious 
present. 'Anatomy abstracts from time. It studies the organism con- 
ceived "at an instant".' 1 A kidney, or a single kidney cell, which has 
stopped functioning no longer has the same spatial structure as before; 
and while it is still functioning its structure is changing at every 
moment. All living matter continuously alters its shape and composi- 
tion; it can be said to preserve its identity only if both structure and 
function are taken into consideration. Vice versa, function detached 
from structure is the grin detached from the cat. Physiological pro- 
cesses, unlike mechanical automata, are 'open systems'; Ostwald 
compared them to the flame of a gas-burner. The flame is a relatively 
stable phenomenon; but how is one to distinguish between its structure 
and function, between combustible and combustion? 

Most of the time it is both convenient and necessary for the biolo- 
gist and physician to forget that when he is speaking of 'structure' and 
'function' he is using 'dirty concepts'- — otherwise his work would 



PRENATAL SKILLS 



417 



come to a standstill. However, we shall soon come across problems 
where the tacit implications of both terms will become relevant. 

A second catch is the semantic ambiguity of the wofd 'function. It 
can either mean the role or part which my liver ought to play to keep 
me in good health, or it can refer with heartless matter-of-factness to 
what is in fact happening in my liver, i.e. not to its function in the first 
sense but to its actual 'functioning*. In the first case, the organ is con- 
sidered as part of the organism; in the second case it is treated, prima 
facie, as an independent whole. Whenever a distinction is indicated, I 
shall use the word 'function in the first sense, and 'functioning' iri the 
second. 

The complementary aspects of structural differentiation and func- 
tional integration are reflected at every step in the process of mor- 
phogenesis. 

The giant molecules of DNA (dioxyribonucleic acid) in the chromo- 
somes of the fertilized egg are said to represent the blue-print of the 
future organism. Let us consider for a moment this first code which 
we meet at the base of the hierarchy. It is a 'code' in the twofold 
meaning in which I have used that term: a canon of rules for making 
an organism, represented in a 'coded', compressed language. The way 
in which the coding is done deserves some attention. Each DNA 
molecule is supposed to be capable of storing something of the order 
of 10 10 bits of information. 2 According to the Watson-Crick model, 
the molecule has the shape of a ladder twisted into a double helix. 
The two sides of the ladder consist of uniform, linear chains of sugar 
groups alternating with phosphate links. The rungs of the ladder are 
pairs of nitrogenous bases attached on each side to the sugar groups 
in the double helix. There are four of these bases: adenine, guanine, 
cytosine, and thymine, or A, G, C, T for short. A is always paired with 
T, and G always with C, so that the two sides of the ladder are com- 
plementary. The sequence of bases as read down along one side of the 
ladder is the genetic code, written in the four-letter alphabet, 'A*, 
*G\ 'C\ 'T\ Here, then, floating in the nuclear sap, is the code which 
governs the skill of creating a six-foot drum major with a slight squint 
and dimpled cheeks, out of an egg with a diameter of a few microns. 

The code's remarkably complex activities are set off by a relatively 
simple signal: the impact of the fertilizing agent. Theprinciple involved 
must indeed be relatively simple, because in virtually all main groups 
of animals, including rabbits and sheep, normal development of the 



4i8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



egg can be induced by stimulation with non-specific, physical, or 
chemical agents: heat or cold, salinity, ultra-violet rays, galvanic 
currents, or puncture with a fine needle. Though it may be hurtful 
to the male's pride, his seed seems to be a dispensable commodity. 
Its primary function is to trigger off the egg; but—with frogs at least 
— a platinum needle will do just as well.* 

The main task of the growing cell is the manufacture of proteins 
which constitute the basic stuffs of the body, and of protein-enzymes, 
which control all its biochemical activities. The growing cell is pri- 
marily a protein-producing factory, or rather a group of specialized 
plants, each engaged in synthesizing one variety at a time among the 
thousands of different types of protein-molecules. The order and 
quantity in which each substance is produced, is regulated by the 
genetic code. The key-substances are the enzymes, which can be 
regarded as structural embodiments of the genetic instructions coded 
in the DNA chains. Each discrete set of instructions — a code-word 
composed of several hundred code-letters — contains the recipe, as it 
were, for a specific enzyme. It is usual to call these sets of instructions 
'genes* (although the meaning of this traditional term has become 
somewhat blurred and some geneticists prefer more non-committal 
words). Each code-word is composed of sub-wholes: three-letter 
syllables like CTA, AAG, etc. Each of these sub-units in the code- 
sequence is capable of 'recognizing* and transporting one particular 
kind of sub-unit which goes into the making of proteins. These sub- 
units or 'building-blocks' are the amino acids; there are twenty common 
varieties of them. A protein usually contains all or most of the twenty 
varieties of amino-acid units, strung together into a chain of two 
hundred or more in a specific sequence. The number of permuta- 
tions of twenty units in a sequence of several hundred links is of course 
enormous, and accounts for the impressive variety of proteins and 
protein-enzymes which go into the making of our all-too-solid flesh. 
Thus the main process in morphogenesis seems to consist in trans- 
cribing the implicit, 'functionaT four-letter alphabet of the code into 
the explicit 'structural* twenty-letter alphabet of proteins. 

The details of the process are only beginning to be known at the time 
of writing; and progress has become so accelerated in this particular 
field that by the time these pages appear in print much in them will 
be outdated. Broadly speaking, we know at present of two kinds of 
instruction-carriers between the genes and the protein-plants of the 
cell. The first is messenger RNA\ The chemical structure of RNA— 



PRENATAL SKILLS 



419 



ribonucleic acid— is closely related to that of DNA. The DNA chain 
apparendy manufactures 'messenger RNA' chains by the same 
process of base-paring by which it replicates itself. Each messenger is 
supposed to contain the 'recipe' of one specific enzyme, and to carry 
it to the protein-plant, the ribosome. A second type of messenger is 
'transfer RNA\ Each variety of it is a much shorter chain, supposed 
to represent a triplet of code-letters corresponding to a particular 
variety of amino acids. When a transfer RNA unit meets an amino 
unit of the proper type in the proper condition, it will attach itself to 
the unit like a sort of locomotive, drag it to the ribosome plant, and 
shunt it into its proper place in the nascent protein chain, according to 
the instructions of its bigger colleague, the 'messenger RNA*. 

This, in broad outlines, is the picture to date— in the year after the 
Crick-Watson-Wilkins team received the Nobel prize for 'breaking 
the genetic code'. It is to a large extent derived from work on the 
genetics of micro-organisms such as the colon bacillus, and there are 
reasons to believe that something essential is still missing from the 
picture,* But we need not be concerned with these niceties. What 
matters is that we find, literally ab ovo, fixed, invariant codes in 
control of the variable cell matrix. JThe order in which the various 
sub-codes — the genes — become active and engage in producing their 
specific varieties of messenger RNA is supposed to depend on the pre- 
set activities of 'operators' and 'repressors* in the chromosomes, and 
perhaps on some additional biological clocks. But it must also depend 
to some extent on feedback signals from the cytoplasm, including 
signals from neighbouring tissues which reach the cell through its 
sensitive membranes. Finally, recent experiments by Hyden 2a have 
shown that in the nerve-cells of the mature organism experiences 
retained in learning lead to more or less lasting alterations in the 
chemical composition of the cell's RNA content: a fact of great sig- 
nificance for the problem of memory. 



The Cell-Matrix 

The growing cell illustrates the relativity, or complementary nature, 
of such terms as part and whole, or structure and function. 'What are 
called structures are slow processes of long duration, functions are 
quick processes of short duration. If we say that a function such as the 
contraction of a muscle is performed by a structure, it means that a 



420 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



quick and short process-wave is superimposed on a long-lasting and 
slowly running wave (Bertalanfry). 3 

The same considerations apply to the relations between the genetic 
code and the cell-matrix. The latter is of course a very complex struc- 
ture, equipped with an animal and a vegetal pole, with chemical and 
morphogenetic gradients, and with a variety of organelles— these, in 
their ensemble, are the members of the matrix. Each member is a 
sub-whole governed by its sub-code which can be turned on and off 
by orders 'from above, but once triggered into action follows its 
autonomous functional pattern. The centrosomes and kinetosomes, for 
instance, are organelles of apparently similar structure but vastly 
different functions. Both possess the privilege of self-replication when 
the cell divides; both have a cylindrical shape and are made up, it 
seems, of eleven fibres — two in the centre, nine outside. But these 
deceptively simple structures revealed by the electron-microscope 
are complete biochemical machines in miniature. The kinetosomes 
are attached to the cilia or flagella of motile cells and trigger off their 
activities. The centrosomes provide the poles of the spindle apparatus, 
which effects cell division; they establish connections with the chromo- 
somes in the distant nucleus, tear the pairs of duplicated chromosomes 
apart as it were, and direct them towards their new locations in the 
centres of the two nascent daughter cells. 

To take another example, let us cast a quick glance at the most 
glorious of organelles, the mitochondria. There are fifty to five 
thousand of them according to the type of cell and (together with the 
chloroplasts of green-leafed plant-cells) they are 'the power plants of 
all life on earth'. As a physicist has said, waxing lyrical on a biological 
peccadillo, they 'feed on negative entropy and drink orderliness from 
the environment'. 4 The chloroplasts do it by photosynthesis, the 
mitochondria by extracting a very special form of energy from the 
chemical bonds in glucose, fat, and proteins. The end product is ATP 
— adenosine-triphosphate — the universal carrier used by the organism 
to supply the energy needed for the contraction of muscles, the trans- 
mission of nerve impulses, the manufacture of proteins, and so on. 
The synthesizing of ATP is carried out in three main stages (glycolysis, 
Krebs cycle oxidation, and 'respiration'*) involving about fifty dif- 
ferent successive reactions, each of them catalyzed by a specific enzyme 
system. A single mitochondrion may possess up to forty thousand of 
such enzyme systems; their assemblies are arranged in the membrane 
of the organelle in patterns which have been described as 'wiring 



PRENATAL SKILLS 



421 



diagrams*. They represent the sub-codes which govern the operations 
of the energy plant. It also has a complex feedback system: in the 
presence of an excess of ATP, for instance, the organelle will contract. 

Even this very sketchy outline indicates the hierarchic organization 
of the living cell — once considered the ultimate 'atom' of life. The 
genetic code is blue-printed in the chromosomes; but the chromosomes 
do not deal directly with the sub-matrices on lower levels of the 
hierarchy. They do not interfere with the stepwise operations of 
breaking down glucose into phosphoglycerate, into lactate, into 
pyruvate, into citrate, and so forth; these operations, just as those of 
the spindle apparatus of the centrosomes, are governed by their own 
sub-codes. Each organelle is a highly integrated structure and enjoys a 
considerable amount of functional autonomy. Its operations are 
switched on or off by signals from the higher echelons; but these sig- 
nals are addressed, as it were, to the code which governs the action- 
pattern of the whole organelle, and not to its subordinate parts. 
Generally speaking, we shall see that a matrix on any level of the hierarchy 
is represented on the next-higher level by its code. Or, to put it the other 
way round: the members of a matrix are sub-matrices which respond 
as functional units to signals activating their codes. 



Nucletds and Cytoplasm 

The fertilized egg contains the total pattern of the unborn individual. 
This privileged position of a single cell representing the whole is of 
short duration: after the first few cleavages, the daughter cells begin to 
differentiate; they lose their potential capacity of reconstructing the 
whole individual, and are reduced to being parts of the growing 
embryo. 

The process involves both the nucleus and the cytoplasm, but in 
different ways. The characteristics of different types of cells, tissues, 
organs, are essentially the characteristics of their cytoplastic structure, 
which vary from type to type. The nuclei which (jointly with the 
cell's environment) determine that structure also differ according to 
cell-type, but in a subtler, more 'functional' than 'structural' way, It 
is generally assumed that each cell in the mature organism inherits a 
complete set of the genetic blue-print in the DNA chains of its chromo- 
somes; but only a fraction of the set remains active — i.e. those 
genes which govern the cell's specialized functions; the remainder is 



422 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



permanently 'switched off. As mentioned before, the activity of the 
enzyme-producing genes is supposed to be controlled by 'operators* 
and repressors' built into the chromosomes; and these regulators in 
turn are controlled by feedback from the cytoplastic environment. 6 
Thus the changes in the nucleus could be described as functional 
specialization: only certain sub-codes — fractions of the complete code 
— remain operative; whereas the changes in the cytoplasm of successive 
generations amount to structural individuation. 

The nuclear changes can actually be observed under the micro- 
scope. The salivary gland cells of midge larvae for instance possess 
large bundles of chromosomes, which are seen as sausage-like structures, 
with occasional swellings or puffs — the so-called Balbiani rings. The 
purls are the sites of intense RNA production; it is therefore assumed 
that they indicate active genes. The pattern of these swellings changes 
according to the age of the larva and the type of cell.* 

The action of the cytoplasm on the nucleus has also been directly 
demonstrated. When the nucleus from the salivary gland cell of a 
drosophila larva is transplanted into the cytoplasmic environment of a 
cell at an earlier stage of development, the chromosomes again under- 
go very marked changes: certain swellings disappear and others appear 
in their place. This clearly indicates the existence of a feedback mecha- 
nism whereby the development of the cytoplasm as a result of gene 
activity in its turn calls forth the activity of particular genes. 6 

The reverse type of experiment demonstrates the action of nuclei of 
different ages on the same cytoplasmic environment. The nucleus of an 
unfertilized frog-egg is removed, and replaced by a nucleus from a 
developing frog-embryo. If the transplant nucleus was taken from an 
embryo in the early blastular stage, the result will be a clone of normal 
tadpoles; if it was obtained from embryos in later stages of develop- 
ment, it will produce abnormal forms. 

These experiments indicate not only that the nuclei undergo changes 
in the course of differentiation, but also that in the course of these 
changes they progressively lose their erstwhile 'totipotentiality'. The 
more the cell specializes in the role of a part, the less it is capable of 
creating a new whole. 

This does not mean that the DNA chains which contain the genetic 
code of the whole organism are lost in the differentiated cell— it only 
means that as differentiation progresses, more and more genes are 
debarred from activity. Those which remain active are genetic sub- 
codes, governing the particular sub-skills which the specialized cell is 



PRENATAL SKILLS 



433 



called on to perform. Only the future germ-cells, segregated and pro- 
tected from the beginning, retain their total creative potential to con- 
tinue the genetic line— they specialize in immortality as it were. 
Specialization, in morphogenesis as in other fields, exacts its price in 
creativity* 

The transplant experiments which I have briefly mentioned, and 
other evidence clearly show that while on the one hand the nuclear 
code governs the activities of the cell-matrix, the cytoplasm, on the 
other hand, is in communication with the cells' outer environment, 
and by feeding information on the total state of affairs back to the 
nucleus, cc^etermines which sub-code should be switched on next. 
The code as a whole is unalterable; but the choice of the sub-codes to 
be activated depends on the 'lie of the land', as in other skills. The 
destiny of a cell depends on the composition of the cytoplasm which it 
inherited from its mother cell (e.g. more animal or vegetal stuff) and 
on its spatial position in the growing embryo.* We have here the 
equivalent of a flexible strategy in morphogenesis: the development of 
the individual cell is determined by its invariant code and by the 
hazards of environment. The code represents the fixed rules of the 
game: if you get into the ectoderm, you must do this; if into the 
endoderm, you must do that. Both the fixity of the code and the flexi- 
bility of strategy become more evident as we turn to later stages of 
development— the matrices of morphogenetic fields, which differen- 
tiate, in hierarchic order, into organ-systems, organs, and organ-parts. 



Regulative and Mosaic Development 

In the five-day-old salamander embryo, whose development is fairly 
typical for vertebrates in general, transplantation experiments make it 
possible to distinguish well-defined areas which will give rise to the 
eye, gill, limbs, kidney, etc., although not the faintest indication of 
these organs is as yet visible. At this stage, the tissue of a limb-area 
transplanted into a different position on the embryo, or on another 
embryo, will form a complete limb; even a heart can be formed on 
an embryo's flank. Such autonomous, 'self^etermining' tissue-areas 
are called morphogenetic fields. If half of the heart, limb, or eye area is 
cut away, the remainder of the field will form not half an organ, but 
a complete heart, limb or eye—just as, at the earlier, cleavage state, 
each half of a frog-egg, mechanically broken up, will form a complete 



424 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



frog. Moreover, if the tissue of, say, the kidney area is (by centri- 
fuging) completely disintegrated into freely floating separate cells dis- 
tributed at random, these cells, suspended in a proper medium, will in 
due time produce rudimentary kidneys— -just as the dissociated cells 
of a living sponge, which has been broken up by straining through a 
filter, will start to form new cell aggregates and end up by forming a 
complete, normal sponge. 7 

Thus a morphogentic field behaves 'as a unit or a whole and not 
merely the sum of the cellular materials of which it is composed. The 
field with its organizing capacities remains undisturbed if the cellular 
material which it controls under normal circumstances is diminished 
or enlarged. The unit character of the field finds its clearest manifesta- 
tion in these regulative properties.' (Hamburger. 8 ) 

The various fields of the future organs and limbs form a mosaic in 
the embryo as a whole; at the same time they display remarkable 
regulative properties towards their own parts; — they are again Janus- 
faced entities. Each organ primordium is, when 'looking upward', a 
member of the total matrix; when 'looking downward', a self- 
governing, autonomous sub-whole. Although the future of the field 
in its entirety is clearly predetermined on the mosaic principle, the 
future of its parts is still dependent on regulative factors. The cell- 
populations which constitute an organ-primordium have lost their 
genetic totipotentiality, but they stiU possess a sufficient amount of 
multi-potentiality to keep the matrix of the field flexible. The shape of 
the future organ is fixed, but the part which a given cell-group or 
single cell will play in it is again dependent on biochemical gradients 
and inducers in the environment, which will trigger off the appro- 
priate genes in the cells' genetic code. 

The differentiation of organ systems, organ parts, etc., is a stepwise 
affair which has been compared to the way a sculptor carves a statue out 
of a block of wood. With each step in development the functions 
assigned to each group of cells become more precise, and more of its 
genetic potential is suppressed— until in the end most cells lose even 
their basic freedom to divide. By the time the fertilized ovum has 
developed into an adult organism, the individual cell has been re- 
duced from totipotentiality to almost nullipotentiality. It still carries 
the coded blue-print of the whole organism in its chromosomes, but all, 
except that tiny fraction of the code which regulates its specialized 
activities, has been permanently switched off. 



Organizers and Inducers 



The embryo grows; the adult behaves. Growth is controlled by the 
genetic code; adult behaviour by the nervous (and hormonal) systems.* 
But in between the initial and the final stage there are some transient 
controlling agencies at work, which catalyze development by a 
mechanism as yet incompletely understood: the organizers or evocators. 

During the earliest stages of development the growth of the embryo 
takes place in a fairly stable environment, so that feedback-controls 
play a relatively minor part. But with the beginning of gastrulation 
the situation changes: from now on each differentiating tissue acts as 
'environment* on adjacent tissues; the various types of cell-population 
interact within the embryo. 

A particularly important cell-population originates in the grey 
crescent of the zygote; reappears as an analogous crescent on 
the blastula; gives rise to the dorsal lip, migrates into the in- 
ternal cavity of the gastrula, where it takes its place in the chorda- 
mesoderm, and becomes the so-called 'primary organizer* of the 
embryo, specifically concerned with initiating its nervous system— to 
which it will eventually hand over control. The tissue in the ectoderm 
which lies directly above it is destined to become the neural plate — 
but only if it remains in physical contact with the organizer. If that 
contact is prevented, the ectoderm will not form a neural plate and 
there will be no nervous system. If, on the other hand, organizer tissue 
from the dorsal Hp is grafted on to the flank of another salamander 
embryo which is in the process of gastrulation, it will invade the host 
and produce a complete Siamese twin, composed pardy of the in- 
vader's tissue and partly of host tissue. It was this remarkable experi- 
ment, first performed by Spemann and Hilde Mangold in 1925, which 
earned the privileged region of the dorsal lip in the gastrula die name 
of 'primary organizer. 

At a later stage, the organizer tissue seems to differentiate into head-, 
trunk-, and tail-organizers; and with the appearance of organ pri- 
mordia, its inductive functions are further divided up and handed over 
to centres located in the organs themselves. A classic example of in- 
duction is the formation of the vertebrate eye. The rudimentary brain 
has two sacs, or vesicles, attached to it: the future eyes. The brain and 
its eye primordia originate as thickenings of the surface area which, 
after the in-folding of the neural tube, come to lie under the surface. So 
the eye vesicles must now move outward again to make contact with 

425 



42<5 THE ACT OF CREATION 

the surface, but at the same time remain attached to the brain by the 
optic stalks (which will develop into the optic nerves). In the process, 
the vesicles assume the shape of concave saucers, the optic cups. 
When these make contact with the surface, the skin areas overlaying 
the contact areas fold neatly into the hollow cups, thicken, detach 
themselves from the surface, and eventually become the transparent 
lenses. It can be shown that it is the optic cup which induces the skin 
to make a lens, for if the cup of a frog embryo is removed, no lens will 
form; and vice versa, if the eye vesicle is grafted under the embryo's 
belly, the belly skin will form a lens. 

However, the docility of embryonic tissue has its limits. The tissue 
must be 'competent' 9 to react to the inductor; and 'competence' is 
determined by the degree of differentiation the tissue has reached — or, 
put in another way, by the amount of genetic multipotential which it 
still retains. An inductor 'cannot make any cell produce any specific 
response unless the cell is intrinsically prepared to do so'. 10 A given 
region of the ectoderm at a given stage of differentiation may retain 
enough genetic flexibility to become either a lens or skin-tissue; it 
will not be prepared to form a kidney. In the experimental laboratory, 
a transplanted eye-vesicle can be used to induce a lens on the sala- 
mander's belly. But under normal conditions the inductor's function 
is to catalyze or 'evocate' the actualization of the genetic potentials 
present in the appropriate tissue. Hence the term 'evocator-sub- 
stance' for the chemical agent responsible for induction. 

A curious fact about inductors is that they seem to be organ-specific 
but not species-specific. The optic cup of a frog transplanted under a 
salamander embryo's skin will cause it to produce a lens; the primary 
organizer of the salamander will induce brain structures not only in 
frogs but even in fish; 11 and the organizer of a frog, even of a fish, can 
induce secondary embryos in the obliging salamander. But the in- 
duced embryo will be a salamander, not a frog or a fish; and the frog- 
skin transplanted on to the salamander's head will form a frog-mouth, 
not a salamander-mouth. In this respect, too the evocator seems to 
act merely as a trigger-releaser on the genetic potential of the cell. 

This assumption was confirmed when Holtfreter, J. Needham, and 
others discovered that rudimentary nervous systems could be in- 
ducted in salamander embryos by a great variety of liying or dead 
organizers. These include most tissues of the adult salamander itself; 
mouse-liver and insect organs, molluscs, acidified salt solutions, 
sterols, and dye stuffs. Moreover, it was found that some tissues (such 



PRENATAL SKILLS 



427 



as embryonic skin and intestine) which cannot act as inductors when 
alive can do so when killed (in alcohol or by heating). All this points 
to the conclusion that the evocator of the nervous system is a non- 
specific chemical agent whose function is merely 'to release the true 
active substance from neighbouring cytolyzing cells'; 12 and that the 
substance thus released is RNA, the carrier of the cell's genetic instruc- 
tions. It has indeed been shown that there exist distinct RNA gradients 
in the inducted tissues, and that the highest RNA concentrations are 
found in nervous-systems induction. Since the evocator substances, un- 
like hormones, act only by direct contact, i.e. by diffusion from cell to 
cell, it seems that their function is merely to activate those RNA sub- 
codes which will specify the tissues' destiny. This is in keeping with 
Hamburger's definition of embryonic induction as a process in which 
one developing structure, the "inductor", stimulates an adjacent 
structure to undergo a specific differentiation'. 13 Artificial induction 
through transplant experiments would then amount to drastic changes 
in the environment of a cell-population, which interfere with its 
biological time-clocks (the pre-set sequence of gene-activities); just 
as the transplantation of a nucleus into a different cytoplasmic environ- 
ment causes a change in the pattern of its chromosome-puffs. 

Induction is a transient method of regulating development, where the 
genetic potentials of certain cell-populations, or morphogenetic fields, 
are activated by chemical agencies diffused in their immediate environ- 
ment. Although the chemistry of induction is still a ^problematic 
affair, it seems safe to assume, as Mittasch has pointed out, that 'organic 
catalyzers also show a rank order: beginning with the enzymes, which 
are adjusted most specifically to carry through a single reaction, to 
biocatalyzers such as the . . . organizer substances in animals which 
regulate more or less wide complexes of processes, and up to directing 
biocatalyzers, such as many hormones, that influence to a large extent 
the whole organism psychophysically. ,:u 

Past the early and transitory phase of induction, more advanced 
methods of co-ordination and control make their appearance. In the 
human embryo the heart begins to beat at the end of the third week, 
controlled by its own pace-maker, when the whole creature is less 
than a fifth of an inch long. Muscle contractions in response to ex- 
ternal stimuli can be elicited after the eighth week, and spontaneous 
movements may begin in the tenth week. They are myogenic re- 
actions of the muscle tissue to direct local stimulation, while the 
nervous system is still in the making. But the conspicuous readiness 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



of the neural plate to start growing in response to non-specific evoca- 
tors' designates it, as it were, as the heir apparent to the earlier forms 
of integration. 

To sum up: at various stages of embryonic development, and at 
various structural levels, we find different biochemical mechanisms, 
but analogue principles at work. At every stage and level the game is 
played according to fixed rules but with flexible strategies (although 
their flexibility is normally hidden from the eye and revealed only by 
the transplantation and grafting techniques of experimental embry- 
ology). The overall rules of the game are laid down in the complete 
set of instructions of the genetic code; but the particular set of in- 
structions operative at any level at any time is triggered off by mes- 
sages from the inter- and extra-cellular environment, which vary in 
character according to structural level and developmental stage: 
fertilizing agents, cytoplasmic feedbacks, direct-contact evocators, 
hormones, and other catalysts. 

On the level of the zygote, the cell-matrix consists of biochemical 
gradients and organelles; it is a structural mosaic equipped with axial 
polarity which under normal conditions predetermines the head and 
tail region; the blastopores, etc., of the embryo; but it also has striking 
regulative properties revealed by experimental manipulation. With 
progressive differentiation the regulative properties of the cell diminish, 
and its degrees of genetic freedom* freeze up. On the level of the 
morphogenetic field we again find self-regulating properties— half the 
field will still form a complete limb — and a mosaic-matrix of cell- 
populations. The autonomous, self-assertive character of morphogene- 
tic fields is manifested in grafting and centrifuging experiments; their 
dependent, or part character by the trivial fart that they are kept in their 
proper size and place in the normally growing organism. This will 
sound less of a truism when we turn to the phenomena of regeneration 
(Chapter HI). We shall find regulative character and mosaic character, 
autonomy and subservience, the self-assertion of the part and its 
dependence on the whole to be complementary aspects on every level 
of the hierarchy in normal development and behaviour; but also, that 
under abnormal conditions this ceases to be the case, and that the part 
may then assert itself at the expense of the whole, with sometimes 
beneficial, mostly destructive, effects.* 



NOTES 



To p. 418. This is, of course, not meant to belittle the enormous advantages 
of sexual over asexual reproduction. 

To p. 419. The three-letter 'dictionary*, for instance, is partly a dictionary 
of synonyms: there are 4 3 =^64 triplets, but only 20 amino acids, and many of the 
latter are represented by more than one code syllable. 

To p. 420. 'Respiration' is an approximate term. The process is in fact oxida- 
tive phosphorylation. 

To p. 422. In some, probably extreme cases, the nuclear changes are even 
more drastic. The nucleus of the fertilized egg of the gall-midge contains forty 
chromosomes, and in the course of the first few divisions these are faithfully 
duplicated. But in the fifth division, only eight sets of chromosomes in the soma 
cells duplicate in the orthodox manner; the other thirty-two fail to do so and 
gradually dissolve in the cytoplasm. The future germ cells, however, which have 
previously been segregated from the rest of the eggs, do not participate in the 
fateful fifth division and preserve their chromosome complement intact. Thus 
the nuclei of all specialized body cells have only eight chromosomes, whereas 
the germ cells have forty. Cf. Fischberg, M. and Bladder, A. W. (1961). 

To p. 423. In a paper read at the British Association Meeting in August 
1962, L. Wolpert suggested that differentiation resulted from the single cell's 
tendency to stick on to that part of the gastrula wall best suited for it (the 
idea seems to have been originated by T. Gusthafson). At the same meeting 32. N. 
Willmer showed that changes in the salt balance of the surrounding medium 
made amoebae change from amoeboid to flagellate form, reversibly — the implica- 
tion being that chemical gradients played an important part in the early stages of 
differentiation (New Scientist, No 303, 6.9.1962, p. 492). 

To p. 425, During maturation in the higher species, the two types of control 
overlap; and pre-set biological time-clocks seem to exercise some influence 
throughout adult life. 

To p. 428. In this necessarily simplified discussion of morphogenetic pro- 
cesses I have made no mention of cytoplasmic inheritance and other complicating 
factors, which do not affect the basic argument of this book. 



429 



II 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 
Development of the Nervous System 

The pioneer work on the development of the nervous system in 
vertebrate embryos is G. E. CoghilTs monumental study of 
ambystoma, a larval form of salamander. 1 Coghill published his 
results in a series of papers spread over a period of twenty-five years, 
1914-39. Since they are surprisingly seldom quoted outside the 
technical literature — presumably because they ran against the be- 
haviourist Zeitgeist — I must briefly summarize his conclusions. 

The traditional assumption about the development of the nervous 
system was that elementary, local reflexes arise first, and are chained 
together at a later stage. Thus the segmental reflex arcs of the earth- 
worm would develop first, as independent units aligned in a series 
perpendicular to its axis, and only later on would they become con- 
nected, like rings hanging from a festoon string, by the spinal cord. 
CoghilTs work showed that the opposite is true. In the salamander, 
development starts with the growth of the motor-tracts of the cord 
axially from head to tail; then this central bundle sends out collateral 
branches into the segmental muscles, co-ordinating their actions in 
primitive, unitary patterns; the sensory neurons become functional 
only at a later stage, and the local reflex-arcs come last, as segrega- 
tions of 'partial patterns' out of the 'total pattern' which preceded them. 
The whole development is centrifugal: the stem precedes the branches, 
spontaneous undifferentiated movements involving the whole neuro- 
muscular apparatus precede differentiated movement, total responses 
precede specialized local responses. To give an example: when the 
limbs develop, their first movements are entirely dependent on and 
synchronized with the movements of the trunk. Only later on do the 
limbs begin to move independently; the same applies to the motions 
of head, mouth, etc. The growth of the nervous system from beginning 

430 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



431 



to end is dominated by 'a totally integrated matrix, and not a progres- 
sive integration of primarily individuated units*. The organism is not 
a sum of its reflexes, but on the contrary 'the meclianism of the total 
pattern is an essential component of the performance of the part, i.e. 
the reflex'. The stimulus-response scheme cannot explain even em- 
bryonic behaviour, because movements appear long before the motor 
neurons of the reflex arc are connected with the sensory neurons. This 
centrifugal mode of development means that the individual acts on 
its environment before it reacts to its environment. 

'In so far as the correlation of nervous structure and function in the 
development of the individual has been carried, structural provision 
has been found for the perpetuation of spontaneity, autonomy, or 
initiative as a factor in its behaviour. Any theory of motivation, there- 
fore, that attributes this function wholly to the environment, is 
grossly inadequate.' The idea that instincts are chained reflexes must 
be abandoned; instincts represent 'total action patterns in response to 
relatively general situations'. Comparing the embryonic development 
ofambystoma with that of the human foetus, Coghill sums up: 

In conclusion I am convinced by a study of all available records of 
movement in human foetuses during the first six months, that be- 
haviour develops in man as it does in ambystoma by the expansion 
of a total pattern that is integrated as a whole from the beginning, 
and by individuation of partial patterns (reflexes) within the unitary 
whole.* 

We thus find in the development of the nervous system the same 
principles at work which we have discussed before. The neural plate 
starts as a primordium with multipotential cell-populations which 
differentiate in a series of steps into the brain, the spinal cord, and its 
sub-structures. The 'wiring diagram' of the organism has a standar- 
dized pattern — an invariant code; but transplant experiments again 
show the great flexibility of the 'neurogenetic skill' which realizes that 
pattern. If a limb-bud from a salamander embryo is transplanted to 
another embryo's flank, outgrowing nerve-fibres locate the bud and 
establish a normal nerve pattern. The bulb-shaped tips of the outgrow- 
ing nerves are apparendy guided by sub-microscopic structures in the 
cell-matrix of the growing bud — at least according to the current 
'contact guidance' theory. 

I have called differentiation of structure and integration of function 



43^ THE ACT OF CREATION 

complementary aspects of a unitary process. But the 'functions' of the 
growing embryo are different from the 'functions' of the adult. It 
has been shown that the limb-buds and wing buds of chick embryos 
develop into almost normal legs and wings if nerves are prevented 
from entering them. This does not mean, of course, that differentiation 
of structure comes first, and integration of function later on, as a 
separate act. For the function of the leg-bud is to grow— -not to walk. 
Growth is a function controlled by the genetic code; when growth is 
completed and the time has come to walk, the nervous system takes 
over control; and if it fails to do so, the muscle tissues will degenerate, 
as denervated adult muscles do.* 



Locomotor Hierarchies 

'Whatever the nature of organizing relations may be,' J. Needham 
wrote in 1932, 'they form the central problem of biology, and biology 
will be fruitful in the future only if this is recognized. The hierarchy of 
relations, from the molecular structure of carbon compounds to the 
equilibirum of species and ecological wholes, will perhaps be the 
leading idea of the future.' 2 

This prophecy has not come true. The Gestalt school's over-em- 
phasis on 'wholeness', and the behaviourists' over-emphasis on 'simple 
elementary processes— the so-called S.-R. (stimulus-response) scheme 
—created a controversy based on a fallacious alternative, and prevented 
a true appreciation of the multi-layered hierarchic order to be found in 
all manifestations of life. 

Yet the idea is of course by no means new; hierarchies in nervous 
function were proposed by Herbert Spencer in the 1870s, and elabor- 
ated by Hughlings Jackson, Sherrington, and others. 3 The hierarchical 
character of skills was demonstrated in great detail by Bryan and 
Harter in their study of telegraphy and in Book's study of touch- 
typing (see below, pp. 544 ff ) at the turn of the century, but neither 
S-R psychologists nor Gestaltists paid attention to them. Woodger 
(1929) attempted a formalization, by means of symbolic logic, of 
certain types of hierarchies ('divisional hierarchies', 'spatial hierarchies', 
'genetic hierarchies', etc.) which are of somewhat abstract interest. 
Heidenhain (1923) 4 proposed a hierarchy of 'histo-systems' which are 
'encapsulated* into one another (e.g. neuro-fibriles, neurons, nerve 
fibres), Bertadanfiy (1952) tried to make a distinction between 'hier- 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



433 



archies of parts', 'hierarchies of processes', 'hierarchies of centraliza- 
tion, etc. Tinbergen defined instinct as a hierarchically organized 
nervous mechanism — but his mechanism is fixed and rigid (see below 
p. 478). A stimulating discussion of the subject can be found in 
Miller, Galanter, and Pribram's remarkable essay on 'Plans and the 
Structure of Behaviour' (i960). 

The word 'hierarchy can be used to mean simply rank-order. 
Hull's famous 'habit family hierarchy', for instance, means just that 
(the ordering of a group of interchangeable responses according to 
their strength), and is not a hierarchy at all in the sense in which the 
term is used in this book. I have summarized what I meant by it in the 
chapter 'Partness and Wholeness' (Book One, Chapter XIH). A hier- 
archy, in this sense, is not like arowof organ pipes; it is like a tree, arboriz- 
ing downward. The structural or functional entities on each level are 
autonomous sub-wholes of complex pattern, but are represented on 
the next higher level as units. In every organic hierarchy, to para- 
phrase Gertrude Stein's statement about the rose, a part is a whole is a 
part is a whole*. 




Figure 11 

Perhaps the most satisfactory theoretical treatment of the concept of 
hierarchic order was given by Paul Weiss— whose experimental work 
was a major contribution towards providing the concept with a firm 
empirical hasis. The quotation which follows is from the celebrated 
Hixon Symposium; its vividness is enhanced by the fact that it is 



434 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



taken from an ex tempore contribution by Weiss to the discussion of 
Lashley's paper on 'The Problem of Serial Order in Behaviour* (my 
italics): 

'While the physiologist and psychologist deal with the ready-made 
machine of the nervous system and can add to it as many properties as 
he thinks necessary, the embryologist must explain just how such an 
immensely intricate, yet orderly, thing can develop. These studies 
are still in their infancy, but a few things have already come out . . . 
for instance, the relative autonomy of structured patterns of activity, and the 
hierarchical principle of their organization, . . . The nervous system is not 
one big monotonic pool whose elements can be freely recombined in 
any number of groupings, thereby giving an infinite variety of nervous 
responses. This used to be the old idea of the associationists, and it is 
utterly incompatible with what we have learned about the develop- 
ment of the nervous system and its function in animals. 

'The working of the central nervous system is a hierarchic affair in 
which functions at the higher levels do not deal directly with the ultimate 
structural units, such as neurons or motor units, but operate by activa- 
ting lower patterns that have their own relatively autonomous struc- 
tural unity. The same is true for the sensory input which . . . operates 
by affecting, distorting, and somehow modifying the pre-existing, 
preformed patterns of central co-ordination. . . . The final output is 
then the outcome of this hierarchical passing down of distortions and 
modifications of intrinsically preformed patterns of excitation, which 
are in no way replicas of the input. The structure of the input does not 
produce the structure of the output, hut merely modifies intrinsic nervous 
activities that have a structural organization of their own. This has been 
proved by observation and experiment. Coghill has shown that the 
motor patterns of the animal develop prior to the development of 
sensory innervation. I have shown, as others have, that the removal of 
the sensory innervation does not abolish the co-ordination of motor activities. 
Moreover, co-ordinated motor functions of limbs and other parts 
develop even if these parts have been experimentally prevented from 
ever becoming innervated by sensory fibres. Therefore, the sensory 
pathway can have nothing to do with the structure of the motor 
response. There are still some authors who try to save the old associa- 
tionist idea that actually the input shapes the structure of the output. I 
think that they are fighting a losing fight, and I think that today's 
discussion ought to have given them the coup de grdce. 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



435 



'Intrinsic automatic rhythms have been shown, for instance, by 
Adrian in the brain stem of the goldfish and in insect ganglia, by 
Prosser in other arthropods, by Bremer and by von Hoist in the spinal 
cord, and by Bethe in jellyfish. I have shown experimentally that any 
group of bulbar or spinal nerve cells taken from vertebrates, if deprived 
of their structural bonds of restraining influences and allowed to under- 
go a certain degree of degradation, will display permanent automatic, 
rhythmic, synchronized activity of remarkable regularity. Rhythmic 
activity, therefore, seems a basic property of pools of nervous elements. 
. . . The rhythm is not something generated through an input rhythm, 
but is itself a primary rhythm which may be released and even speeded 
up or retarded by the input, but is not derived from the input. So we 
have experimental evidence that rhythmic automatism, autonomy of 
pattern, and hierarchical organization are primary attributes of even the 
simplest nervous systems, and I think that this unifies our view of the 
nervous system/ 5 

Let me enlarge on some of these points and add a few facts which 
have emerged since. 

In the first place it has been found that intrinsic, rhythmic activity 
of an autonomous character is not confined to motor nerves, but that 
'receptors also are spontaneously active even in the absence of stimula- 
tion from environment.' 8 This spontaneous receptor activity, while 
modified by environmental events, is under efferent control from the 
central nervous system. The central control (both of the spontaneous 
receptor activity and of the input) is, as we shall see, primarily of a 
restraining, inhibitory nature. But for the time being let us confine 
ourselves to motor organization. 

In an earlier paper (1941 a, p. 23) Weiss distinguished the following 
levels of the hierarchy: 

'1. The level of the individual motor unit. 
'2. All the motor units belonging to one muscle. 
'3. Co-ordinated functions of muscular complexes relating to a 
single joint. 

'4. Co-ordinated movements of a limb as a whole. 

'5. Co-ordinated movements of a number of locomotor organs 

resulting in locomotion. 
'6. "The highest level common to all animals", the movements of 

"the animal as a whole**.* 



436" 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



This is as far as the schema proposed by Weiss goes. Now let me 
extend it one step further downward in the hierarchy. Even the lowest 
among the six levels is a very complex affair. The individual muscle 
cell of a striped muscle — usually called a muscle fibre — is a long, 
cylindrical structure surrounded by a membrane. Its principal functions 
are: (a) to serve as a receptor for nerve impulses which reach it at the 
synapse through a chemical transmitter; (b) to re-code this message 
into an electro-chemical excitation spreading along its surface; (c) to 
relay it to the actual contractile structure, and to provide the energy 
for the contraction in the cell's internal energy currency — ATP; 
(d) to contract.* This involves at least three distinct processes (acetyl- 
choline transmission; sodium-potassium action potentials; activation 
by ATP) entering successively into action between the synaptic and 
the filament levels, with mechanical contraction as the end product. 
Thus the ultimate 'motor unit' at the base of the hierarchy is not the 
cell itself, but the apparatus within it which provides the contraction. 

That apparatus is, broadly speaking, a kind of cylindrical cable, the 
fibre, composed of a bundle of fibrils, each in turn composed of 
bundles of filaments. The filaments are of two varieties, a thick 
and a thin one, the former supposed to be consisting of molecular 
threads of actin, the second of myosin. The combination of these two 
proteins — acto-myosin — is a substance which contracts when activa- 
ted by the energy carrier of the cell, ATP. The mechanism of the con- 
traction is presumed to be a telescoping into each other of the thick 
and fine bundles of filaments. 7 * 

It is assumed, then, that muscle movement is due to the chemical 
action of ATP on contractile proteins; and moreover that essentially 
the same process is responsible for the streaming motion of amoeba, 
the rowing motion of cilia, and the tail-stroke motion of flagella. 
Amoeba, as I have mentioned before (note to p. 423, previous chapter) 
are capable of changing from amoeboid to flagellate form — and back. 
Thus at the very bottom of the hierarchy we find the same basic, 
universal mechanism — the archetype of organic motility as it were — 
throughout the whole animal kingdom from amoeba to man; and 
within man, we again see it at work, serving such varied functions as 
the swimming of his spermatozoa, die brisding of his hair, and the 
flexing of his muscles in a tennis-stroke. It is a mechanism or apparatus 
with a high degree of autonomy — and it reminds one of the equally 
autonomous functioning and universal occurrence of the power- 
plant-organeile, the mitochondria. 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



437 



However close we seem to get to rock-bottom in the organic 
hierarchy, we find complex, integrated sub-wholes leading a relatively 
autonomous existence. Viruses have been compared to nomadic* 
genes (though 'freelancing* genes might be a more appropriate des- 
cription). 

Even a dead muscle cell (dissected and soaked in a cold glycerine 
solution for months, which makes it very dead indeed) will contract 
when exposed to the chemical trigger-action of ATP. The glycerine 
destroys cell-components serving its higher functions, but the essential 
structure of the fibrils — the structural matrix of the basic motor unit 
— remains intact; and it is still capable of functioning according to its 
built-in code. This function is of course a fixed reaction, as one would 
expect on the lowest level of the hierarchy; it is activated by the trigger- 
action of ATP on the acto-myosin. The environment of this matrix is 
represented by the temperature, oxygen supply, degree of fatigue in 
the cell, but the degrees of freedom of the fibre to adjust to these 
conditions boil down to an 'aU-or-nothing' strategy: the alternative 
is to twitch or not to twitch. 

On the higher levels of the hierarchy, the autonomous function- 
patterns of muscles and muscle-complexes are even more in evidence; 
at the same time the degrees of freedom in the matrix allowing for 
adaptable performance increase with each level. Muscles dissected 
from the body and put into Ringer solution will contract normally for 
hours. Practically any part of an animal's heart, a muscular strip, and 
even a single muscle cell grown on a blood clot, will continue to go 
on beating in its own intrinsic rhydim. The heart of the chick embryo 
starts beating before any nerve cells have grown into it, and the hearts 
of frogs and tortoises will go on beating normally if the nerve supply 
is cut. Some smooth muscles equally show a rhythm of their own. 

But complementary to this Eigenfunktion, or functional autonomy, 
is control by a centre or system on the next higher level. The heart has 
its own pacemaker-system which is in itself a threefold hierarchy; 
under normal conditions, the sino-auricular node, the fastest part, 
acts as a pacemaker; but if it is prevented from doing so, the auro- 
ventricular node will take over, and as a last resort (in experiments 
carried out on frog and tortoise) yet a third centre may enter into 
action. The pacemaker-system is, in its turn, subject to regulatory 
control by sympathetic and parasympathetic nerves and by hormones, 
which will speed up or slow down the rate of beat by order of centres 
in the hypothalamus. Other organs — kidney, intestine, stomach — also 



438 THE ACT OF CREATION 

have their self-regulating, intrinsic codes which assure their status as 
autonomous sub-wholes, while at the same time they function as parts 
in a multi-levelled hierarchy. Even the mid-brain centres which 
control temperature, metabolism, food and liquid intake, respiration, 
etc. — even these homeostatic controls responsible for maintaining the 
equilibrium of the milieu interieur, turn out to be subject to the control 
of still higher levels. They are 'biassed homeostats* which can be 'set', 
as a thermostat is 'set* by the tenant to keep a higher or lower room 
temperature. 8 And so the top of the hierarchy which controls the 
controls recedes into a cloud— just as its base is embedded in the 
murky problem of what constitutes living matter — and ultimately 
dissolves into genetic mutations with thresholds on the quantum 
level. 

The Goldfish and the Crab 

Getting back to earth, that is, to the medium levels of the hierarchy — 
the levels 3, 4, and 5 in Weiss*s schema — we find, fortunately, more 
precise indications about its manner of working. 

Von Hoist's study of the swiniming motions of fish revealed a 
distinct three-step hierarchy: (a) the motions of the rays within a 
single fin, due to the alternative contractions of two antagonistic 
pairs of muscles; (b) the motions of the fin as a whole; and (c) the co- 
ordination of the motions of all the fins. In the anaesthetized goldfish, 
the swinging motions of each individual ray remain perfecdy regular, 
but their co-ordination within the fin is disturbed: they flutter in dis- 
order. The anaesthesia evidently does not affect the integrative centres 
on the lowest (a) level, but puts the higher nervous centres on the (b) 
level out of action. On the next higher, (c) level, the pectoral fin acts 
as a kind of pacemaker by imposing, or superimposing, its own rhythm 
on die caudal fins — the so-called 'magnet effect'. This whole loco- 
motor hierarchy is relatively independent of sensory stimuli, for 
fishes and tadpoles go on swimming in perfect co-ordination if they 
have been disafferentated, i.e. if all the main sensory connections have 
been severed. Von Hoist concludes that the stimulus-response schema 
does not apply to the autonomous locomotive hierarchy, and that 'the 
reflex is not the primary element of behaviour but a device for adapt- 
ing the primary automatism to changing peripheral conditions'. 9 

Higher up on the evolutionary ladder we find increasing flexibility 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



439 



of motor skills. In a series of famous experiments, von Buddenbrook 
and Bethe have shown that the removal cf one or several legs from 
centipedes, spiders, and other insects does not lead to disorganization, 
but to a spontaneous rearrangement of the whole pattern of loco- 
motion which is instantaneous and not preceded by trial-and-error 
learning. The normal progress of an insect or crab is the so-called 
cross-amble'. If 'U and 'R' stand for left and right, and the index 
numbers stand for the order of legs from front to rear, the crab's 
locomotive code is as follows: R x , L 2 , R 3 , L 4 , R 5 , etc., are stepping 
simultaneously; then Lj, R 2 , L 3 , R 4 , L 5 — are stepping simultaneously; 
and so on. If, now, the left front leg is removed, the pattern changes 
instantaneously to: R 1 , L 3 , R3, L 5 , etc. ; followed by L 2 , R 2 , L 4 , R 4 , L 6 , etc. 
The crab's progress before and after loss of the left front leg: 



Before: 



7 



X 



Z 1 




-Pi ► 



After: 7 




Figure 12 



This transformation indicates that the front legs act as 'pacemakers'; 
this makes it impossible for the animal to adopt the simpler solution of 
preserving the original pattern minus 1^: for in tins case R 2 would 
become the second pacemaker and both pacemakers would be on the 
right side of the animal. The crab's behaviour provides us with a 
rather elegant example how a motor skill can be adapted to changed 
conditions while preserving the basic pattern laid down in its code. I 
have mentioned other examples earlier on — from the spider's net to 
the pianist who transposes a tune from one key to another. The 
experiments to be described presently illustrate the challenging nature 
of the problem. 



Shuffling the Salamanders Limbs 



Weiss's transplantation experiments date back to the 1920s and 
proved to be, as one author said, 'of immeasurable positive signifi- 
cance for the appraisal of centro-peripheral co-ordination in nervous 
function. 10 

Weiss grafted fully developed limbs of salamander as super-numera- 
ries on to normal animals which thus had five limbs instead of four. The 
additional limb was always grafted next to a normal one, and in the 
process some of the nerve-fibres supplying the normal limb were 
severed. At first the transplant limb hung inertly from the body as a 
mere appendage — the fifth wheel of the cart. However, after a few 
weeks, it began to give signs of movement, and within a short time it 
functioned in complete synchronicity with the adjacent normal limb, 
as its equal in vigour and co-ordination. 

The implications of this phenomenon wece described by Weiss as 
follows (italics in the original): 

'As could be incontrovertibly gathered from the microscopical 
(post-mortem) investigation and reconstruction of the course of the 
nerves in the original limb and in the transplanted limb, this is what 
took place. The severed nerve fibres had vigorously split up in the 
scar at the place of grafting. The branches had pressed forward, and 
some of them, had eventually met the degenerated nerve paths of the 
transplanted limb. As fortuitously as they were located and distributed, 
they had penetrated into these and so had reached the muscles ... in 
the most extraordinary and ^discriminate tangle. . . . Moreover, 
those few paths belonging to the normal extremity which had also 
been previously cut (in order to obtain severed nerve stumps capable 
of regeneration for the supply of the grafted limb) these too were 
filled with fresh nerves. In the end, therefore, the relatively small 
number of ganglion cells, which originally led to a small, limited 
section of the musculature of the normal extremity were now not 
only connected with this very section of muscle again, but in addition 

with the entire musculature of the grafted limb Thus not only have 

the ganglion cells involved to serve a terminal area several times as 
large as before; and not only have they to serve muscles altogether 
different from the previous ones ... but above all the previous rule, 
that one ganglion cell had connections with only one muscle, now 
becomes the exception. Instead the rule is now a boundless confusion 
of conduction paths.* 11 

440 



PC 



0 


3 1 


1 ' 






6 




) < 


■ 1 




A B C D £ A fi C D £ 
0 0 0 0 0 t t t t -v 



origwuiL extremity tran^lcmted,extrem^ 

Figure 13 

Assuming D 0 and E 0 to be a pair of antagonistic muscles — how can 
they properly function if both now depend on the same nerve supply? 
And what about \, B t , C t ? Yet this 'boundless confusion of con- 
duction paths' nevertheless produces perfectly co-ordinated movement- 
Weiss concludes that it is not the topographical layout of the pathways 
which matters, but the specific properties of the excitation transmitted 
by them; in other words, that although each muscle of the added 
limb will receive a chaotic medley of excitations, it will respond 
selectively to such excitations only which are appropriate to it: 

'The means by which the central nervous system maintains concord 
with each muscle individually, does not consist in separate conduction 
paths. ... If one and the same nerve cell has to supply excitation to 
several organs simultaneously, but if under these circumstances only 
one single route common to all these end-organs is at its disposal . . . 
then it is logical to assume that the periphery is so constituted that a 
control of its functioning in a co-ordinated manner inheres in itself. . . . 
We require ... a mechanism of positive selectivity in the end organ, 
which must explain us why, when two muscles in the same state arc 
given, one of them enters into function and the other does not, 

441 



442 THE ACT OF CREATION 

although both, being connected with the same nerve cell, receive 
excitation equally. . . . The nature of every muscle is such that it does 
not react to every excitation from the centre, but only to excitation of a 
quite definite form which is characteristic for it.' 12 

To account for the specific selectivity of muscle response, Weiss 
uses the analogy of selective resonance in a broad sense. The acoustic 
analysers of the ear each respond to one particular pitch and to one 
only, thus analysing a complex clang into its harmonic elements. 
Mutatis mutandis, Weiss assumes that: 

\ . . the total impulse flowing towards a particular peripheral 
region from the central nervous system can, metaphorically speaking, 
forthwith be designated as an "excitation clang". The "excitation 
clang" is composed of "excitation tones" for the varying muscles 
which are to be activated at a given moment, and hence is constantly 
fluctuating in its composition. . . . The process now is as follows: at 
the very same time, the same "excitation clang" flows through all 
the motor root fibres (at least all those supplying a given functional 
area of considerable extent) towards the periphery. It flows equally 
through all the fibres as if it had been indiscriminately poured into a 
canal system and were flooding all the channels. Thus it arrives at all 
the muscles which are in any way whatever connected with the centre. 
But when it gets to this point it is analysed. Every muscle, in accordance 
with its constitution, selects the components appropriate to it from 
those eventually arriving, and acts as if these components alone had 
arrived. And thus, although the very same impulse streams to all the 
muscles and across every available route, only that combination of 
muscles comes into action — as is now intelligible — which the central 
nervous system has provided for/ 15 

He then proceeds to show that the theory of selective response is 
not contradicted by the mdiscriminate responses of muscles to electro- 
galvanic stimulation. The latter is an artificial, gross stimulation which 
compares to natural stimulation like a violent a-periodic blast to a 
specific clang. *Just as, both with the clang and with the blast, the sub- 
stratum carrying the movement is always the same, i.e. the air, so 
obviously the medium in which both the organized and the un- 
organized nerve impulse run their course is always the same, i.e. the 
conductive substance of the nerve fibre. But just as the clang sets a 
definite selection of resonators vibrating, whereas a noise or blast 
causes them to resound all at once and without an exception; so also 
only the organized impulse, built up of specific impulse-tones, is 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



443 



capable of bringing the co-ordinated selection of muscles into activity, 
while the artificially induced, unorganized impulse, by contrast, 
forces every muscle whatsoever which it reaches into function.' 1 * 

Let me translate the picture that emerges from the experimental 
evidence into the terms of the present theory. The locomotor matrix 
on level 4 of the hierarchy (p. 435) is represented by the muscular 
structure of the limb, plus the 'canal-system' of nervous pathways 
leading into it, and includes the apparatus — whatever its nature — 
which accounts for the selectivity of the response by enabling muscles 
to analyse incoming impulses. The code is the sequence of excitation- 
clangs which calls forth one complete motion— say, one step of the 
limb. Members of the matrix are the several joints on the next-lower 
level No. 3, which are triggered off in a pre-set order by their sub- 
codes, i.e. by the appropriate components of the excitation-clang. 
We may remember by way of analogy, how part-sequences of the 
genetic code are triggered into action in a pre-set order. 

The 'motor unit' at the bottom of the hierarchy responds according 
to the aH-or-nodiing rule, but the musculature of a joint is capable of 
graded responses, and the motions of the whole limb follow a flexible 
strategy — shorter or longer step, swift or groping — dependent on the 
input from the environment. Weiss accounted for these variations by 
proposing that the excitation-clang 'is constantly fluctuating in its 
composition*, and thus determines which single muscle should be 
activated at any given moment. But this conception does not seem to 
agree well with the basic principle that centres on high levels do not 
deal directly with units on low levels of the hierarchy. A way out of 
this difficulty is to be found in suggestions by Ruch (195 1) and Miller 
et al. (i960), according to which pre-set patterns of skilled, movements 
are triggered offas units by the brain; but the signal— i.e. the 'excitation 
clang* — would merely 'rough in* the sequence of movements 'and thus 
reduce the troublesome transients involved in the correction of move- 
ment by output-informed feedbacks'. 15 Since feedback circuits must 
be assumed to operate on every level, down to the single cell, the 
adjustment of the details of the 'roughed-in' movement could be 
handed over to lower levels. Miller et al. have made the further sugges- 
tion that this handing-down procedure may be the equivalent of 
converting an order coded in a 'digital' language, into a graded, 
'analogue' output. The excitation-clang could thus consist in a series 
of 'on*, 'off signals like the dots and dashes of the Morse code; but 
each sub-unit could respond to its specific 'on' signal by a 'more* or 



444 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



'less' intense activity, dependent on local conditions (see also below, 
pp. 519 f£). These are speculations, and offered by their authors as 
such; but there are various alternative possibilities to account for the 
' fillin g in of details which were left open in the generalized excitation 
pattern, by feedback devices on successively lower levels. 

Limits of Control 

In the experiments previously discussed, a super-numerary limb was 
grafted next to a normal one, facing in the same direction. In another 
series of experiments Weiss exchanged and reversed the position of 
the limbs of newts. The result is again best described in his own words: 

'The essential independence of the structure of motor activity is 
dramatically demonstrated when one exchanges and reverses the 
limbs of animals and then finds them crawling backwards whenever 
they aim to crawl forwards and vice versa. . . . This has been done in 
the developed animal, but the same operations have been done in 
embryos, and these animals have then functioned in reverse from the 
very beginning. What more spectacular expression can there be of the 
intrinsic primacy of the motor patterns of behaviour for which the 
external input acts only as a selective trigger?* 16 

In other transplant experiments, only the position of the two fore- 
limbs was interchanged and reversed: 

*The grafted limbs moved just as they would have done had they 
been left in their original position, causing backward motion when 
the rest of the animal was trying to move forward, and forward motion 
when the rest of the animal was trying, for example, to avoid a noxious 
stimulus presented in front of it, A year's experience did not change 
this reversed movement of the grafted legs.' 17 

The experiment beautifully illustrates the autonomy of the limb- 
matrix. As in the fifth-limb experiment, the nerves growing out of 
the stump reached the muscles of the grafted limb in a random manner. 
Once more, the graft-limb achieved perfectly co-ordinated motion, 
thanks (we assume) to the analyser devices in the muscles which 
respond to one component in the clang signal only. But since the 
limb was grafted in reverse, it has to step in reverse. No doubt the poor 
creature senses that something is wrong if its fore-limbs move back- 
ward and the back limbs move forward. But owing to the principles 



THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 



445 



of hierarchic order, the centre which co-ordinates the movements of 
the animal as a whole — level 5 in "Weiss's schema — cannot interfere 
with the functioning of the analyser devices on level 2, to reverse their 
responses. It apparently cannot even prevent excitation-clangs being 
triggered off automatically by level 4 to the useless limbs. And when 
the excitation reaches the latter, they respond as they must. We have 
here a first, artificially produced example of 'faulty integrations' which 
will occupy our attention later on. 

The example further illustrates a point mentioned before: a matrix 
on the n-level is represented on the n -j- 1 level by its code. There is, under 
normal conditions, no direct commerce between its members on the 
n — 1 level, and the co-ordinating agency on the n + 1 level. If the 
latter interferes directly with the former, routines become disor- 
ganized, and we get the paradox of the centipede'. Loss of direct 
control over automatized processes on lower levels of the body hier- 
archy is part of the price paid for differentiation and specialization. 
The price is of course worth paying so long as the species lives in an 
environment that is fairly stable. It is after all not part of the normal 
destiny of the salamander to encounter Dr. Paul Weiss. 

NOTES 

To p. 431. The validity of Coghill's findings for a whole range of other 
species — cat, bird, man — was demonstrated in a general way by authors like 
Coronios (1933), Herrick (1929), Kuo (1932). However, some geneticists (e.g. 
Windle and his associates) have maintained that functional co-ordination in 
higher species is the result of additive chaining of specialized local reflexes. As 
against this, Hooker (1950) has pointed out the undisputed fact that motor nerves 
are functional before the sensory nerves, and that the sensory and intercallated 
neurons in the reflex arc are the last to become functional, which amounts to an 
indirect refutation of the reflex summation view. For a summary of this con- 
troversy see Thorpe (1956) pp. 20 IE and p. 45; also Barron (1950) and Hooker 
(1950). 

On the other hand, Tinbergen has shown that in some patterns of complex 
instinct behaviour (e.g. nest building, Kortlandt, 1940), the part-performances 
which go into the total pattern emerge at different times, following 'a fixed time 
pattern just as with growing morphological structures' (Tinbergen, 1951, p. 136). 
Thus, for instance, fastening of twigs in the nest precedes searching for twigs. 
The existence of 'internal clocks* which regulate the serial activation of the 
various sub-codes of the integrated performance is entirely in keeping with the 
total pattern view. Thorpe concludes: 'Embryological studies now suggest that 
ontogenetically, complex muscle co-ordinations resembling fixed action patterns 
[see below] precede responses of the simple reflex type in mammals.* Cf. next 
note 

To p. 432. This confusion may have been a contributing factor in the con- 
troversy mentioned in the previous note. Since myogenic muscle contractions 



446 THE ACT OF CREATION 

can be produced in embryos by electrical or mechanical stimulation before 
neuro-muscular integration is established, the 'isolated reflex-school' assumed 
such pseudo-reflexes to be true reflexes and the primary elements of adult be- 
haviour. See, e.g. Thorpe, loc. cit. 

To p. 434. The Hixon Symposium was one of the most fertile exchanges ever 
held between leading experts in various disciplines. Among its participants were 
H. Kluver, Wolfgang K6hler,K. S. Lashley, W. S. McCulloch John V. Neumann, 
R. W. Gerard, Lorente de No, Paul Weiss, Linus Pauling, etc., to mention only 
a few. No wonder that Weiss, carried away by enthusiasm after hearing 
Lashley 's brilliant paper on 'The Problem of Serial Order in Behaviour*, concluded 
with expressing his hope that today's 'discussion will mark a turning point in the 
building of neurological theories'. 

To p. 436. To make matters a little more complicated, we may remind our- 
selves in passing that muscle-contractions serve not only motility but also main- 
tenance of tone and temperature in the organism; sometimes they serve only the 
last function alone (in shivering) since muscle is a main source of animal heat. 

To p. 436. At the time of writing this theory still has certain difficulties to 
overcome; among them the fact that the energy supply of the fibre depends not 
only on ATP itself but also on creatin phosphate. 



Ill 



DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND 
REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 

Acting and Reacting 

The organism', to quote Coghill once more, 'acts on the en- 
vironment before it reacts to the environment.' This statement 
seems to apply to every level and every aspect of organic life. 
The lowliest creature and the highest, the moment it is hatched or 
born, lashes out at the environment, be it liquid or solid, with cilia, 
flagellae, or contractile muscle fibre; it crawls, swims, glides, pulsates; 
it kicks, yells, breathes, feeds, and sucks negative entropy from its 
surroundings for all its worth. 

The patterns of these built-in motor activities we saw to be to a 
large extent autonomous; 'the structure of the input does not produce 
the structure of the output, but merely modifies it.' Moreover, the 
input itselt is actively controlled and modified by the central nervous 
system from the moment it impinges on the peripheral receptor 
organs; and recent developments have caused, at least among an 
unorthodox minority of psychologists, a distinct 'shift from the notion 
that an organism is a relatively passive, protoplasmic mass whose res- 
ponses are controlled by the arrangement of environmental stimuli 
to a conception of an organism that has considerable control over what 
will constitute stimulation.' 1 

Even below the level of the single cell, organelles such as the mita- 
chondria and kinetosomes carry on their autonomous activities; their 
shadowy patterns under the electron-microscope are a reminder that 
the emergence of life means the emergence of spontaneous, organized 
exertion to maintain and reproduce originally unstable forms of 
equilibrium in a statistically improbable system in the teeth of an 
environment governed by the laws of probability. The live organism 
succeeds in this by creating an inner environment with which to 

447 



448 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



confront the outer environment — and in which the law of entropy 
seems to be reversed, biological clocks replace astronomical clocks, and 
hierarchic order reigns supreme. 

An organism is said to be well balanced' or 'well adapted' or 'in 
dynamic equilibrium' if it has established a modus vivendi between its 
internal and external environment. This, of course, is a more complex 
form of balance than mechanical or chemical equilibrium; it implies 
metabolic processes required for the maintenance of form and function 
in an open system in perpetual flux — Bertalanffy's (1941) Fliessgleich- 
gewicht; it implies self-regulating devices which keep irritability and 
motility within a safe standard range; and it also implies the slow, 
cyclic changes of morphogenesis, maturation, and reproduction, regu- 
lated by biological clocks. If all these processes are to be lumped to- 
gether under the portmanteau word 'adaptation', then we must call 
it adaptation of a special kind, on the organism's own terms; after all, 
the perfect adaptation of an organism to the temperature and chemistry 
of the environment is to die. In fact, the animal does not merely adapt 
to the environment, but constantly adapts the environment to itself. 
It eats environment, drinks environment, fights and mates environ- 
ment, burrows and builds in the environment; and even in observing 
environment, it modifies, dismantles, analyses, and reassembles it 
after its own fashion, converting 'noise' into 'information . 'Percep- 
tion', Woodworth wrote, 'is always driven by a direct, inherent motive 
which might be called "the will to perceive".' 

Thus the terms 'adaptation', 'environment', 'equilibrium' will be 
used in the following pages not in their usual passive connotations, but 
with active overtones, as it were. Instead of treating an animal as a 
'relatively passive, protoplasmic mass whose responses are controlled 
by the arrangement of environmental stimuli' — a Pavlov-dog in its 
restraining harness — we shall regard it as a relatively self-contained 
organism, deploying spontaneous activities simultaneously on various 
levels of its constituent functional hierarchies — activities which are 
triggered and modified, but not created by the environment. 

What is Equilibrium? 

An organism can be said to function normally so long as the stresses 
between internal and external milieu do not exceed a certain standard 
range. To simplify the argument, let the term 'internal milieu* em- 



DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 449 

brace all processes within the organism, and let us lump together the 
nature, intensity, and duration of environmental excitations in a single 
variable. We shall then be able to distinguish between (a) 'normal', 
(b) 'paranormal' or 'traumatic', and (c) destructive environmental 
conditions — though, needless to say, the boundaries between them 
cannot be sharply defined. 

The term 'dynamic equihbrium' shall apply only to a normal 
organism functioning under 'normal' conditions. Under these con- 
ditions the organ-systems, organs, and organ-parts of the animal per- 
form their specific, autonomous functions as sub-wholes, at the same 
time submitting to the regulative control imposed by the higher 
centres. The control is exercised by excitatory and inhibitory pro- 
cesses, but the latter play a vastly greater part. From the moment of 
conception, the genetic potentials of the individual cell are further 
restrained with every step in differentiation; and on every level of the 
growing and mature organism inhibitory blocks, negative feedbacks, 
growm-inhibiting hormones are at work. In the nervous system, 
in particular, there is censorship at every step — to prevent overloading 
of the information channels and overshooting of responses. Without 
this hierarchy of restraints, the organism would instandy blow its 
fuses in a kind of delirium agitans and then collapse. 

Under normal conditions the part will not tend to escape the res- 
training influence of the whole. Under paranormal conditions the 
balance is upset. Thus the term 'balance' or 'equmbrium* takes on a 
special meaning in the context of an organic hierarchy: it is not meant 
to refer to relations between parts on the same level of the hierarchy, 
but to the relation of a part to its controlling centre on the next higher level. 
The stresses arise not between inputs 'competing for the final common 
path,' as the expression goes, not between 'antagonistic drives' or 
'conflicting impulses' (which do not direcdy communicate with each 
other and cannot 'fight it out among themselves') — but between the 
excited part and the whole, whose attention it is trying to monopolize: 
in other words, between the self-assertive tendencies of the part and the 
restraints imposed by the controlling centre. Equilibrium is maintained in 
the organism by rules comparable to the procedure in a law court 
where the opposing parties address themselves not to each other, but 
to the judge. 

This interpretation of equilibrium in a hierarchy was suggested in 
my Insight and Outlook (p. 139 seq.), and independendy proposed by 
Tinbergen. In discussing the competition between various 'fixed 



450 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



response patterns' in innate behaviour, Tinbergen wrote: 'It should be 
emphasized that it is quite possible that these interconnections [between 
the competing centres] do not in reality run directly from one centre 
to the other, but go by way of the superordinated centre/ 2 Thorpe 
has expressed similar ideas. 3 

Super-Elasticity and Regenerative Span 

An organism lives by constant transactions with the environment. As 
a result, stresses are set up in the parts or organs which have been 
aroused to carry out the transaction. The excited part may tend to 
'get out of control', i.e. to assert its autonomy against the restraints 
imposed on it; it may tend to act to the detriment of the whole. In a 
normal' environment, these tensions between part and whole are of a 
transitory nature, and equilibrium is restored with the completion of 
the transaction. Under paranormal conditions — traumatic challenges — 
this is not the case, and only what one might call 'adaptations of the 
second order' can restore the balance. The animal's capacity to re- 
cover from such traumatic challenges is its regenerative potential. 

A stable, monotonous environment tends to produce stereotyped 
and automatized reaction-patterns. A variable environment calls for 
flexible strategies, for behavioural matrices with sufficient degrees of 
freedom to cope with the changing conditions. Paranormal challenges 
call for a kind of super-flexibility, for adaptations of a second order 
which enable the animal to carry out major reorganizations on several 
levels of its structural or functional hierarchies. The range of this 
ability constitutes the animal's 'regenerative span'. 

The regenerative span of a species thus provides it with an additional 
safety device in the service of survival, which enters into action when 
the limits of dynamic equilibrium are exceeded — as the shock-absorbers 
of a motor-car take over when the range of elasticity of the suspension 
springs is exceeded. But it is more than a safety device. Regeneration 
has been described as 'one of the more spectacular pieces of magic in 
the repertoire of living organisms'. 4 That may be the reason why it is 
so difficult to find a satisfactory definition which would embrace the 
whole range of phenomena to which the term is applied. 

These include (a) the replication of entire individuals by asexual re- 
production (fission and budding); (b) the reconstitution of a whole 
organism from its brokqn-up fragments, or from a single fragment. 



DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 451 

Sponges and hydra can be disintegrated into small clumps or even 
single cells by forcing them through a fine filter mesh, yet will re- 
organize themselves into normal, complete individuals. A single 
tentacle of a sweet-water polyp is capable of regenerating a complete 
individual; and transverse slices of a flatworm, taken from any part of 
its body, will regenerate the whole animal — including, brains, eyes, 
genitalia, and other complex organs which the segment did not contain, 
(c) Among the higher animals, crustaceans are capable of regenerating 
single organs exposed to accidental damage (antennae, stalk-eyes, etc.); 
among vertebrates, salamanders and newts are capable of regenerating 
limbs, eyes, tails, and some inner organs (lungs and gonads); the pro- 
cess in these cases follows closely the processes of embryonic develop- 
ment, (d) Equipped with high regenerative powers, some animals 
practise autotomy — the self-amputation of an exposed structure in 
the grasp of an enemy, which is subsequently replaced. Lizards let go 
of their tails; crabs, insects, and spiders of their legs or antennae, star- 
fish cast off an arm. Self-amputation is facilitated by a 'breaking plane* 
of weakened structure somewhere near the base of the expendable 
appendage — rather like the perforations between stamps, (e) Among 
mammalia, regeneration is generally limited to the repair of damaged 
bone, muscle, skin, and peripheral nerves, (f) Lastly, the term 'physi- 
ological regeneration is used for the routine replacement of tissues 
used up by ordinary wear and tear. 

Thus regeneration appears to serve two different functions: on the 
one hand normal, asexual reproduction, on the other, the restoration 
of organs and structures lost by accidental mutilation or by wear and 
tear. But the two functions are in fact continuous; they shade into 
each other, and are often undistinguishable. If a flatworm spon- 
taneously sheds its tail, then grows a new tail and the shed tail grows a 
new head, this is called asexual reproduction; if it is sliced into two in 
the laboratory it is called regeneration; and the same goes for budding, 
which is the natural way of reproduction of some marine coelen- 
terates, but can be artificially induced by laceration of the body wall. 
The 'regenerative field* in the salamander's amputated leg-stump 
obeys the same type of code as the morphogenetic field of embryonic 
primordia. And vice versa: the development of twins or triplets 
following accidental fragmentation might as well be called a regenera- 
tive process. Hence, ontogenesis may be described as the regeneration 
of a complete individual from a fragment specially set aside for that 
purpose. But this 'setting apart' of undifferentiated embryonic cells 



452 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



which 'specialize in non-specialization occurs in regenerative pro- 
cesses too — for instance, in annelids, hydra, and natworms, which store 
'reserve cells' or 'regeneration cells' in various parts of their bodies 
and mobilize them when the need arises. Sexual reproduction thus 
appears merely as an added twist to asexual regeneration— though a 
twist with momentous consequences. Instead of replicating a single 
genetic code ad infinitum, the bisociation of two genetic codes is the 
basic model of the creative act. 

Although closely related species on the same level of the evolu- 
tionary hierarchy may differ widely in their regenerative power, it is 
nevertheless true that, in a general way, this power decreases as we 
proceed from lower to higher organisms. The essence of organic 
regeneration is a release of genetic cell potentials which are normally 
inhibited in adult tissue. 



Physiological Isolation 

These genetic potentials are the residues of the cell's erstwhile toti- 
potentiality before differentiation set in — its original power to create 
a whole new organism. Some of that power is reactivated when the 
regeneration tissue — the part designed to replace the lost organ or 
limb — is released from the controls which under normal conditions 
keep it under restraint. For this partial or total secession of the part 
from the whole, C. M. Child coined the useful concept of physio- 
logical isolation. 5 

Physiological isolation may be regarded as a drastic form of dis- 
equilibrium between the part and the whole. Its consequences may be 
beneficial or deleterious. Child distinguishes four causes for it. (a) 
Growth of the whole beyond a critical limit may make it ungovern- 
able so that parts of it find themselves outside the range of central 
dominance and control. This may lead in lower organisms to re- 
production by fission or budding: the isolated part is either shed (as, 
for instance, the planarians tail) to form a new organism, or it may 
de-differentiate and reintegrate into a complete organism by budding, 
(b) Decline of the organism's powers of control (through senescence, 
metabolic or hormonal disorders) may, in combination with other 
causes, lead to a pathological regression of cells and tissues with un- 
tramelled proliferation and without reintegration, resulting in malig- 
nant growths, (c) Partial obstruction or total blockage of (nervous and 



DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 453 

chemical) communications, and (d) persistent local excitation beyond 
a critical limit, may release the part from its normal controls and 
activate, for better or worse, its latent potentialities. 

"We shall see that Child's 'isolation* concept has a wide range of 
applicability. In all cases, isolation of the part from the whole leads to 
de-differentiation or other forms of regression; in some cases this is 
followed by re-differentiation and reintegration. Isolation leading to 
regression of an irreversible kind plays a considerable part in pathology, 
psycho-pathology, and social pathology.* On the other hand, re- 
gression followed by a progressive rebound releases creative potentials 
which are normally under restraint. Its magic can be observed on every 
level: from asexual reproduction to the repair of structural damage 
and functional disorder, and further up to psychotherapy, scientific 
discovery, and artistic creation. In the chapter which follows I shall 
briefly discuss the manifestations of 'super-flexibility' — of recukr pour 
mieux sauter — on these various levels. 

NOTE 

To p. 455. Thus, for instance, Smithers in A Clinical Prospect of the Cancer 
Problem (i960) stresses the decisive influence which Child's Physiological Founda- 
tions of Behaviour had on the development of his ideas. 



IV 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 
Structural Regenerations 

In primitive organisms such as the flatworm, and in the early em- 
bryonic stages of higher organisms, a physiologically isolated part 
tends in general 'to lose its characteristics as a part and to become or 
approach the condition of a new whole individual'. 1 Liberation of the 
part's previously restrained genetic potential 'involves a change in 
behaviour and structure from that of a part towards that of a whole 
organism'. 2 Such organisms could be said to live not only in dynamic 
equilibrium with their environment, but in a kind of 'regenerative 
equilibrium' which enables them to rise to virtually any challenge by 
means of these secondary adaptations. 

Some higher animals are still capable of regenerating lost organs or 
limbs. Let us have a closer look how it is done. When a salamander's 
leg has been amputated, the tissues near the wound surface de-differen- 
tiate and the cells acquire an embryonic appearance. This is the regres- 
sive or 'catabolic' phase. Around the fourth day begins the formation 
of the blastema — the regeneration bud; and from here on throughout 
the 'anabolic' or synthetic phase the process follows closely the forma- 
tion of limbs in normal embryonic development.* The blastema 
elongates into a cone and develops axially, the toes at its tip appearing 
first, and the rest of the limb gradually taking shape as it grows in 
length. When the organ is completed, central control is taken over 
by the nervous system, just as in the case of the embryo. The nervous 
system, however, also plays an indispensable part in initiating the first, 
catabolic phase. If no peripheral nerves are present in the amputation 
stump, regeneration does not occur.** 

The 'isolated part* in this case is the amputation stump. The blastema 
has in the beginning the multi-potential characteristics of the organ 
primordia, and its re-diflferentiation again proceeds stepwise: if the 

454 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 



455 



field is split in half, each half gives rise to a whole organ; if one half is 
removed, the remaining half will still develop into a complete limb. 

Although the isolated part, transformed into a new organ primor- 
dium (or its close equivalent), enjoys a high degree of independence 
and controls the formation of the new limb, its ties with the higher 
levels of the hierarchy are not completely severed. Its function in the 
whole has changed; its normal controls (through the nervous system 
and local chemical gradients) are out of action or even reversed; but 
the organism as a whole nevertheless assists the regenerating part by 
certain emergency measures — a 'general alarm reaction* followed by a 
'general adaptation syndrome', each stage indicated by metabolic 
changes and by the appearance of specific proteins and hormones in the 
circulatory system. 

Thus the isolation of the part is only temporary and relative; and 
when the process is completed, the regenerated limb assumes its 
normal function in the whole. The entire regressive-progressive 
sequence is the means by which the animal's 'regenerative equiHbrium' 
enables it to adjust to traumatic experiences from the environment. 

Looked at from a different angle, one might say that the whole 
process is designed to prevent or correct malformations, i.e. faulty 
integrations. Without the initial nerve supply, the regressing am- 
putation stump would be resorbed, the scar tissue would close over 
it, and the animal would achieve a modus uivendi as a cripple — a faulty 
integration. On the other hand, a frog which will not normally re- 
generate a lost limb will do so if the nerve supply to the stump is 
artificially augmented, providing the initial stimulus to start the pro* 
cess. Traumatic challenges can only be met by the liberation of the 
organism's latent powers — a temporary return to a more youthful or 
primitive condition. 

Reversed Gradients 

An important part in regeneration, as in morphogenesis, is played by 
axial gradients. The apical or 'head* end of the fertilized egg, the 
growing embryo, or the regenerating limb, are exposed to the highest 
degree of stimulation and show the highest rate of metabolism, pro- 
tein synthesis, and RNA activity. Thus the anterior end becomes the 
dominant region, the 'head* in the literal and metaphorical sense, and 
exercises a restraining influence on the genetic potentials along the 
axial gradient— so that activity is highest at the front and lowest at the 



45<* 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



tail end (higher organisms have of course a complex pattern of inter- 
acting gradients, some axial, some radial). But physical isolation by 
blockage or hyper-excitation (Child's third and fourth cause) of parts 
in previously subordinate positions can be shown to alter or reverse the 
gradient. In plants, where the dominant region is the growing tip of 
die shoot, pruning makes previously subordinate parts burst into 
activity. If in the marine polyp, tubularia, a piece of the stem is cut out, 
the frontal end of the fragment will normally regenerate the hydrant 
which is its 'head'; but if a ligature is applied to isolate the front end 
of the fragment, the gradient is reversed and the tail end, now the region, 
of maximum excitation, becomes dominant and grows a head. 
Similarly, short pieces of planaria sometimes regenerate one head at 
the front and another at tie tail end, if the metabolism of both cut 
surfaces is equally high. 



The Dangers of Regression 

Two more phenomena must be mentioned in this context: the first 
illustrates the flexibility, the second the vulnerability of regenerative 
processes. 

If the crystalline lens of a salamander-eye is removed, part of the 
iris de-differentiates, forms a vesicle, enters the cavity through the 
pupil, re-differentiates, and forms a normal lens— whereas in embryonic 
development the lens is formed by the epidermis overlaying the eye- 
cup, without participation of the iris. Thus the morphogenetic skill of 
making a lens can make use of either of two different materials; the 
code is again invariant, the strategy adaptable.* 

On the other hand, the factors which, in a higher organism, deter- 
mine whether a given trauma will lead to regenerative or pathological 
changes are of an extremely delicate nature. Thus Smithers 8 writes: 

'The type of structure regenerated, or the kind of neoplasm formed, 
will depend on the level of the controlling field-gradient against which 
it is exerting itself, and the steepness of the gradient it can itself es- 
tablish and promote as shown by its tendency towards undifferentiated 
cell-reproduction. The part which is physiologically isolated then 
produces an imperfect portion of a new whole, giving rise to whatever 
tissues it is capable of forming under the circumstances pertaining. 
This may result in malformations of all degrees, from simple over- 
growth of adult tissues, through irregular mixtures of recognizable, 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 



457 



well-differentiated cells, to the most rapidly growing, undifferentiated 
tumours/ 

Pathogenic regulatory responses are reactions to stimulations which 
are 'outside the standardized range of normal experience of the species 
during its developmental peak period. They do not differ from the 
normal regulatory responses, however, in any fundamental particular. 
. . . Tissue overgrowth as a response to a long-continued external 
irritant, is of the same order as heat regulation, wound-healing or 
lactation. . . . Useless or harmful regulating mechanisms and tissue 
responses to isolation, injury, or stimulation are not fundamentally 
different in kind from those favourable ones which have become in- 
corporated into the inheritance of the species because they promoted 

survival through the period of reproductive activity The tissues 

most often called on for regeneration and repair, or most liable to re- 
current stimulation into specialized activity, are those most prone to 
tumour formation.' 4 

'Routine Regenerations' 

The last sentence that I have quoted leads into the borderland between 
regenerative and 'normal' processes: namely routine replacements. 
They range from the periodic moulting of feathers and shedding of the 
antlers, to the replacement of the whole human epidermis about once 
a month owing to wear and tear, and the replacement of red blood 
cells at the rate of 3 X io 11 per day; not to mention the metabolic turn- 
over on die molecular level which consumes about thirty per cent of 
our total protein intake. This type of routine (or so-called 'physio- 
logical') regeneration which goes on all the time is sometimes described 
as a constant 'renewal' or 'rejuvenation' of the body. It is often im- 
possible to make a clear distinction between 'wear' and 'tear' — for 
instance in minor abrasions of the skin. The differential factor is 
obviously the degree of stress, which, past a critical threshold, will 
bring general alarm reactions and 'adaptations of the second order' 
into play. 

Reorganizations of Function 

The transplanted salamander limb which functions normally in spite 
of its randomized nervous connections can be regarded as an example 
of both regeneration of structure and reorganization of function. The 



458 THE ACT OF CREATION 

pathways leading into the limb all seem to be equipotential in their 
capacity as conductors of the excitation-clang. Without entering the 
old controversy about equipotentiality versus localization of func- 
tions in nervous tissues, it seems to be safe to say that in repetitive 
routines and local reflexes, equipotentiality has 'frozen up' into fixed 
local arrangements; whereas in case of injury to the pathways in 
question, the equipotentiality (or rather, multi-potentiality) of alter- 
native canal-systems' is revived, and they take over the function of 
the injured system. To quote Lashley: 'The results indicate that when 
habitually used motor organs are rendered non-functional by removal 
or paralysis, there is an immediate, spontaneous use of other motor 
systems which had not previously been associated with, or used in, the 
performance of the activity/ 5 Nearly a century earlier Pfliiger had 
shown that even the spinal reflexes of a frog are capable of 'crisis 
adaptations'. If a drop of acid is placed on the back of the left front 
limb of a decapitated frog, it will attempt to wipe it away with the left 
hind limb; but if prevented from doing so it will use the right hind 
limb — which it normally never does in the exercise of the wiping 
reflex. 

Turning from the spinal level to the brain, Lashley's celebrated maze 
experiments have shown what astonishing regenerative adaptations the 
cerebral cortex is capable of. If a rat is trained to choose between 
two doors the one where a brighter light is shown, this habit (or at 
least part of it) must be localized in its optical cortex, for if this is 
extirpated, the habit is lost. But a rat with its optical cortex cut out 
can still be taught or re-taught the same skill. This means that some 
other cortical area has taken over the learning function after extirpation 
of the proper area—just as in the morphogenetic field intact tissue will 
deputize for lost tissue. Moreover, if a rat has learned to run a certain 
maze, no matter what parts of its motor cortex are injured, it will 
follow its path — even if it has to roll the whole way with paralysed 
legs; and if the injury makes it incapable of executing a right turn, it 
will achieve its aim by a three-quarter turn to the left. The rat may be 
blinded, deprived of its smell, partially paralysed in various ways — 
each of which would throw the chain-reflex automation, which the 
rat was supposed to be, completely out of gear. Yet: 'One drags him- 
self through [the maze] with his forepaws; another falls at every step 
but gets through by a series of lunges; a third rolls over completely 
in making each turn, yet avoids rolling into a cul-de-sac and makes an 
errorless run. The behaviour presents exactly the same problem of 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 



459 



direct adaptation of any motor organs to the attainment of a given end 
which was outstanding in my earlier observations on monkeys after 
destruction of the pre-central gyri. If the customary sequence of move- 
ments employed in reaching the food is rendered impossible, another 
set, not previously used in the* habit, and constituting an entirely 
different motor pattern, may be directly and efficiently substituted 
without any random activity/ 6 

In human beings, structural regeneration — of skin, bone, muscle, and 
peripheral nerves — is confined to tissue-outgrowth: that is to say, the 
new structures are derived from cells of their own kind, not from de- 
differentiating tissues. But though we have lost the amphibian's 
enviable powers of replacing a lost limb, we have gained a unique 
super-flexibility of functions in our nervous system. 

On its lowest level it is manifested in certain secondary or crisis- 
adaptations of neuro-muscular mechanisms. The artificial limbs in- 
vented by the Austrian surgeon Sauerbruch are flexed by muscles in 
the stump which formerly acted as extensors, and extended by flexors. 7 
Other reversals of function are obtained by grafting operations. When 
the musculo-spiral nerve which activates the extensors of wrist and 
fingers is severed with resulting paralysis, the damage can be re- 
paired by grafting one of the flexor-tendons from the inner side of 
the wrist on to the extensor-muscle. After a while the flexor will depu- 
tize for his former antagonist, although it remains attached to the 
'wrong' (median) nerve — which thus carries opposite orders to the 
remaining flexors and to the transplanted one, along the same common 
path* 8 

In these and similar grafting operations the first step is the undoing 
of a fixed neuro-muscular connection; thereby the nerve to be grafted 
becomes 'de-specialized' as it were — the functional analogue to the de- 
difTerentiation of structures — and regains its multi-potentiality to 
function in more than one way. The second step, when the grafting 
operation is completed, is 're-specialization of the nerve in its new 
role, and the reintegration of the new neuro-muscular unit into the 
whole. Similar considerations apply to Lashley's rats or Bethe's insects 
— except, of course, that in their case, the reorganization of functions 
is spontaneous. 

Thus there is a close parallel between the regeneration of structures 
and the reorganization of functions after traumatic challenges; and 
both are continuous with the regulative principle in morphogenesis. 
The antithesis between localization of functions, fixed pathways' on 



460 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the one hand, and 'mulitpotential pathways, selective responses' on 
the other, reflects the earlier antithesis between the mosaic character 
and the regulative character in embryonic development. But the 
seemingly opposite principles turn out to be in fact complementary 
aspects of development. "With each successive step in the differentiation 
of the embryo, of the nervous system, and of adult behaviour-patterns, 
the regulative powers decrease, and the mosaic-character of structures 
and functions increases: tissues become specialized, responses localized, 
habits automatized — up to a point. For all matrices of structure and 
behaviour display varying amounts of flexibility even while the 
organism lives in dynamic equilibrium with its environment; but the 
often unsuspected amount of its regenerative potential becomes only 
manifest when a severe challenge induces it to retrace its steps on the 
genetic gradient, as it were, and make a fresh start. 



Recuter sans Sauter 

Hyper-excited organs or organ-systems tend to get out of control. 
During the repair of physical injuries, the injured part tends to monopo- 
lize the attention of the whole organism; in periods of starvation, the 
digestive system asserts itself to the detriment of other parts; in rage 
and panic, the sympathico-adrenal apparatus tyrannizes the whole; and 
when sex is aroused, reason (as the Austrian proverb has it) descends 
into the testes'. The over-excited part behaves as if it were in a tem- 
porary state of 'physiological isolation' (pp. 452 £), released from its 
restraints; it asserts its autonomy and sometimes tends to usurp the 
functions of the whole. 

Analogous situations occur on the cognitive level, where the 'hyper- 
excited part' appears in the guise of the idiejixe, or a closed system' of 
beliefs. Both the achievements and aberrations of human thought are to a 
large extent due to obsessionalpreoccupations withreligious and scientific 
theories, or political ideologies, more or less closely knitted around some 
central idea, around a part-truth usurping the role of the whole truth. 

We have seen in the previous volume how an obsessional pre- 
occupation can force the whole mental organization into its service 
during the period of incubation, and give birth to a new system of 
thought. But these are the glorious exceptions; in the vast majority of 
cases, the 'over-valued idea' (to use Kretschmer's 9 term) will become 
segregated from the rest of the mental field, and assert itself in harm- 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 



461 



ful ways. The results are all too familiar: personalities whose whole 
outlook is dominated by prejudice and biassed values; the compulsive 
rituals of neurotics; the devouring obsession of the crank; and so on 
to the major psychoses in which large chunks of the personality have 
been 'split off' and become permanendy isolated from the rest. The 
intrusion of magic causation; inability to distinguish between fact and 
fantasy; delusions of grandeur, or persecution by invisible powers, are 
symptoms of regression to earlier levels, of the de-differentiation of 
thought-matrices — of reenter sans sauter. 

Regeneration and Psychotherapy 

Less extreme cases are neurotics who react to their traumatic experiences 
by elaborating defence systems which enable them to find some kind of 
modus vivendi with the world. One may call such behaviour-patterns 
'faulty integrations' — like the newt's whose forelegs move back- 
wards. Psychotherapy aims at undoing faulty integrations by inducing 
a temporary regression of the patient to an earlier level, in the hope 
that he will eventually reintegrate into a more stable pattern. Neuro- 
surgery, shock-therapy, and related methods aim at releasing philo- 
genetically older centres of the brain from cortical restraints. In a less 
drastic form, Freudians, Jungians, etc., try to make the patient revert 
to unconscious and infantile planes of experience, and to regenerate, 
as it were, into a more or less new-born person. 

Thus psychotherapy may be called an experiment in artificially in- 
duced regeneration. It relies on the same basic process of reader pour 
mieux sauter \ which we see operating on every level: from the flatworm 
which replaces a lost head, through the crab which adjusts its gait to 
the loss of a leg, to the rat which, unable to turn to the right, makes a 
three-quarter turn to the left. We found the same pattern repeated on 
the level of human creativity: the scientist, faced by a perplexing situa- 
tion — Kepler's discrepant eight minutes' arc, Einstein's light-traveller 
, paradox — must plunge into a 'dark night of the soul' before he can re- 
emerge into the light. The history of the sciences and arts is a tale of 
recurrent crises, of traumatic challenges, which entail a temporary 
disintegration of the traditional forms of reasoning and perception: a 
de-differentiation of thought-matrices, a dismantling of its axioms, a 
new innocence of the eye; followed by the liberation from restraint 
of creative potentials, and their reintegration in a new synthesis. 



The Routine of Dreaming 



There is also a mental equivalent for the less spectacular routine re- 
generation of tissues, designed to compensate for wear and tear. The 
analogue process is the maintenance of mental tissues' exposed to the 
wear and tear of diurnal stresses, by the regenerative effect of nocturnal 
regressions to me primitive levels of the dream. Experimental evidence 
seems to indicate that the restorative powers of sleep are primarily 
derived from the process of dreaming. Experimental subjects who were 
woken up each time their EEG waves indicated the onset of dreaming, 
displayed symptoms of fatigue and nervous disorder; long periods of 
dreamless sleep could not compensate for dream-deprivation. 'Man 
cannot persist long in a conscious state/ wrote Goethe, 'he must throw 
himself back into the unconscious, for his root lives there/ 

We have seen (Book One, VII, VIII) that these periodic plunges 
into the unconscious are accompanied by the temporary disintegra- 
tion of matrices of logical thought. But they also entail a partial loss 
of identity, a de-differentiation of the personality — as indicated by the 
remarkable degree of uniformity in the contents of dreams shared by 
people of very different character, and by the relatedness of these 
contents to mythological themes and symbols. These shared patterns 
led Jung to postulate a 'collective' — that is, individually undifferen- 
tiated— level of the unconscious. On that level, members of the same 
culture seem to share some degree of psychic equipotentiality ex- 
pressed in 'archetypal symbols'. These are supposed to be condensa- 
tions of basic experiences of the race in the distant past; hence their 
great emotion-rousing potential. 

To recapitulate: the fact that art and discovery draw on uncon- 
scious sources indicates that one aspect of all creative activity is a 
regression to ontogenetically or philogenetically earlier levels, an 
escape from the restraints of the conscious mind, with the subsequent 
release of creative potentials— a process paralleled on lower levels by 
the liberation from restraint of genetic potentials or neural equi- 
potentialiry in the regeneration of structures and functions. The 
scientist, traumatized by discordant facts, the artist by the pressures of 
sensibility, and the rat by surgical intervention, share, on different 
levels, the same super-flexibility enabling them to perform 'adapta- 
tions of a second order', rarely found in the ordinary routines of life. 



462 



Regeneration and Creativity 



I must enlarge a little on this seemingly sweeping analogy, and try to 
show that it is in fact based on homologous principles, traceable on all 
levels of the hierarchy, and preserving their basic pattern throughout 
them. 

Differentiation and specialization of the parts are necessary for the 
normal functioning of lie whole; abnormal conditions call for radical 
measures which may include a retreat of the over-exerted part to a 
structurally less differentiated, functionally less specialized stage, if 
the whole is to survive. The part* may be the newt's amputation 
stump, or the unsolved problem in the scientist's mind which tortures 
and obsesses him. We have seen that such regressions are mostly patho- 
genic, but under favourable conditions they may redress the situation 
by re-activating potentials which had been operative in the past but 
are inhibited in the adult — such as the regulative powers of the embryo 
in the womb or the undifferentiated total-pattern-responses of its 
nervous system. The period of incubation is a similar retreat, if not 
into the womb, at least into long-outgrown forms of ideation, into the 
pre-verbal, pre-rational games of the unconscious, the wonderland- 
logic of the dream. The challenge which sets the process going is in 
all cases a traumatic experience: physical mutilation or mental lacera- 
tion — by data which do not fit, observations which contradict each 
other, emotions which disrupt approved styles in art: experiences 
which create mental conflict, dissonance, perplexity. The creative 
stress' of the artist or scientist corresponds to the 'general alarm re- 
action' of the traumatized animal; the anabolic-catabolic sequence of 
de-differentiation and reintegration corresponds to the destructive- 
constructive sequence in the creative act. The 'physiological isolation 
of the over-excited part which tends to dominate, corresponds to the 
smgle-minded and obsessive preoccupation with the idee fixe — 
Kretschmer's 'over-valued idea', Kepler's pursuit of a chimera — which 
monopolizes the whole mind; it will either lead to its reorganization 
by giving birth to a new system, or to the cancerous proliferation of a 
degenerate tissue of ideas. 

Over-excitation of an organ or part is one of the four causes of 
'physiological isolation'. The other three were: growth of the whole 
beyond a critical limit; senescence; and (partial) blockage of com- 
munication (pp. 452 f.). Each situation has its parallels on the mental 
plane — of the individual, or the history of thought. The unmanageable 

463 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



size of the total body of human knowledge — or even a single province 
thereof— created that dissociated phenomenon, the specialist mind; 
senescent cultures produce degenerate art-forms; blocked communica- 
tions between Ptolemaic astronomy and the main body of the physical 
sciences led to the untramelled proliferation of epicycles in a closed 
system, divorced from reality. 

'It is wonderful to see how analogies can blossom when they are 
given a little affection', wrote the authors of a book I have repeatedly 
quoted. 10 Particularly, one might add, if they have solid roots in the 
earth. So let me carry analogy one step further. In Book One (Chapters 
V-VHI) I have described various aspects of the Eureka process; each of 
these re-structurings of thought has its obvious correlate in regenera- 
tive processes on lower levels. The 'displacement of emphasis' to a 
previously irrelevant part or aspect of experience corresponds to the 
sudden dominance of a hitherto subordinate part of an organism — 
such as the crab's second leg which becomes a pacemaker. The reversal 
of logic' (or of the figure-background relation) has its parallel in the 
reversal of physiological gradients during regeneration. When psycho- 
logical textbooks describe Duncker's experiments as 'detaching' part 
of a visual percept from the context in which it is 'embedded', and 
'attaching' it to the new context of the problem to be solved (pp 1 89 f.) 
this description itself is based on analogies from physiological pro- 
cesses. During incubation, the intuitive groping of ideas towards the 
'good combination, and their guidance by 'gradients in the un- 
conscious', reminds one of the biochemical gradients in morpho- 
genesis, or the 'contact-guidance' of out-growing nerve-processes 
towards their end-organ. Lasdy a 'nascent', unverbaHzed analogy may 
be compared to an unarticulated organ-primordium. 

But these genetic skills operate only in the embryonic stage of 
development; in the adult they are superseded by the integrative 
action of the nervous system — unless the embryonic potentials are re- 
activated by regenerative needs. Similarly, the adult's mental co- 
ordination relies on conscious, verbalized, 'logical' codes; not on the 
quasi 'embryonic' (infantile, pre-causal) potentials of the unconscious; 
again unless these are revived under the creative stress. Physical re- 
generations strike us as 'spectacular pieces of magic' because they 
derive from pre-natal skills; and creative inspirations are equally 
mysterious because they derive from levels which predate the 
conscious mind. As Polanyi wrote (in a different context): 'The 
highest forms of originality are far more closely akin to the 



RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER 46$ 

lowest biotic performances than the external circumstances would 
indicate.' 11 

Regeneration and Evolution 







A | 


1 

I 




B 






( diffcrtrUuitioru ^ 


R- 


/ specialised rvtttme 



Figure 14 

These rather fancy diagrams are solely meant to indicate in a crude way 
the complementary factors in the reculerpour mieux sauter phenomenon. 
In A, increase in tissue-differentiation entails a reciprocal decrease of 
genetic multipotentiality. In B, an analogous reciprocity prevails 
between unconscious intuitions and automatized routines — or, if you 
like, between fluid imagery and 'misplaced concreteness'. R indicates 
the 'regenerative span'. (The curve in A should of course have breaks 
and a series of discrete steps.) 

It could be objected that structural regenerations merely restore the 
status quo ante whereas mental reorganization leads to an advance. But 
in the first place this is not always the case. Psychotherapy aims at 
correcting 'faulty integrations' caused by traumatic experiences — at 
restoring normality. In the second place the biological evolution of 
the species with which we are concerned has to all intents and purposes 
come to a standstill, whereas mental evolution continues, and its 
vehicle is precisely the creative individual. The Eureka process is a 
mental mutation, perpetuated by social inheritance. Its biological 
equivalent are the genetic mutations which carried the existing species 
up the evolutionary ladder. Now a mutation — whatever its unknown 



466 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



cause — i s n0 doubt a re-moulding of previous structures, based on a 
de-diiFerentiation and reintegration of the otherwise rigid genetic 
code. The transformations of fins into legs, legs into arms, arms into 
wings, gills into lungs, scales into feathers, etc., while preserving certain 
basic structural patterns (see, for instance, d'Arcy Thompson's On 
Growth and Form) were eminently 'witty* answers to the challenges of 
environment. It seems obvious that the dramatic release, at periods of 
adaptative radiations, of unexplored morphogenetic potentials by a 
re-shufHing of molecules in the genetic code, resulting in the de-dif- 
ferentiation and reintegration of structures like limbs into wings, is 
of the very essence of the evolutionary process. After all, 'ontogenesis 
and regenesis are components of a common mechanism', 12 which 
must have a phylogenetic origin. 

In Book One, Chapter XX, I have mentioned the perennial myth of 
the prophet's and hero's temporary isolation and retreat from human 
society— followed by his triumphant return endowed with new powers. 
Buddha and Mohamed go out into the desert; Joseph is thrown into 
the well; Jesus is resurrected from the tomb. Jung's 'death and re- 
birth' motif, Toynbee's 'withdrawal and return' reflect the same 
archetypal motif. It seems that reader pour mieux sauter is a principle of 
universal validity in the evolution of species, cultures, and individuals, 
guiding their progression by feedback from the past. 

NOTES 

To p. 454. It is still an open question, however, whether or how much 
undifferentiated 'reserve cells' (as in lower animals) contribute material to the 
blastema. 

To p. 454. It seems that the initial role of the nervous system is to determine 
the main axis of the regenerate — that it acts, not as an inductor, but as a trophic 
agent. At the later, anabolic stages of the process no nerve supply is needed — as 
denervation experiments show. 

To p. 4$6, This, actually, is the only clearly demonstrated case of metaplasia 
among higher animals. 

To p. 45g. About the ways how this is achieved, cf. McCuIloch in the 
Hixon Symposium, p. 56. 



V 

PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION 



Before we turn to adult behaviour, a pause for stocktaking may 
, be in order. 
In a four-dimensional continuum, embryonic development 
would be represented by an ascending hierarchy of spatial levels per- 
pendicular to the time axis. In spite of the perplexing diversity of 
phenomena on different levels — cleavage, gastrulation, induction, 
neuro-genesis — certain basic principles were seen to operate on every 
level throughout the hierarchy. Principles (or 'laws of nature') can 
only be described in symbolic language of one kind or another. The 
language used in the present theory is based on four key-concepts: 
motivation, code, matrix, and environment. Since these are assumed to 
operate in a hierarchic framework, the dichotomy of self-asserting and 
participatory tendencies of behaviour on all levels need not be separately 
postulated, but derives logically, as it were, from the dual character 
of every sub-whole as a subordinate and supra-ordinate entity. 
Let me now recapitulate some of the main points which have 
emerged from the previous chapters, taken in conjunction with 
Book One: 

1. Motivation in embryonic development is a subject for the meta- 
physician. J. Needham's tongue-in-the-cheek phrase about 'the 
striving of the blastula to grow into a chicken indicates the directive- 
ness of the morphogenetic process and its equifinal, regulative proper- 
ties, which become particularly evident under adverse conditions. 
These properties represent the genetic precursors of the motivational 
drives, needs, and goal-directedness of the adult animal; during matura- 
tion, the former shade into the latter, and there is no sharp dividing line 
between them. 

2. 'A part is a whole is a part*. Each sub-whole is both a 'sub' and a 

467 



468 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



'whole*. Facing downward or outward in the hierarchy, it behaves as 
an autonomous whole; facing upward or inward, it behaves as a 
dependent part which is inhibited or triggered into action by higher 
controls. One might call this the 'Janus principle' in organic (and 
social) hierarchies. 

3. The 'whole-aspect of the sub-whole is manifested in its auto- 
nomous and spontaneous activities. The principle of autonomy is asserted 
on every level; from cell-organelles functioning as power plants or 
motor units, through the self-differentiating activities of the morpho- 
genetic field, to the autonomous regulations of organs and organ 
system. In the motor hierarchy, it is reflected at every stage, from the 
muscle's selective response to specific excitation-patterns, through the 
stubborn behaviour of the reversed newt limb, to the unalterable 
features in a persons gait or handwriting. I have briefly mentioned 
(Book One, Chapters XIII, XXI), and shall discuss in more detail later, 
autonomous mechanism in perceptual organization — visual constancies, 
the automatic filtering, analysing, generalizing of the input. Lastly, 
thinking and communicating are based on hierarchically ordered, 
autonomous patterns of enunciation, grammar, logic, mathematical 
operations, universes of discourse. 

The dynamic aspect of the part's autonomy is manifested in its 
apparently spontaneous, unprovoked rhythmic activities which are 
'modified but not created by the environmental input' — a statement 
which equally applies to morphogenesis, to intrinsic motor patterns, 
to the spontaneous discharges of unstimulated sensory receptors, the 
electric pulses of the unstimulated brain, to drives in the absence of 
external stimuli or to communications addressed to imaginary 
audiences. 

Autonomy and spontaneity taken together constitute what I have 
called the 'self-assertive' aspect of part-behaviour. 

4. The opposite aspect is the part's dependence on supra-ordinate 
controls which may be said to represent the interests of the whole 
vis-h-vis the part in question. The controls are largely of an inhibitory 
or restraining character, to prevent overloading of information 
channels, over-shooting of responses, confusion and redundancy in 
general; while the activation of the part ii effected by signals of the 
trigger-release type. During morphogenesis, control is exercised by 
the suppression of unrequired, and the release of required genetic 
potentials; in the mature organism by interlacing multiple hierarchies 
of nervous and circulatory processes, and biochemical gradients. 



PRINCIPLES OP ORGANIZATION 



469 



5. Sub-wholes on any level of the hierarchy function (a) auto- 
nomously in supra-ordination to their own parts, (b) in sub-ordination 
to their controlling agency, and (c) in co-ordination with their en- 
vironment. 

'Environment' is a relative term. On the level of the single cell, the 
environment of the nucleus is cytoplasm; on the level of the morpho- 
genetic field, the environment of one cell-population is another cell- 
population; each organ in the adult animal is bathed in body-fluids 
which constitute its environment. The structure and function of any 
sub-whole is determined by (a) and (b) — its intrinsic pattern and its 
controls in the Vertical' hierarchy to which it belongs; but it is also 
affected by inputs and feedbacks from its 'horizontal' environment, 
as it were — the lie of the land. The difference between (a) and (b) 
on the one hand, and (c) on the other is that the former determine the 
invariant pattern of the operation, (c) only its variable details. To 
mention a few examples: feedback from the cytoplasm to the genetic 
blue-print co-determines into which variety of specialized cell that par- 
ticular unit will develop; but it does not alter the blue-print itself. 
Inductor substances in the immediate environment of a tissue will pro- 
mote its differentiation into an organ — but only within the limits of 
the tissue's 'competence'. Environmental hazards decide the neuro- 
muscular connections in the grafted salamander-limb, but its func- 
tional co-ordination remains unaffected by it: it is controlled by its 
'vertical* hierarchy, and the lie of the land in the scar-tissue determines 
only the local 'tactics' of the outgrowing nerve-filaments. 

Thus the function of every component in the organism is determined 
by two types of 'input'. The first consists of specific trigger signals 
from its superior controls in the hierarchy; the second are inputs and 
feedbacks from more or less random events in its environment. But 
I must stress again that the meaning of the word 'environment* depends 
on the hierarchic level to which it is applied. The environment of John 
driving his car is the traffic stream around him. The environment of 
John's right foot is the brake-pedal on which it rests. Let us call the 
former an environment on the t-level, where t stands for the top of the 
hierarchy controlling the various sensory, motor, and cognitive pro- 
cesses which constitute the skill of driving; then the brake-pedal will 
be an environment on the, say, t minus 4 level. Now John approaches 
a sign which reads 'Halt— Road Works Ahead*. This input is analysed 
and relayed by various stations of the perceptual and cognitive hier- 
archy, and is eventually re-coded into a 'sign releaser' which triggers 



470 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



off the pre-set patterns of slow-down-to-a-halt behaviour on lower 
echelons of the motor hierarchy. Thus an environmental input on the 
t-level has been transformed into a specific trigger signal in a 'vertical' 
hierarchy; in other words a 'category c input on a higher level has 
been translated into a 'category b' input on a lower level, activating 
the autonomous pattern of the slowing-down skill. This consists in 
several sub-skills: braking, steadying the wheel, going into neutral 
gear at the proper moment. The foot on the brake-pedal is not res- 
ponding to the 'Halt* signal from the environment; it is responding to 
a specific 'excitation-clang' travelling down John's spinal cord. But 
the foot's pre-set response is modified by feedback from the environ- 
ment on its own level: the 'feel* of the pedal's elastic resistance governs 
the 'strategy' of braking — neither too abruptly nor too softly. Similar 
feedbacks influence the automatized motions of the hands on the 
wheel, etc. 

We may perhaps speculate that the digitally coded signals: 'brake', 
'steady wheel' have been converted into analogue-computing servo- 
mechanisms. But speculations apart, we can confidently say that an 
action-pattern of a general nature has been initiated on the top level, 
and that the details were successively filled in by feedbacks from more 
and more restricted local environments on the lower echelons. Simi- 
larly, the future adult is 'roughed in' in a summary way in the morpho- 
genetic gradients of the zygote, then 'sketched in' in the organ- 
Anlage of the uncouth embryo, and so on, until the last detail is elabora- 
ted by the joint action of a cell-group's self-difTerentiation potential and 
its local environment. The performance of a skill means executing a 
general order by a series of progressively differentiated action-patterns, 
each controlled from above, and adjusted by local feedbacks.* 

We thus arrive at a synthesis between the principles of hierarchic 
organization and feedback adjustment. To the hierarchy of autono- 
mous sub-wholes must be added the complementary 'hierarchy of 
environments' and 'hierarchy of feedbacks' — of loops-within-loops, 
from those embracing the personality as a whole in the 'total field', 
down to the molecular level. An elementary but engaging model for 
a hierarchy of servo-mechanisms is the 'TOTE unit' proposed by 
Pribram. 1 

Let me dot my i's on this rather important point by a martial 
analogy. The commander of the N'th Army has decided, taking into 
account all available intelligence reports on the enemy's dispositions, 
to capture tomorrow at dawn the vital hill No. 607. He sends his orders 



PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION 



471 



to his six divisional comanders, broadly outlining their tasks. The 
commander of the 3rd division is assigned the task of occupying ham- 
let X. There are several approaches to the hamlet; to decide which is 
best, he sends out some reconnaissance aircraft which feed informa- 
tion to him. He then communicates his orders to his battalion com- 
manders. Each of these will send out patrols to get the lie of the land 
allotted to them before giving orders to his company commanders; 
and in the end each individual soldier will have to make the best of 
his own small environment of protective hedges and ditches as he 
moves forward in obedience to the sergeant's orders. 

6. It ought to be evident by now that the terms 'matrix* and 'code' 
are not meant to refer to separate entities, but (like 'structure' and 
'function) to complementary aspects of a unitary process. The, code is 
the invariant pattern of the process; it is not affected by environmental 
input. The matrix is the ensemble of part-processes, or 'members' 
potentially capable of being activated by the code; it thus represents the 
total repertory of alternative (equipotential or equifinal) variations in 
carrying out the process, according to feedbacks from the environ- 
ment. The code is the fixed, the matrix the adaptable side of the pro- 
cess; the former determines the rules of the game, the latter the actual 
course of the game. The matrix, therefore, represents the more 'alert' 
or 'articulate' or 'explicit' side of the unitary process — the side turned 
towards the environment. The twenty-letter alphabet of protein- 
synthesis in the cell-matrix is more explicit than the three-letter 
alphabet of the genetic code; it 'spells out' what the latter implied. 
The articulated motions of the limb spell out the compressed message 
of the excitation-clang, as the pianist's ringers spell out the tune. In 
the perceptual and cognitive hierarchies, the codes which govern per- 
formance (e.g. grammar and syntax) function on lower levels of 
awareness than the performance itself. 

7. The control of the whole over the parts is exercised, as in our 
military hierarchy, through 'regulation channels'. The genetic code 
does not interfere with the details of ATP synthesis: it activates the 
sub-code of the mitochondria. The centre coordinating the motion 
of the limbs — in newt or man — does not deal direcdy with individual 
muscles; it activates the proper sub-centres. The battalion commander 
does not issue orders to individual soldiers, or even squads; he signals 
to Company headquarters: 'D Company will advance at 1800 hours.* 
The Company, the limb, the mitochondria are complex sub-wholes; 
but they are activated from the next-higher level as units, through their 



472 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



codes; and they in turn activate their members as units through their 
sub-codes. 

To put it in a different way: each part-process is a pattern of relations; 
but it is manipulated from the next-higher level as a unit— a relatum. 
We shall see that as a general rule, when we ascend in any hierarchy, 
relations turn into relata, which enter into new relations, and so on. 
The code can be said to represent the invariant pattern of a relation; 
the matrix the ensemble of the relata. But one step up, and the code 
itself becomes a relatum; one step down, and the members of the 
matrix are seen as complex relations. "We may thus add one more pair of 
complementary terms to characterize the Janus-faced entities in the de- 
velopmental hierarchy: part < > whole; structure < > func- 
tion, regulative < > mosaic, autonomous < > dependent, 

relation < > relatum, matrix < > code. 

8. The stresses set up between the organism's inner and outer en- 
vironment are matched by active adaptations on various scales. The 
term 'dynamic equilibrium' indicates adaptative processes which do 
not entail major changes in the pattern of the whole; 'regenerative 
span* refers to the organism's capacity for 'adaptations of the second 
order to challenges which can be met only by a reshaping of structures 
or a reorganization of functions; while 'routine regenerations' occupy 
an intermediary position, and overlap with both. 

'Equilibrium* in this context refers not to relations between parts, 
but between the excited part and the controls which represent the 
whole. Under conditions of dynamic equilibrium, the stresses between 
the self-assertive tendencies of the excited part and its integrative 
controls are of a transitory character. Paranormal challenges may lead 
to the phenomenon of 'physiological isolation , owing to over-stimula- 
tion of the part or blockage of communication with its normal con- 
trols. In lower organisms, the isolated part tends to develop into a 
new whole. If it was segregated ab ovo, as sex cells and regeneration 
cells are, this development follows a straight course; if isolation occurs 
at later stages, as in fissure, budding, and organ-regeneration, it in- 
volves a temporary regression of the part to an embryonic or more 
juvenile phase of development, and the liberation of genetic potentials 
which are normally under restraint. It is a safety device which enables 
the organism to cope with traumatic challenges, and correct faulty 
integrations; it furthermore confers on it a super-flexibility which 
plays an important part in biological and mental evolution. 

On higher levels of the evolutionary scale, regenerative processes 



PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION 



473 



are predominantly reorganizations of functions. These range from the 
repair of neuro-muscular co-ordination to the compensation of cor- 
tical damages, and to the re-stracturing of perceptual and conceptual 
patterns in the reculerpour mieux sauter of the creative process. 

During the regressive, catabolic phase, the part tends to dominate 
the whole through the reversal of axial gradients and hierarchic con- 
trols. This may lead to irreversible changes of a pathological nature 
(malignant growths, idee fixe). To avoid snapping of the loosened ties, 
the isolation of the part must be temporary and not complete: after 
the routine-controls have gone out of action, the organism as a whole 
must assist the regenerative process. 

'Routine repairs' were seen to range from the regeneration of tissues 
lost through wear and tear, to the restorative effects of sleep. Dreaming 
could be described as a de-diflerentiation of reasoning-matrices and 
even, up to a point, of personal identity. 

9. These periodic fluctuations from the highest level of integration 
down to earlier or more primitive levels and up again to a new, 
modified pattern, seem to play a major part in biological and mental 
evolution. Their universality is reflected in the myths of death and re- 
birth, the 'dark night of the soul', etc. The 'magic of organ-regenera- 
tions, and of unconscious guidance in creativity, both owe their 
striking character to the sudden re-activation of (morphogenetic or 
psychogenetic) potentials which are normally under restraint in the 
adult individual. The period of incubation may be compared to the 
catabolic phase in organ-regeneration: the former releases pre-con- 
ceptual, intuitive modes of ideation from the censorship imposed by 
the conscious mind; the latter triggers off embryonic growth-processes 
equally inhibited by the mature organism. The contact-guidance of 
nerves towards their end-organs and the revival of other pre-natal 
skills, provide enticing parallels to the unconscious gradients and ancient 
'waterways' which mediate the underground rendezvous of ideas. 



Summary 

To the hierarchy of sub-wholes in the development and behaviour of 
organisms, we have now added a complementary 'hierarchy of en- 
vironments', and a third hierarchy of (exteroceptive and proprioceptive) 
feedbacks — of loops-within-loops which connect the first and the 
second on every level. Certain homologue principles of organization 



474 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



were seen to operate on all levels, such as: (a) the dichotomy of self- 
assertive and participatory tendencies derived from the dual character 
of each part as a 'sub' and a 'whole'; and the related complementarity 
of regulative and mosaic development, of equipotentiality and fixed 
pathway, of relations and relata. (b) Control within the organic hier- 
archy is exercised by 'regulation channels', i.e. high centres do not 
normally have direct dealings with lowly ones, and vice versa, (c) 
Trigger-releaser devices seem to be the general rule in the activation of 
pre-set, autonomous patterns, (d) The releaser signals (excitation- 
clangs, frequency-modulation sequences?) from higher echelons were 
found to be of a more implicit, generalized order than the actual per- 
formance 'spelled out' by the addressee, (e) The pattern of the per- 
formance is determined by its invariant code, but sub-wholes have 
varying degrees of freedom for adaptable strategies (equipotential 
variations) dependent on feedback from their local environment. 

(f) Under normal conditions these flexible strategies are sufficient to 
restore dynamic equilibrium between the whole and its excited parts. 

(g) Traumatic experiences may cause irreversible, degenerative changes 
in the exposed part, but under favourable conditions may initiate 
superflexible adaptations of a second order — regenerations of structure 
or reorganizations of function, which are capable of redressing faulty 
integration, and also play an important part in biological and mental 
development. 

The reader may consider some of these conclusions trivial, others 
perhaps as rash generalizations. In the following chapters their validity 
will be tested in the light of instinct-behaviour, learning, and problem- 
solving. 

NOTE 

To p. 470. 'Feedback' is used here in a broad sense, to include all extero- 
ceptive and proprioceptive inputs relevant to the ongoing activity. 



VI 



CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 

The Genetics of Behaviour 

The phylogenetic origins of instinct-behaviour are among the 
blackest black boxes found in the sciences of life. The causative 
mechanism responsible for the evolution of species in their 
morphological aspect is perplexing enough; regarding the origin of 
specific behaviour-patterns, the darkness is almost complete. As one 
eminent ethologist laments: 'The backward position of ethology is 
striking. Owing to the difficulty of tracing genetically determined be- 
haviour components, geneticists have nearly always used morpho- 
logical characters as indicators of gene-function. ... A genetics of 
behaviour still has to be developed.* 1 

Evolutionary genetics lies outside the scope of this book, but a 
brief remark in passing may be excused. If, apart from a few tentative 
studies, 2 the genetics of behaviour is still an uncharted territory, the 
reason may perhaps be an unconscious reluctance to put the already 
strained theoretical framework of neo-Darwinian genetics to an 
additional test. To quote a very trivial example: an individual song- 
bird or jackdaw or sparrow, on spotting a predator, will give an 
alarm call, warning the whole flock. 'These alarm calls', Tinbergen 
points out, 'are a clear example of an activity which serves the group 
but endangers the individual.' 3 Are we really to assume that the occulo- 
vocal 'wiring diagram' in the sparrow's nervous system which releases 
the alarm call in response to a sign-Gestalt stimulus of predatory shape, 
arose by random mutations and was perpetuated by natural selection 
in spite of its negative survival value for the mutant? The same question 
could be asked concerning the phylogenetic origin of the ritualized 
tournament rights in such various animals as stags, iguana, wolves, 
and fish. Wolves sprawl on their backs as a token of defeat and surren- 
der, exposing their vulnerable bellies to the victor's fangs. One is 

475 



476 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



inclined to call this a rather risky attitude; and what is the individual 
survival value of not hitting (or biting, goring) below the belt? Or if 
it comes to that, of the digger-wasps' nerve-racking maternal activities? 

*A female of this species, when about to lay an egg, digs a hole, 
kills or paralyses a caterpillar, and carries it to the hole, where she 
stows it away after having deposited an egg on it (phase a). This done, 
she digs another hole, in which an egg is laid on a new caterpillar. In 
the meantime, the first egg has hatched and the larva has begun to 
consume its store of food. The mother wasp now turns her attention 
again to the first hole (phase b), to which she brings some more moth 
larvae; then she does the same in the second hole. She returns to the 
first hole for the third time to bring a final batch of six or seven cater- 
pillars (phase c), after which she closes the hole and leaves it for ever. 
In this way she works in turn at two or even three holes, each in a 
different phase of development. Baerends investigated the means by 
which the wasp brought the right amount of food to each hole. He 
found that the -wasp visited all tie holes each morning before leaving 
for the hunting grounds. By changing the contents of the hole and 
watching the subsequent behaviour of the wasp, he found that (i) 
by robbing a hole he could force the wasp to bring far more food than 
usual; and (2) by adding larvae to the hole's contents he could force 
her to bring less food than usual.' 4 

Let me repeat: the reason why a genetics of behaviour still has to be 
developed' seems to be that it cannot be developed with the existing 
theoretical tools without reducing the whole attempt to absurdity. 
It may still be possible, and even respectable today for a geneticist to 
state that: "The hoary objection of the improbability of an eye or a 
hand or a brain being evolved "by blind chance" has lost its force.' 5 
But are we also to assume that the behaviour-patterns of the digger- 
wasp, or of the courtship and fighting rituals of various species have 
all evolved 'by pure chance'? This assumption is implied in the doctrine 
of contemporary genetics — though rarely stated in explicit form. 
Similar assumptions fcave been made by extreme behaviourists in the 
field of learning theory; there is, in fact, a direct continuity between 
the doctrine of natural selection operating on random mutations, and 
reinforcement operating on random trials. Both grew out of the same 
philosophical climate. But while learning theory is in full retreat from 
that extreme position, and has a variety of alternative suggestions to 
offer, nothing the like is in sight in the genetics of instinct-behaviour. 



Instinct and Learning 



Learnt behaviour is built on the foundations of innate behaviour, 
though it is often difficult, if not impossible, to tell where the 'founda- 
tion' ends and the building' starts. But the absence of fool-proof 
delineations between 'inheritance', 'maturation', and learning' need 
not prevent us from recognizing the existence of distinct patterns of 
animal behaviour which are (a) stereotyped, (b) species-specific, (c) 
unlearnt in the sense that they can be shown to appear, more or less 
completely, in animals raised in isolation. It has been objected against 
this view that 'innate* behaviour, e.g. the pecking of chicks, may 
partly be due to pre-natal influences, 6 that 'isolation' is never absolute, 7 
and that learning may be practically instantaneous (as in imprinting). 
Such arguments are valuable in showing that pure heredity sans 
environment is an abstraction; but they do not alter the fact that each 
animal is born with a hereditary potential to feed, hoard, court, nest, 
fight, and care for its young in certain specific and highly characteristic 
ways which are as much part of its native equipment as its morpho- 
logical features, and which can be modified by, but are not derived 
from, imitation and learning. Only the unbalanced claims of some 
extreme behaviourists could temporarily obscure the obvious fact 
that 'if the physical machinery for behaviour develops under genetic 
control, then the behaviour it mediates can scarcely be regarded as 
independent of inheritance'. 8 

learning appears then as the adaptation of the innate potential to 
lived experience. To quote the convergent definitions of one etholo- 
gist and one psychologist: 'Learning is a central nervous process causing 
more or less lasting changes in the innate behavioural mechanisms 

under the influence of the outer world ' 9 'learning is a process by 

which an activity originates or is changed through reacting to an en- 
countered situation, provided that the characteristics of the change in 
activity cannot be explained on the basis of native response tendencies, 
maturation, or temporary states of the organism (fatigue, drugs, etc.)/ 10 

It must be repeated, however, that outside the experimental labora- 
tory it is virtually impossible to draw a precise distinction between the 
'innate' and 'acquired' aspects or components in the adult animal's 
behaviour. Even the discrimination of biologically relevant sign- 
Gestalten in the environment seems to require a minimum of ex- 
perience; and one must conclude, with Thorpe, that 'since comparison 
involves learning, an element of learning enters into all orientation 

477 



478 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



and all perception. Accordingly it is suggested that the difference 
between inborn and acquired behaviour is of degree rather than kind; 
it becomes, in fact, a difference chiefly of degree of rigidity and plas- 
ticity/ 11 In the terms of our schema, what is inherited is the specific 
and invariant factor in the native skill— its code. Its more or less 
flexible matrix develops through learning from experience. To quote 
Thorpe again: 

'In each example of true instinctive behaviour there is a hard core of 
absolutely fixed and relatively complex automatism— an inborn move- 
ment form. This restricted concept is the essence of the instinct itself. 
Lorenz originally called it "Erbkoordination" or fixed action pattern. 
Such action patterns are items of behaviour in every way as constant 
as anatomical structures, and are potentially just as valuable for systema- 
tic, philogenetic studies. Every systematist working with such groups 
as birds or higher insects will be able to recall examples of the value of 
such fixed behaviour patterns in classification/ 12 

Tinbergens Hierarchy 

Thus on the level of instinct-behaviour 'codes* appear in the guise of 
fixed action-patterns, which incorporate the rules of the game of 
courting, nest-building, duelling, etc. Each of these activities is again 
a hierarchy of autonomous sub-skills. These tend to be more flexible 
on the higher levels which co-ordinate the drive, and more rigid on 
the lower levels. The autonomous sub-codes are restrained from 
spontaneous activity by 'inhibitory blocks', and triggered into activity 
by patterned impulses from higher echelons. This trigger-sensitive 
apparatus is called, after Lorenz, the innate releasing mechanism — or 
I.R.M. for short: 

'In all the channels which flow downward from the centre [of a 
given drive], there is supposed to exist a physiological mechanism 
which effectively prevents all discharge of activity unless the animal 
encounters the right environmental situation and stimuli to remove or 
release this block. Thus there is an innate releasing mechanism (LR,M.) 
* . . which is in some way attuned to the biologically right stimulus in 
the environment . . . and which is, as it were, unlocked by the app- 
ropriate releaser, thus allowing behaviour to proceed to the next lower 
level. These in their turn incorporate blocks and, so long as these 
remain, action of these lower centres cannot proceed/ 13 



CODES OP INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 



479 



Tinbergen's famous example of the hierarchic control of instinct- 
activity is the reproductive behaviour of the male stickleback, which 
I shall describe in the terminology of the present theory. 

Lcvctofthe 
Wtsummatory act 




Figure 15 

In spring the lengthening of days triggers off the small fish's 'migra- 
ting code', while hormonal activities provide the drive or motivation. 
The fish then migrates into shallow water and swims around until a 
certain environmental configuration (rise of temperature, combined 
with green vegetation, etc.) strikes the 'right note*, i.e. releases an 
efferent impulse, which in turn triggers off the sub-code of the nest- 
building activity. This activity is again subdivided into digging, glue- 
ing, etc., each of these skills governed by its autonomous sub-code. 
The latter are activated by trigger releasers; the order of operations is 
determined by inputs from the environment and proprioceptive 
feedbacks. The hierarchy of mating behaviour remains blocked until 
nest-building is complete; but the 'fighting* hierarchy (with its five 
different sub-codes) may be called at any moment into action by a 
trigger mechanism sensitive to a specific sign-Gestalt input: 'red male 
enteri ng te rritory'. In this case the fighting code dominates the animal's 



48o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



entire behaviour, and nest-building as well as other activities are in- 
hibited while the emergency lasts: the (functional) part monopolizes 
the attention of the whole. 

The sub-units of the behaviour-pattern tend to become more 
specific regarding input and more stereotyped in output on the lower 
levels of the hierarchy. * Which one of the five motor responses belong- 
ing to the fighting pattern will be shown depends on sign stimuli that 
are still more restricted in effect.' 14 The nuptial colours of the fish are 
shining blue eyes and a red underbelly. Accordingly, any crude model 
which is red underneath will release an attack, regardless of shape and 
size — whereas a perfecdy shaped model without nuptial colouring will 
not do so. Apart from colour, behaviour also acts as a releaser. *When 
the stranger bites, the owner of the territory will bite in return. 
When the stranger threatens, the owner will threaten back; when the 

stranger flees, the owner will chase it; and so on 15 But fighting is 

rarer than threat. The threat-behaviour of male sticklebacks is peculiar. 
Not only do they dart towards the opponent with raised dorsal spines 
and open mouth, ready to bite, but, when the opponent does not flee 
at once but resists, the owner of the territory does not actually bite 
but points its head down and, standing vertically in the water, makes 
some jerky movements as if it were going to bore its snout into the 
sand.' 16 

This of course is an exceptional example — ^nest-building is a rarity 
among fish. But the rigidity of fixed action patterns in certain classes 
— such as birds and insects — remains nevertheless a striking phenome- 
non. The ritualized rules of the game of courtship and display, of threat 
and danger signals, of tournament fighting and social behaviour, some- 
times reminds one of the ceremonious observances at Byzantine 
courts, at other times of the obsessive rituals of compulsion-neurotics. 
And the process of 'ritualization' does indeed suggest the emancipation* 
— or isolation — of a behaviour-pattern from its original context, 
accompanied by intensification, stabilization, and rhythmic repetitive- 
ness of the pattern; the reasons are as yet hardly understood. 17 

Appetitive Behaviour and Consummately Act 

In spite of the relatively stereotyped nature of fixed action-patterns — 
of which ritualization is an extreme example — it would be entirely 
wrong to regard the hierarchy of instinct behaviour as a one-way affair, 



CODES OP INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 



481 



in which a plastic, general drive (the 'appetitive behaviour) dis- 
charges downward along pre-formed and discrete alternative channels 
into the completely rigid and mechanical, fixed-action-patterns of the 
'consummatory act\ This conception of the organism as an automaton 
whose 'adaptability' is reduced to that of a kind of automatic record- 
changer or jukebox, with a choice between a few dozen fixed records 
appropriate to the occasion, seems to have originated in a misunder- 
standing of the distinction made by Wallace Craig between appetitive 
behaviour' and 'consummatory act'. This point must be briefly dis- 
cussed as it is of some importance for the sections which follow. 

Appetite (or 'appetance') was denned by Craig (191 8) as a 'state of 
agitation', a striving for an absent 'appeted' stimulus (conversely, a 
striving to escape from a noxious or disturbing stimulus); whereas the 
'consummatory act' was meant to bring the activity to a close by 
attaining (or escaping from) the appetitive stimulus, 'after which the 
appetitive behaviour ceases and is succeeded by a state of relative rest'. 1 * 
More generally, 'the term appetitive behaviour is used by present-day 
writers on ethology to mean the flexible or variable introductory 
phase of an instinctive behaviour pattern or sequence'. 1 * 

Thus 'appetitive behaviour' became a more refined and noncom- 
mittal name for the old, shop-soiled concepts of 'need', 'drive', 
'instinct', and 'purpose'.* So far all was well; it was the 'consummatory 
act', which led instinct-theory into a cul-de-sac. The trouble started* 
rather inconspicuously, when first Woodworth 20 then, independently 
from each other, K.* S. Lashley and Konrad Lorenz became impressed 
with the stereotyped character of certain 'consummatory acts' (animal 
rituals and automatized habits in humans), as compared with the more 
general 'appetitive behaviour' or drive.** Eventually the focussing of 
attention on such fixed patterns of behaviour led to a distortion of the 
whole picture: Lorenz and Tinbergen made a rigid distinction between 
appetitive behaviour which was supposed to be flexible, and con- 
summatory acts which were supposed to be completely fixed and 
automatic. Thus Tinbergen: 

*It will be clear, therefore, that this distinction between appetitive 
behaviour and consummatory act separates the behaviour as a whole 
into two components of entirely different character. The consum- 
matory act is relatively simple; at its most complex it is a chain of 
reactions. . . . But appetitive behaviour is a true purposive activity, 
offering all the problems of plasticity, adaptiveness, and of complex 
integration that baffle the scientist in his study of behaviour as a whole. 



482 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



. . . Lorenz has pointed out . . . that purposiveness, the striving towards 
an end, is typical only of appetitive behaviour and not of consumma- 
tely actions Whereas the consummatory act seems to be dependent 

on the centres of the lowest level of instinctive behaviour, appetitive 
behaviour may be activated by centres of all the levels above that of 

the consummatory act 21 The centres of the higher levels do control 

purposive behaviour which is adaptive with regard to the mechanisms 
it employs to attain the end. The lower levels, however, give rise to 
increasingly simple and more stereotyped movements, until at the 
level of the consummatory act we have to do with an entirely rigid 
component, the taxis, the variability of which, however, is entirely 
dependent on changes in the outer world. This seems to settle the 
controversy; the consummatory act is rigid, the higher patterns are 
purposive and adaptive/ 22 

But what exactly, one might ask, constitutes a 'consummatory act'? 
A glance at Tinbergen's diagram on page 479, for instance, will show 
that all actual manifestations of the reproductive instinct are classified 
as 'consummatory acts', whereas 'building', 'fighting', etc., are merely 
abstract, classificatory terms in which longer sequences of consum- 
matory acts are bracketed together. Where, then, is the 'appetitive 
behaviour'? In the stickleback's spring migration in search of a nesting 
site? But that action-pattern was, judged by its dependence on specific 
releasers (temperature, verdant vegetation, etc.) on the same 'con- 
summatory' level as, for instance, 'testing of materials'. The nearest 
Tinbergen gets to a definition of the consummatory act is in the 
following passage: 

'The activation of a centre of the lowest level usually, perhaps always, 
results in a relatively simple motor response: biting, chasing, threaten- 
ing, etc., in the case of fighting. . . . actual eating, actual escape, actual 
coition, etc., in other instincts. . . . These relatively simple responses 
are, usually, the end of a bout of prolonged activity, and their per- 
formance seems to "satisfy" the animal, that is to say, to bring about a 
sudden drop of motivation. This means that such an end-response 
consumes the specific impulses responsible for its activation. Fighting, 
eating, mating, "playing the broken wing" etc., are, as a rule, "self- 
exhausting".' 23 

However, neither 'digging' nor 'leading female to nest* is an end- 
response, or self-exhausting, or leads to a 'drop in motivation'. 'Testing 
of materials' is not a consummation, but a part-activity in the flexible, 
i.e. 'appetitive*, pattern of%uilding. And the building activity is not a 



CODES OP INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 



483 



one-way affair in the sense of higher levels in the hierarchy discharging 
along fixed conduits into the lower level of consumxnatory acts, along 
irreversible gradients. On the contrary, the control of operations 
oscillates all the time between different levels; the operational units 
responsible for one kind of 'end-response* carry on until a centre on a 
higher level, informed by feedback, switches to some other *con- 
summatory act'. It is at this point that the concepts of 'hierarchies of 
environment' and 'hierarchies of feedback* become important. In a 
complex activity like nest-building, even the relatively stereotyped 
operations on subordinate levels are under the dual control of their 
fixed codes and variable environment; and furthermore, information 
about their activities is constancy fed back (by proprioceptive and 
exteroceptive channels) to higher centres, so that the whole always 
remains in hierarchic control 'through regulation channels' of all of its 
parts. Tinbergen's schema does not really represent an organismic 
hierarchy, but a mechanical one — rather like an automatized telephone 
net-work where the subscriber making a trunk call first dials the code- 
number of the whole town ('appetitive behaviour'), then the code of 
his fiancee's local exchange (semi-appetitive, semi-consummatory?), 
and lastly her personal number (consummatory act). 

Thorpe, arguing on similar lines, has given an inventory, which 
fills two printed pages, of the eighteen releasers and fourteen distinct 
action-patterns in the Longtailed Tits' 'consummatory acts' of build- 
ing a nest — ending with the exclamation: 'So much for simplicity!' He 
concludes: 

It seems, then, that in much of appetitive behaviour the animal's 
own activities . . . must be sel£-rewarding and self-stimulating. ... In 
other words, much appetitive behaviour is also in a sense the con- 
summatory act 24 Hinde concludes that appetitive behaviour and 

consummatory act differ only in degree, and that no absolute distinc- 
tion can be made between them. Both are to some extent "spon- 
taneous" in that they show evidence of external activation, and both 
are stereotyped to some degree and show some rigidity. Thus the 
classic examples of appetitive-behaviour and consummatory act can 
be regarded as the two ends of a series ranging from extreme varia- 
bility and plasticity on the one hand to almost complete fixity on the 
other.'** 

Many patterns of instinct-behaviour are of course cyclic: hunt- 
ing > capturing > ingesting > digesting > hunting, 

etc.; and all one can say about the sub-activities in the cycle is that they 



484 THE ACT OF CREATION 

are both 'appetitive* and 'consummately, but that some are more 
appetitive and some more consummatory than others. 

"What really matters in our context is the continuous scale of grada- 
tions between rigid and flexible action-patterns. Somewhere near the 
middle of the scale we find the common spider, whose web-making I 
have already used as a paradigm for an invariant yet adaptable built-in 
code (Book One, p. 38). It will suspend its familiar net from three, 
four, or more points of attachment, according to the Be of the land; 
yet the centre of the polygonal web will always coincide with its 
centre of gravity and the radial threads will always intersect the lateral 
threads at equal angles. We thus have a simple fixed code, yet a highly 
flexible strategy. Moreover, if some of the garden spiders legs and 
claws are amputated, it will still construct a more or less normal net — 
the code remains unaffected by the elimination of some members of 
the matrix. 

Leerlauf and Displacement 

Towards the rigid' end of the scale we find reflex-like matrices, exem- 
plified in the so-called Leerlauf activities. This term, too, was coined 
by Lorenz; the current English translation is Vacuum activity' — but 
'freewheeling* would perhaps be more appropriate. Seagulls, reared 
in isolation, will perform on the stone floor of the laboratory their 
characteristic 'tap-dance* which, under normal circumstances, would 
serve to bring small animals to the surface of the tidal mud. Cats will 
go through the motion of burying their faeces on the kitchen tiles; and 
hand-reared young flying-squirrels 'when given nuts, would go through 
all the motions of burying them in the bottom of the wire-cage, and 
then go away contented, even though the nuts were exposed to full 
view*. 26 The same author describes the behaviour of hand-reared 
tawny owls 'which, after being fed, would act as if pouncing upon 
living prey though it had never had the experience of dealing with a 
living mouse*. 27 

Such examples of 'stupid', automaton-like behaviour are the stron- 
gest evidence for innate codes of action. At the same time they are 
also additional evidence against the chain-reflex theory of instinct- 
behaviour: the owl, which has never seen a mouse, pounces after being 
fed, and without any visual stimulus; in the gulTs case, the hard floor 
of the laboratory is a stimulus quite different from the soft mud — hence 
the 'chain-reaction ought never to start, or to break off after the .first 



CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 



485 



unsuccessful attempt at 'digging' the tiles. Instincts are purposive and 
flexible, but their flexibility is limited to conditions more or less within 
the experience of the race. In a crassly unnatural environment the 
performance degenerates into 'freewheeling' and loses its purposive 
aspect. 

According to Lorenz's rather controversial theory, the motivation 
of Leerlauf activity is derived from a 'damming up' of the animal's 
'specific action potential' (SAP) which lowers the threshhold of the 
innate releasing mechanism so that the action will go off even in 
the absence of appropriate stimuli. Hence also the term 'overflow 
activity'. 

Another distortion of instinct-behaviour are the so-called displace- 
ment activities which overlap with Leerlauf (and also with play). 'Dis- 
placement is the performance of a behaviour pattern out of the 
particular functional context of behaviour to which it is normally 
related. It seems to appear when the charge (SAP) attached to one 
instinct is denied opportunity for adequate discharge through its own 
consummatory act or acts and instead "sparks over" to set going the 
consummatory act of another instinct.' 28 A dog in its restraining harness 
in a Pavlov-type laboratory, while expecting the fall of food from the 
container, will stamp, yawn, and pant — activities which do not belong 
to his normal feeding behaviour; but what else, one may irreverently 
ask, can the poor excited creature do? Pail-fed calves will suck the 
ears or navels of their companions, as infants suck their thumbs. Some 
birds play elaborate games, throwing up and catching sticks; so do 
puppies; kittens will 'pretend* that a ball of wool is a mouse. Leerlauf 
and 'displacement* thus comprise a broad range of activities which 
occur in the absence of the proper stimulus or in the presence of 
normally inadequate ersatz stimuli; or when the proper response is for 
some reason blocked. Its human equivalents range from playful 
activities to repetition compulsions and the formation of neurotic 
ersatz symptoms. 

Instinct and Originality 

At the opposite end of the rigidity-flexibility scale we find adapta- 
tions of instinct-based behaviour-patterns which give the impression 
of original improvisation. Even the ritual-bound stickleback, that 
stickler for etiquette, is capable of them: 'If the normal behaviour- 
pattern is continually interfered with, quite large modifications in the 



48(5 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



normal instinctive orientation of the nest-building movements may 
be made/ 29 

Thus the denial of normal outlets can lead either to the mechanical 
reeling-off of the built-in pattern in freewheeling or displacement 
activity; or to original re-adaptations of the pattern. "Which of these 
alternative possibilities will occur depends on the nature of the chal- 
lenge, and the animal's ripeness' to cope with it. What solution, after 
all, could even a genius cat find to comply with its code of hygiene 
on the kitchen tiles? What creative outlet is left to the squirrel to solve 
his nut-hiding problem? 

On the other hand, ethologists have produced many striking 
examples of ingenious instinct-based behaviour in the face of ad- 
versity. The female of a certain wasp, Eumenes conica, builds clusters of 
clay-cells or pots, deposits an egg in each, provisions it with cater- 
pillars for food, then closes the cells with clay lids. If now an artificial 
hole is made in a cell, the wasp will first stuff the caterpillars which 
have fallen out back through the hole, then mend the hole with a 
pellet of clay — operations which are quite different from her normal 
building routines. Hingston 30 has described in detail the actions of 
another wasp — Rkynchium nitiderium — in repairing a man-made hole 
in a clay-pot. On one occasion the female tried for two hours to mend 
the hole with bits of material taken from the wall of the pot. Then 
night came and she had to give up. Next morning she flew straight to 
the damaged spot and set about repairing it by a different strategy. 
In the normal course of events the wasp works from outside. But now, 
in order to repair the hole, 'she examines it from both sides and then, 
having made a choice, elects to do the repair from within'. 31 

Equally surprising is the ingenuity of the caddis-fly larva. If a group 
of larvae are ejected from the tubular 'houses' which they built, and 
are then allowed to return, they often get mixed up and enter the 
wrong 'house' which is either too big or too small. The larva then 
sets about to cut off parts of the tube or to add to it, until it fits it 
exactly. Again the 'consummatory acts' in these activities are quite 
different from those in normal building. 

Many birds, too, are capable of such 'super-flexible' behaviour in 
emergencies. If their brood is taken away, they will re-start their 
sexual cycle, court and mate out of season, and get a new family 
going. In some species, in the absence of the female, the male bird 
takes over her dudes in feeding the young— which never happens 
under normal conditions. 



CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUX 



487 



Lastly, a brief mention must be made of 'supra-individual codes' — 
such as those which regulate activities in the honey-bee hive. Lindauer, 
among others, has shown that 'the programme of work carried out by 
the individual is not determined by the physiological state of the insect 
but is dictated by the needs of the colony as a whole'. 32 An individual 
worker-bee hardly ever builds a complete cell. She may start the cell, 
with wax from her own glands, then complete another cell, started by 
a colleague, using her own wax or that of another bee — whichever 
happens to be convenient. Generally, there is rigid division of labour 
according to age groups: each worker has to perform a different kind 
of * National Service' in different periods of its life. During her first 
three days, she works as a cell-cleaner. For the next three days she feeds 
the older larvae with honey and pollen from the stores. Then she 
feeds the younger larvae, who get an additional diet — a liquid secreted 
from glands on the worker's head. At the age of ten days she is en- 
gaged in complex household chores and building activities. At twenty 
days she takes over guard duties at the entrance of the hive; and finally, 
she becomes a forager and remains one until the end of her life. But 
even among the foragers there is further specialization of labour: some 
of them become 'scouts', whose task it is to discover new sources of 
food, and to communicate, on their return, the nature and location of 
it, in their dance-language, to the hive. 33 

But this is not all. If one of the specialized age-groups is artificially 
eliminated from the colony, a kind of collective super-flexibility mani- 
fests itself in the hive: other age-groups deputize for the vanished 
group 'and thus save the superorganism. When, for instance, all 
pollen-and-honey foragers are taken away — usually bees of twenty 
days or over — young bees of scarcely six days old, who normally feed 
the larvae, fly out and become foragers. If all building workers are 
taken away — those between eighteen and twenty days old—their task 
is taken on by older bees who had already been builders before, but 
who had gone on to the stage of forager. To this end they not only 
change their behaviour, but also regenerate the wax-glands. The 
mechanisms of these regulations are not known.' 34 

Thus at one end of the scale we find rituals, fixed action-patterns, 
vacuum and displacement activities — rigid, automatized, and compul- 
sive, petrified habits of unknown phylogenetic origin. At the other 
extreme we find supra-individual codes which govern behaviour of 
remarkable flexibility, and original adaptations which lie outside the 



488 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



animal's normal skills and habit repertory. In all forms of social 
organization — from courtship, mating, and fighting rituals, through 
territorial demarcations, up to the complex insect state, we find an 
interlocking of individual behaviour-patterns into a collective super- 
code which casts the individual bird or bee into the role of a part in 
the social whole. Thus we see the hierarchic part-whole relationship 
repeated on the level of social organization, where the integrative 
functions of catalyzers, inductors, and nerve impulses are superseded 
by interlacing systems of social releasers, including communication 
by signs and symbol — from display, through bird-song, to the dance- 
language of the honey-bee. 

NOTES 

To p. 481. The equivalent of the term 'appetitive behaviour' in American 
behaviourist theory are Hull's drive-stimulus (S D ); and his 'fractional ante- 
dating goal-stimuli and responses' (S Q Re). 

Tc p. 481. Out of this grew the theory that the fixed pattern of the con- 
summatory act — and not the 'appeted stimulus' — is the goal of the animal's 
striving and the sourc* of the 'action-specific energy' of the drive; but the subject 
is outside the scope of this book. 



VII 

IMPRINTING AND IMITATION 



So far we have discussed the codes of morphogenesis and innate 
behaviour, which emerge ready-made from the black boxes of 
evolution — like Ali Baba's thieves, popping out of the urns in 
which they were hiding. 

In the chapters which follow we shall discuss the ontogenesis of 
behavioural codes — the acquisition of habits, knowledge, skills, by the 
processes of learning from experience. 

The 'Following-response 

The transition from innate to learnt behaviour is sharply highlighted 
in the phenomena of imprinting. The follow-the-leader response of the 
gosling is governed by an innate code; it must stick to the mother- 
goose or perish. But like many phylogenetically acquired codes it seems 
to have been formed according to the principle of parsimony. It can 
be triggered off by any releaser which satisfies very broad Gestalt 
criteria of 'goose-likeness* — including German ethologists and even 
inanimate moving objects of a certain size. In a normal environment 
this would indeed be sufficient to ensure the gosling's survival, since 
the first sizeable moving creature seen would be the mother-goose. 
Accordingly, a young goose, reared from the egg in isolation (or in 
the incubator) will accept — during the brief critical period of matura- 
tion when imprinting occurs — its human keeper as its 'mother*, and 
follow him around. Once this has happened the process becomes more 
or less irreversible: the 'imprinted* bird will reject the company of 
other geese and attach itself only to members of the human species — 
treating them as parents, companions, and later on as objects of sexual 

489 



490 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



advances. Many other birds, and possibly also some fish and insects, 
show the phenomena of imprinting in varying degrees. 

Here, then, we have a pregnant example of the genesis of a matrix 
through the integration of innate and acquired behaviour-patterns. 
The built-in 'following response* has the characteristic autonomy of 
motor-patterns which we have met before: it is triggered off and modi- 
fied, but not created by the environmental input. The first step in the 
development of the matrix is the act of imprinting itself; it must occur, 
as already mentioned, during the critical phase when the young bird 
is susceptible for it (in ducks, for instance, between eleven and eighteen 
hours after birth, with a pointed peak in the susceptibility curve at 
sixteen hours). 1 The input which triggers off the following-response 
is at this stage an undifferentiated and primitive sign-releaser: 'Large 
moving object' — much simpler in character than the more specific 
Gestalt stimuli which release the fighting or mating instinct in the 
stickleback (red belly', 'swollen belly*) or the begging response of the 
herring-gull chick (red spot on beak'). 

The next stage is one of perceptual learning. After a few hours, even a 
few minutes, of following a human being, the gosling will follow only 
human beings — it has somehow learned to 'abstract', or 'encode' in its 
memory some specific Gestalt-characteristics of homo sapiens which 
distinguish it from other 'shapes that move*. On the other hand, at 
this stage all human beings are still 'equipotentiaT members of the 
emergent perceptual matrix. At a still later stage, the goose may 
become attached to one or more single individuals, that is to say, it 
learns to discriminate individuals within the species — as, vice versa, 
animal breeders learn to sharpen their perception and to distinguish 
one sheep or goose from another. 

We thus meet, already on this level, the twin phenomena involved 
in all learning processes: generalization ('transfer', 'abstraction ) and 
discrimination (segregation of pattern, selective inhibition of responses 
to non-specific stimuli). These basic processes will be discussed later 
(Chapter X); in the meantime, let us note that the innate, primitive 
'rule of the game' which made the new-born animal respond to 'things- 
that-move', has been sharpened and elaborated into a more complex 
set of rules by a series of steps. Each of these steps involved a re- 
structuring of the perceptual matrix by successive generalizations and 
discriniinations — which we may regard as quasi-extensions of func- 
tional integration and structural differentiation into the learning pro- 
cess. Morphogenesis and learning form continuous series which over- 



IMPRINTING AND IMITATION 



491 



lap during maturation; and the matrices of innate and acquired be- 
haviour form an equally continuous hierarchy. 

Bird-song and Parrot-talk 

There are no sharply defined boundaries between imprinting and learn- 
ing by imitation, or by trial and error. The word sprinting' itself is 
a translation of Heinroth's Pragung, 2 by which he meant to indicate 
the dramatic form of learning in birds which we have just discussed. 
Its chief characteristics are: it is species-specific and directly dependent 
on innate organization; quasi-instantaneous; and limited to a relatively 
brief period in the animal's life. By applying these criteria, Thorpe has 
extended the concept of imprinting to include a bird's instantaneous 
attachment to territory, its occasional attachment not only to humans 
but also to other animals and even inanimate objects; and lastly, the 
song-bird's way of learning its species-characteristic song'. 3 

Apparently in some birds such as thrushes, warblers, pippits, the 
whole song is genetically 'built in' and can be but slightly modified by 
learning; while in others, for instance the skylark, it is mainly learned. 
In chaffinches Thorpe has shown that while the basic pattern of the 
song is innate, all the finer detail and much of the pitch and rhythm 
have to be acquired by learning.'* We have here another example 
of a 'roughed-in' pattern (p. 470) whose details are filled in later 
by that particular type of 'feedback' process which constitutes 
learning. 

When we turn to imitative bird-song and parrot-talk, the part played 
by innate organization is obviously less specific and the part played by 
learning much greater; yet the difference is again one of degree. In 
fact, Pragung means stamping (a coin), which makes the continuity 
between imprinting and 'stamped-in learning' even more obvious.** 
Less obvious, however, is the biological purpose or adaptive value of 
the striking capacity of parrots, mocking-birds, starlings, etc., to imi- 
tate the songs of entirely alien species — ^including 'God Save the 
King', 4 Now parrots living in freedom in their natural environment 
utter only a few fixed, simple types of cries; yet folklore apart, we have 
no lesser authority than Lashley describing a captive parrot with a 
'vocabulary' of between fifty and a hundred words; and there is 
reliable evidence 5 that both parrots and robins can learn to utter certain 
words meaningfully. Granted that vocal imitation, as McDougall 



492 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



has pointed out, 6 is a special case owing to the close integration 
of auditory-vocal patterns, one must nevertheless admit that such 
imitative ability is 'a further example of pre-adaptation for apparently 
remote and unlikely contingencies, specialization going in advance of 
immediate adaptive requirement, and as such on a par with the 
astonishing number-sense which can be developed in many species 
by careful training. Such a counting ability seems to offer even less 
practical advantage for a wild bird than the features we have been 
considering; all are as yet somewhat mysterious. , 7 (The counting ability 
of birds was revealed in Otto Koehler's famous experiments, to be 
discussed later.) Ethologists such as Koehler (not to be confused with 
Wolfgang Kohler), Lorenz, Craig, and Thorpe all agree that the tonal 
purity, the t inventiveness , and improvisation in the advanced forms of 
bird-song should be regarded as 'the first steps in both music and 
speech'. 8 

To mention one example among many: Waite, at the Museum 
in Sydney, owned an Australian magpie whom he taught by playing 
on the flute a fifteen-note melody in two distinct phrases'. Some years 
later he got a second magpie which learned the tune from, the first. 
The two birds then developed the habit of singing it antiphonally, 
the first singing the first phrase, and the second only the second. 'Later 
the second, younger, bird died whereupon the first resumed its per- 
formance of the whole.' 9 

Examples like this show not only the great flexibility of these 
auditory-vocal matrices. They also show that the total pattern — the 
rudimentary code of the hand-reared chaffinch — develops first, and 
that learning the song does not consist in the chaining of individual 
notes according to the S.-R. scheme, but in the elaboration and varia- 
tion of the pattern. We further note that originality or 'inventiveness' 
make their appearance at only a few removes from innate and im- 
printed behaviour. Lasdy, the striking learning abilities of some birds, 
which are only revealed under the abnormal conditions of captivity — 
these examples of *pre-adaptations for remote and unlikely contin- 
gencies' remind us of regenerative potentials manifested in response to 
traumatic challenges. 

Untapped Resources 

We have seen evidence of this latent super-flexibility — of 'doing won- 
ders' in adversity — on every level: from the restoration of locomotive 



IMPRINTING AND IMITATION 



493 



patterns in mutiliated insects and rats, through the emergency redistri- 
bution of labour in the beehive, up to the solution of blocked problems 
by * thinking aside'. In recent years, unsuspected learning abilities were 
revealed in such widely different classes as flatworms, dolphins, and 
seals — the latter, apparently, can even be taught to obey visual sign- 
commands printed on cards. Yet the evidence for a surplus, or reserve, 
of learning potentials far surpassing immediate adaptive needs has 
always been there in our own species: ten thousand years ago our 
ancestors fought with clubs and arrows, but the structure of their 
brains was the same as ours, and therefore potentially just as capable 
of learning Boolean Logics or the principles of making a nuclear bomb. 
Even the dumb fish have been shown to have optical capacities for 
form and colour discrimination far in advance of their needs under 
natural conditions. Thorpe comments: 'It does indeed seem to be a 
general feature of animal life that the precision and sensitivity of sense 
organs is higher than the environment would appear to justify. This 
fact poses a serious problem for students of evolution, since it is not 
easy to account for such perfection on the basis of natural selection 
alone/* 

It seems that this overshooting of the mark, this giving more than was 
asked for, is an inherent characteristic of the mechanism of evolution. 
In homo sapiens the 'overshooting* is demonstrated by the fact that 
mental evolution— learning to exploit the surplus potentials in his 
brain — has been going on for an astronomical period, and with no end 
in sight. The problem is not so much why mental evolution occurs in 
man, but why no similar phenomenon — learning to use their native 
equipment to maximum capacity — seems to have occurred in any 
other species, although many animals demonstrate the existence of 
their untapped resources in captivity. (Animals, it is true, keep no 
written records of their discoveries, but these could have been trans- 
mitted by imitative learning.) All this is a nice subject for speculations 
on a rainy day; the important point in our context is the hard core of 
evidence to show that various animals reveal in captivity various 
degrees of originality and resourcefulness which are not displayed 
under natural conditions. Most animals seem to have more sensitive 
organs than they need, and more latent capabilities than they ever learn 
to actualize, except when challenged under propitious circumstances. 
That bar-pressing experiments with rats are not the type of challenge 
designed to elicit original responses, need not be emphasized, and it is 
not surprising, therefore, that leading Behaviourists have either denied 



494 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the occurrence of original responses or put them down to chance. 
We shall return to the subject in later chapters. 

NOTES 

To p. 491. The chaffinch song consists of three distinct and well-articulated 
phrases. Hand-reared chaffinches produce a much simplified, rudimentary variant 
of the song, where the first and second phrase are often inseparable, and the third 
partly or wholly missing. But — and this is the elegant point of the experiment — 
if the young bird is left to be reared by its parents, then taken away and isolated 
in September, that is to say, long before it starts singing, it will nevertheless burst 
into normal song next spring. Apparently 'these birds have by their first Septem- 
ber learned that the song "should" be in three phrases and that the terminal phrase 
should contain a more or less elaborate flourish*. Thus 'on the perceptory side 
the process of recognizing and accepting the specific song as henceforth the 
"normal" for the individual (as distinct from the acquisition of the new motor 
habits involved in performing the song) seems to resemble the original examples 
of imprinting [the following response] sufficiently close to warrant considering 
them together' (Thorpe, 1956, p. 375). 

Top. 491. In the human child, processes analogous to Pragung may perhaps 
be responsible for producing infantile fixations and fetishistic rituals. The cases 
of boot-fetishism, for instance, frequently reported in works on sexual pathology 
remind one of imprinting by inanimate objects — such as a gander's seven-year 
fixation on an oildrum, reported by Thorpe (p. 365). A further analogy may be 
found between Gestalt-sign releasers, based on the vital statistics of film-stars, and 
Tinbergen's simplified laboratory models of the pregnant stickleback. 

Top. 493. Thorpe continues: 'However, the answer may be that the nature 
of sensory nervous mechanisms is such that to achieve full efficiency at the normal 
levet of stimulation, the threshold must be much lower.' (Thorpe, 1956, p. 283). 
But other passages which I have quoted show that he does not regard this ex- 
planation as satisfactory. 



VIII 



MOTIVATION 

Retrospect 

Future historians will probably regard it as significant that 
throughout the first half of the twentieth century the dominant 
schools of psychology — even schools as far apart as behaviourism 
and psychoanalysis — recognized only one basic type of motivation, 
and that a negative one: the reduction of biological needs and drives, 
the diminution of tension, escape from anxiety. 'At the level of ego- 
psychology', wrote Mowrer in his survey on 'Motivation* in the 
Annual Review for 1952, 1 'there may be said to be only one master 
motive: anxiety.* 

The trend seems to have originated in the climate of the Darwinian 
revolution independently in Germany and America, with Fechner's 
(1873) 'Tendenz zur Stabilitat' and Thorndike's (1898) 'Law of Effect'. 
Freud (1920), acknowledging his indebtedness to Fechner, postulated 
his own Principle of Parsimony, according to which 'the course of 
mental events is invariably set in motion by an unpleasurable tension, 
and it takes a direction such that its final outcome coincides with a 
lowering of that tension'. Thus pleasure is derived from 'the diminu- 
tion, lowering, or extinction of psychic excitation' and 'un-pleasure 
[Uitlust, dysphoria, as distinct from physical pain] from an increase of 
it'. The organism tends towards stability — a kind of homeostasis, 
applied not only to autonomic regulations but also to voluntary 
behaviour; it is guided by 'the striving of the mental apparatus to keep 
the quantity of excitations present in it as low as possible or at least 
constant. Accordingly, everything that tends to increase the quantity 
of excitation, must be regarded as adverse to this tendency, that is to 
say, as unpleasurable.* 2 

Now this is of course true, in a broad sense, in so far as the frustration 
or satisfaction of primary biological needs is concerned. But it passes 

495 



496 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



in silence a whole class of experiences to which we commonly refer as 
pleasurable excitement 9 . The preHminaries of love-making cause an 
increase in sexual tension and should, according to the theory, be un- 
pleasant — which they are decidedly not. It is curious that in the works 
of Freud there is no answer to be found to this embarrassingly banal 
objection. The sex-drive in the Freudian system is essentially some- 
thing to be disposed q/^-through the proper channels or by sublimation; 
pleasure is derived not from its pursuit, but from getting rid of it. 
One might argue that in Freud's universe there is no place for amorous 
love-play because Freud, like D. H. Lawrence, was basically a puritan 
with a horror of frivolity, who treated sex 'mit tierischem Ernst' * But 
arguments ad hominem do not explain the general trend in the first half 
of the century to interpret motivation as something negative. As 
Hilgard raefully remarked, 3 the 'Zeitgeist favoured our seeing incen- 
tives not as providing something sought after for what was inherent 
in the incentive, but something providing relief. The incentive was 
seen as an avenue of escape from pain, anxiety, tension/ Just as Freud's 
libido-theory had no room for dalliance, so learning-theory had no 
room for curiosity or learning-by-play. 

Thorndike's 'Law of Effect' was essentially a stick-and-carrot theory; 
the reward (and to a lesser degree, punishment) is the factor which 
stamps in the correct responses in learning, and stamps out the in- 
correct ones. In the extreme behaviourist systems of Watson and 
Guthrie, the mechanization of the living organism is complete: con- 
tiguity is the basic factor in producing associative S.-R. bonds, and 
motivation has virtually disappeared from the picture. Nor is any 
theory of motivation allowed to enter into Skinner's concept of 
'operant behaviour'. His system is by programme confined to the 
description of experimental operations, preferably in quantitative 
terms. The effects of different rates and sequences of positive and 
negative reinforcers are counted and plotted; die entity on which they 
act is the 'operant strength', which in turn is measured by the rate 
and number of responses during extinction; but the motivation of the 
animal is represented by a single, crude variable: the number of hours 
in which the rat had been deprived of food. Optimum learning results 
from the combination of the appropriate number of hours of de- 
privation with the appropriate rate of applying positive reinforcers, 
i.e. stimuli of the type, one might say, which are apt to deprive the 
organism of its deprivation. Differences between the learning abilities 
of various species, or of age groups within a species, are not considered 



MOTIVATION 



497 



to be relevant to this type of 'functional analysis' of behaviour. By the 
same method of selective reinforcement, by 'baiting' each step in a 
series of steps, pigeons can be trained to describe a figure-eight with 
their heads held high, and students can be trained to select the right 
answer among several alternatives and to punch it into the tape of the 
learning machine — the reinforcement in this case being that the tape 
moves on to the next question. Since each reinforcer is a drive-reducer, 
learning becomes a process of progressive de-motivation. 

Hull did not share Skinner's rigidly positivistic, hypotheses-non-jingo 
attitude. He kept elaborating and modifying his theory until his death 
in 195 1 ; the system has been described as the last and most impressive 
attempt to build an edifice on S.-R. foundations. His emphasis gradually 
shifted from primary to secondary drives and secondary rewards; and 
from need-reduction to drive-stimulus reduction (eating eliminates 
the stimulus of the hunger-drive but not the biological need — which will 
be satisfied only later by digestion). This made the system more 
elastic, yet in spite of these refinements, the primitive drives of hunger, 
sex, avoidance of pain, were considered to be the only motivational 
factors in learning. To quote Hebb's (1949) summing up of Hull's 
theory: 'Its weakest point, and clearest departure from the facts, is in 
the treatment of motivation as biological need. According to the 
theory, the rat in the maze should learn nothing about it until one of 
his responses is accompanied by a decrease of hunger or thirst, or 
escape from electric shock, or some similar reward. In actual fact, when 
he is allowed to run in the maze without reward or punishment, the 
rat learns a good deal about it. It is clear of course that the primitive 
drives of pain, hunger, and sex are often of overwhelming impor- 
tance. We need an approach to motivation that neither minimizes 
these things nor fails to provide for the unrewarded learning 
that also occurs when the animal's belly is full and his sex drive 
satisfied/ 4 

If we turn to the opposite camp — Tolman and the Gestalt psycholo- 
gists — the emphasis shifts from the need-reducing to the goal-seeking 
aspects of behaviour. In classical Gestalt theory, motivation by rewards, 
usually in the form of bananas, is taken for granted; it does not question 
the effect of reward on learning, the dispute is about whether this effect 
is achieved by stamping in or by insight. Similar considerations apply 
to Tolmans sign4earning theory, although he has progressed a con- 
siderable step further by his explicit rejection of reinforcement theories, 
by his emphasis on 'expectancy' and 'purposiveness', on latent learning 



498 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



and 'creative instability'. Lastly, Kurt Lewin's 'psychological field 
theory', with its complex and changing motivation, its concepts of 
'ego-involvement' and levels of aspiration'; above all with its notion 
of striving after 'success' (which is subjective and relative in contrast 
to reinforcement by tangible rewards), played an important part in 
promoting that change of climate which has been increasingly notice- 
able since about 1950. 

Decline of the Reflex 

This new orientation seems to be the cumulative efiect of independent 
developments in several fields, such as: (a) disillusionment regarding 
the utility of the reflex-formula both in neurology and psychology; 

(b) rediscovery of the fact that organisms are not passive masses of 
software reacting to environment, but 'open systems', feeding on 
'negative entropy', engaged in spontaneous activities on all levels, and 

(c) that animals are capable of 'latent' learning in the absence of tan- 
gible rewards, motivated solely by their exploratory drive. 

(a) The physiological concept of the reflex arc, which even Sherring- 
ton considered as no more than a 'useful fiction , has become an 
anachronism * The Pavlovian conditioned reflex was another useful 
fiction which exercised at first a stimulating, then a paralysing effect — 
a phenomenon frequently met in the history of science. In Hebb's 
words: 'Pavlov has deservedly had a great influence on psychology, 
and his theory has not been rejected because it is too physiological but 
because it does not agree with experiment.' There is no need to re- 
capitulate the evidence which has led to this rejection. 5 'Conditioning* 
is still a useful term when applied to induced changes in glandular 
and visceral reactions, but leads to confusion when used in a loose, 
analogical way for other types of learning. 

The last blow to the reflex-arc concept came with the discovery that 
it was impossible to make a precise distinction between 'stimuli' and 
'responses'. As already mentioned (p. 435) not only motor units, but 
also sensory receptors display constant spontaneous activity in the 
absence of external stimulation. 6 External events alter the pattern of 
this spontaneous activity, but this in itself does not yet constitute a 
stimulus. The receptors are under efferent control from higher levels 
of the central nervous system; the acceptance, suppression, or modi- 
fication of the input starts on the periphery, and the centre decides 
what shall constitute a stimulus and what shall not. Even the stretch- 



MOTIVATION 



499 



sensitive receptors in muscle spindles are controlled by efferent fibres 
from the centre. In other words, 'stimuli* and responses' are not one- 
way processes, and cannot be isolated: 'because stimulus and res- 
ponse are correlative and contemporaneous, the stimulus processes 
must be thought of not as preceding the response but rather as guiding 
it to a successful elimination of the incongruity. That is to say, stimu- 
lus and response must be considered as aspects of a feedback loop. . . . 7 
These properties are a far cry from the ubiquitous S.-R. reflex arc 
diagrams that grace (more appropriately one wants to say "disgrace") 
today's texts' (Pribram). 8 

It is historically interesting that an independent but parallel softening- 
up process of the hard and fast S.-R. concept took place at the same 
time in psychology, e.g. in Skinner's and Hull's systems. Skinner was 
careful to state that he used the word 'reflex' not in an anatomical or 
neurological sense but as a purely psychological, descriptive term for 
the 'unit of behaviour'. But his definition of the unit was constantly 
shifting and changing. 'A reflex is not, of course, a theory. It is a fact. 
It is an analytical unit, which makes the investigation of behaviour 
possible. 9 The appearance of smooth curves in dynamic processes 
marks a unique point in the progressive restriction of a preparation, 
and it is to this uniquely determined entity that the term "reflex" may 
be assigned.' 10 

As Miller et al were to comment, to define the reflex in terms of tie 
smoothness of curves is a 'somewhat odd approach'. 11 Yet even so it 
did not work: 'Skinner's "unit appropriate for experimental study" 
turns out, in fact, to have a measure of arbitrariness about it. . . . Some- 
times the functional unit is a simple response, sometimes a complex act, 
sometimes a rate of responding. The unit no longer has the clean dimen- 
sions of a correlation between a class of stimuli and a class of responses 
as implied in the original concept of a reflex. The atom of behaviour 
proves to be evasive/ 12 In the later versions of Skinner's system the 
stimulus no longer even precedes the response: in operant behaviour 
the organism emits responses in search of a stimulus as it were. The 
reflex as a unit of behaviour has evaporated like the physicist's hard 
little lumps of matter. 

Skinner's experimental work had some lasting merits. He was among 
the first to demonstrate that 'intermittent reinforcement'— where only 
some correct responses are rewarded — can be as efFective as the consistent 
rewarding of all correct responses. Humphreys 13 then showed that 
random rewards are actually a superior (more extinction-resistant) 



500 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



form of training — the rat thus trained is less discouraged when the 
reward is withheld, than the rat trained by the consistent-reward 
method. From this there was only one logical step to Tolman's 
theory of motivation by expectancy— a step which Skinner never 
took. 

In Hull's case the 'softening-up' process took a different course. In 
his later years, Hull's attention shifted more and more from primary 
biological drives to secondary drives (from the need' to the 'taste' 
or 'appetite'). These secondary drives he saw manifested in antici- 
patory events — 'fractional antedating goal-responses Rq\ and 'frac- 
tional antedating goal-stimuli S Q \ 'The fractional antedating re- 
action (R G ) with its proprioceptive stimulus correlate (S G ), provides 
for the "automatic (stimulus) guidance of organismic behaviour to 
goals"/ The great importance Hull attached to this postulate is illus- 
trated by his comment: 'Further study of this major automatic device 
presumably will lead to the detailed behavioural understanding of 
thought and reasoning, which constitutes the highest attainment of 

organic evolution. Indeed the R<j > S G mechanism leads in a stricdy 

logical manner into what was formerly regarded as the very heart of 
the psychic: interest, planning, foresight, foreknowledge, expectancy, 
purpose, and so on.' 14 

From a strictly logical point of view, the postulate makes no sense 
— as Hilgard has pointed out in a careful analysis — because S Q acts at 
the same time as a producer of the secondary drive S D and as a secon- 
dary reinforcer which reduces S D . 15 Hilgard put down this confusion 
as a sign of logical weakness in Hull;* yet he did not seem to realize 
that Hull was intuitively on the right track, that the contradiction is 
merely an apparent one, and vanishes if one stops thinking in terms of 
need-reducing motivation. 'That stimulus associated with reinforce- 
ment could become at once both a drive and a reinforcing agent* sounds 
like a contradiction, but makes eminent sense if, getting rid of the 
dreadful terminology, we translate it as follows: 'A rewarding ex- 
perience can at the same time be both an incentive and a reward'; or 
even simpler: *Some pursuits are self-rewarding*. That is the implied 
conclusion of Hull's eighth and last postulate which he regarded as the 
crowning achievement of his system. That he himself did not realize 
this implication only shows that the once useful S.-R. formula had 
by that time become a strait-jacket to thought. 



Hunger, Fear, and Curiosity 



It took natural philosophy nearly a thousand years to rediscover that 
the earth is round; it took experimental psychology nearly fifty years 
to rediscover, after its Dark Ages of need-reducing S.-R. theories, that 
rats and men are pleasure-seeking creatures, that some activities are 
pleasurably self-rewarding, and that exploring the environment, 
solving a chess problem, or learning to play the guitar are among these 
activities. 

An interesting reflection on the spirit of the times was the long, 
impassioned controversy which followed the earth-shaking discovery 
that rats who were allowed to familiarize themselves with the maze 
by running around in it without reward, got quicker to the food-box 
when this was eventually put in than the control rats who ran the 
maze for the first time. How could the rat profit from its previous 
experience in the maze without being rewarded by food or punished 
by electric shock? As Berlyne put it: 'There are plenty of experiments 
to show that latent maze-learning can occur in the rat, which is em- 
barrassing for those whose theories are not built to assimilate it. . . . 
Where does the reinforcement for these responses come from? Several 
writers have considered the possibility that it comes from the reduction 
of curiosity/ 16 Other writers suggested that it came from the drive- 
reducing diminution of boredom. One might as well say that com- 
posing a song is a silence-reducing activity. 

There have been throughout these Dark Ages voices crying in 
the wilderness', but they were dismissed as old-fashioned. Thus 
McDougall (1923) kept reaffirming that the earth was round and that 
striving towards a goal was often more satisfactory than reaching it. 
Allport held that activities originally derived from biological needs 
may become autonomous and self-rewarding: 'The characteristic 
feature of such striving is its resistance to equilibrium: tension is main- 
tained rather than reduced/ 17 Goldstein emphasized the tendency of 
organisms towards 'self-actualization. 18 But the revival of a dynamic 
psychology which reinstated the academic respectability of such terms 
as curiosity, exploratory drive, purpose, only came about when experi- 
mental evidence showed that even in the rat the urge to explore may 
prevail over hunger and fear. 

The experiments of Harlow, Montgomery, Butler, Hudson, etc., 
on rats and monkeys showed — what naturalists had always known — 
that animals are inquisitive, that they have an urge to manipulate, 

501 



502 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



explore, to look what's inside', which is independent from such bio- 
logical drives as hunger, sex, and fear — or, rather, that the exploratory 
drive itself stems from a primary biological need. They showed that 
exploratory behaviour may combine with, or enter the service of, 
hunger or fear, but that it may also compete with and sometimes 
assert itself against them; and that novelty, surprisingness, or puzzle- 
ment are as real incentives to learning as pellets of food dropped into 
the Skinner box. 19 

As far back as 1930 Nissen had found that rats would cross an elec- 
trified grill to reach a maze which contained nothing but some unusual 
objects; he concluded that an exploratory urge did exist— 'a biogenic 
drive to explore, perceive, to know'. 20 Experiments by Hudson, 
Berlyne, and Walley, in which rats were punished for approaching 
some novel visual pattern, led them to conclude that 'objects that have 
become associated with danger are often explored before they are 
shunned*. 21 Carr and Williams 22 showed that the exploratory drive 
varies with heredity and environment: hooded rats explore more than 
black rats, and black rats more than Albino rats. Montgomery and 
Barnett 23 showed that wild rats are more frightened, tame rats more 
attracted by novelty; Thompson and Heron 24 that young animals 
are more curious than old ones, and — as one would expect — that 
female rats are more inquisitive than males. 25 Confronted with novel 
situations, hungry rats interrupt their feeding to explore their surround- 
ings; 26 but rats whose cerebral cortex has been removed in part, while 
still capable of learning to run a maze to get at food, show a diminished 
tendency to exploration. They 'do not evince the preference for a 
variable path over a standardized path that is characteristic of a normal 
rat, except when the variable path is the shorter. Brain-damaged rats 
likewise show less variability of route in a Dashiell maze.' 27 Yet, as 
Lashley's rats have shown, even depriving the creature of substantial 
portions of its brain does not make it conform to the S.-R. ideal. 

On higher levels of the animal kingdom the evidence becomes less 
monotonous and depressing. What a relief to get out of the Skinner 
box and to read Lorenz's description of curiosity battling with fear 
in one of his birds: 28 

'A young raven, confronted with a new object, which may be a 
camera, an old bottle, a stuffed polecat, or anything else first reacts 
with escape responses. He will fly up to an elevated perch and, from 
this point of vantage, stare at the object literally for hours. After this, 



MOTIVATION 



503 



he will begin to approach the object very gradually, maintaining all 
the while a maximum of caution and the expressive attitude of 
intense fear. He will cover the last distance from the object hopping 
sideways with half-raised wings, in the utmost readiness to flee. At 
last, he will deliver a single fearful blow with his powerful beak at 

the object and forthwith fly back to his safe perch ' In the end 'he 

will grab [the object] with one foot, peck at it, try to tear off pieces, 
insert his bill into any existing cleft and then pry apart his mandibles 
with considerable force. Finally, if the object is not too big the raven 
will carry it away, push it into a convenient hole and cover it with 
some inconspicuous material.' 

As for primates, we can comfortably fall back on Darwin's Descent 
of Man: 

'All animals feel Wonder, and many exhibit Curiosity. They sometimes 
suffer from this latter quality, as when the hunter plays antics and thus 
attracts them; I have witnessed this with deer, and so it is with the 
wary chamois, and with, some kinds of wild-ducks. Brehm gives a 
curious account of the instinctive dread, which his monkeys exhibited, 
for snakes; but their curiosity was so great that they could not desist 
from occasionally satiating their horror in a most human fashion, by 
lifting up the lid of the box in which the snakes were kept.' Darwin 
was 'so much surprised at this account* that he proceeded to the 
monkey-house at the Zoological Gardens armed with a stuffed snake, 
a dead fish, a mouse, and a live turtle: 

'The excitement thus caused was one of the most curious spectacles 
which I ever beheld.' The greatest success was the turtle. The monkeys 

'showed unbounded astonishment, as well as some fear This was 

displayed by their remaining motionless, staring intently with widely 
opened eyes, their eyebrows being often moved up and down. Their 
faces seemed somewhat lengthened. They occasionally raised them- 
selves on their hindlegs to get a better view. They often retreated a few 
feet, and then turning their heads over one shoulder, again stared in- 
tently In the course of a few minutes some of the monkeys ven- 
tured to approach and touch the turtle. ... I then placed a live snake 
in a paper bag, with the mouth loosely closed, in one of the larger 
compartments. One of the monkeys immediately approached, cau- 
tiously opened the bag a little, peeped in, and instantly dashed away. 
Then I witnessed what Brehm has described, for monkey after monkey, 
with head raised high and turned on one side, could not resist taking a 



504 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



momentary peep into the upright bag, at the dreadful object lying 
quiedy at the bottom/ 29 

This was written half a century before Kohler's Mentality of Apes 
was translated into English— with a delay of eight years after the 
appearance of the German original. 30 It had the effect of something 
like a bombshell on American psychology, in which Pavlov and 
Watson were all the rage. Yet even Kohler, though he attacked 
Thorndike, remained essentially conservative as far as motivation is 
concerned; it took another quarter-century for a new crop of experi- 
mentalists to discover, in the 1950s, that the exploration of novelty, 
the manipulation of objects, the dismantling and reassembling of 
complex manual puzzles, and even scribbling and drawing were self- 
rewarding and self-arousing activities. 

'Those who have had opportunities to observe monkeys and apes at 
close hand for prolonged periods invariably dwell on their addiction 
to looking, mauling, prodding, licking, and generally squeezing every 
drop of possible entertainment from whatever crosses their path.' 31 
Particularly revealing is the fact that Rhesus monkeys who have learned 
to dismantle a complex manual puzzle of interlocking pieces performed 
better when there was no food reward put inside the puzzle than when 
they knew that there was one. In the second case they got impatient 
and tried short-cuts; in the first case they practised disinterestedly, 
'V art pour Vart\ 32 

The Exploratory Drive 

The cumulative evidence of these and similar experiments led Harlow 
to die conclusion: 

'There are logical reasons why a drive-reduction theory of learn- 
ing, a theory which emphasizes the role of internal, physiological- 
state motivation is entirely untenable as a motivational theory of 
learning. 

'The condition of strong drive is mimical to all but very limited 

aspects of learning—the learning the ways to reduce tension The 

hungry child is a most uncurious child, but after he has eaten and 
become thoroughly sated, his curiosity and all the learned responses 
associated with his curiosity take place.' 33 

Montgomery came to similar conclusions, which he put into the 
laconic formula: 'Exploratory behaviour is motivated by the ex- 
ploratory drive.' 



MOTIVATION 



505 



These clarion calls of a new generation of experimentalists in fact 
echoed the earlier Voices in the wIlderness , — such as Woodworm's: 
'To see, to hear — to see clearly, to hear distinctly — moment by mo- 
ment, such concrete, immediate motives dominate the life of relation 
with the environment.' 34 In the meantime, however, these 'old- 
fashioned' views had received added, powerful support from neuro- 
physiology. Lindsley (195 1), Hebb (1955) and others have shifted 
their attention from tension-reducing, stabilizing processes in the 
nervous system to the supposedly arousing, attention-sharpening 
functions of certain structures in the midbrain — the so-called 'reticular 
activating system', RAS. Although these theories are still controversial, 
parallel studies on sensory deprivation have dramatically revealed the 
deleterious effects of protracted stimulus-starvation, and the organism's 
need for more or less constant stimulation, or at least a steady inflow 
of information — a hunger for experience and thirst for excitation 
probably as basic as hunger and thirst themselves. Instead of respond- 
ing passively to the environment, 'human beings and higher animals 
spend most of their time in a state of relatively high arousal and . . . 
expose themselves to arousing stimulus situations with great eager- 
ness'. 35 Two thousand years ago Juvenal had said much the same: 
'Duos tantum res anxius optat, j Partem et circenses. 9 

Berlyne 36 has made a systematic survey of the manifestations of the 
exploratory drive on various levels — from orientation reflexes to 
artistic and scientific curiosity. At the bottom of the ladder we have 
Pavlov's 'investigatory' or 'what is it?' reflex. 'It is this reflex', Pavlov 
wrote in a famous passage, 'which brings about the immediate res- 
ponse in men and animals to the slightest changes in the world around 
them, so that they immediately orientate their appropriate receptor- 
organ in accordance with the perceptible quality in the agent bringing 
about the change, making full investigation of it.' 37 From true reflexes 
such as dilatation of the pupil and automatic scanning, we ascend to 
oculo-motor responses, movements of the head or the whole body 
towards the stimulating phenomenon: animals prick their ears, tense 
their muscles, sniff the air 'musingly'. Next comes 'locomotor ex- 
ploration' which 'appears to be universal among higher vertebrates 
and present to some degree in other branches of the animal kingdom'; 
yet, as Berlyne ruefully remarks: 'It has been studied systematically in 
rather few species. By far the greater part of the relevant literature is 
concerned with the rat.' According to Darchen, 38 even the cockroach 
is capable of disinterested latent learning, prompted by sheer curiosity; 



506 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



while kittens, puppies, and young chimps seem to spend a major portion 
of their time in locomotive exploration. Lastly, we come to 'investi- 
gatory' or 'mquisitive' behaviour, ranging from Darwin's monkey who 
cannot refrain from peeping into the snake-infested Pandora's box, to 
the 'insatiable curiosity' of the artist and explorer. 

Thus neuro-physiological considerations, laboratory work with 
animals, and the observations of ethologists of the Lorenz-Tinbergen 
school, all seem to converge in the same direction. Even the embryo- 
logical studies of Coghill (pp. 430 £F.) and Weiss (p. 434 seq.), with their 
emphasis on spontaneous, intrinsic activities on all levels of the organic 
hierarchy, lend indirect support to the primacy of the exploratory 
drive. The lesson of fifty years of rats-in-mazes has been summed up, 
e.g. by Thacker in the statement that 'motivation for learning is 
central and neural . . . organized and proliferated cognitive structure 
itself is the goal towards which learning moves'. 39 In other words, 
the motivation for teaming is to team. 

Thorpe, for all his habitual caution, has gone even further. He 
starts with a rhetorical question: *And so it becomes important to 
consider how far there is evidence of learning motivated by a general 
drive quite independent of the motivation of particular instincts'; 40 
and he concludes that 'there is now substantial and precise evidence for 
a general drive in a number of animals, and this can be looked upon 
as an indication of a primary motivation which to some extent, how- 
ever slight, is superior to the governing centres of any of the instincts 
or of their combinations, and finds its most characteristic expression 
in exploratory behaviour in all its various forms'. 41 

In his monograph on The Nature of Explanation (1943), which has 
inspired a great many neurologists and computer-theorists, the 
Cambridge psychologist K. J. Craik put forward the idea that the 
function of the organism's nervous system is to set up a symbolic 
model of the external world: 'The brain . . . imitates or models 
external processes. The function of such symbolization is plain. If the 
organism carries a "small-scale model" of external reality and of its 
own possible actions within its head, it is able to try out various alter- 
natives, conclude which is the best of them, react to future situations 
before they arise, utilize the knowledge of past events in dealing with 
the present and future, and every way to react in a much fuller, safer, 
and more competent manner to the emergencies which face it.' 42 

To extract information from the chaotic environment is as vital 
to the organism as it is essential for it to extract specific forms of 



MOTIVATION 



507 



energy from sunlight and food. If we assume this to be an inherent 
tendency of all living organisms, then we must also assume the exis- 
tence of an inherent primary drive to explore the environment for 
relevant information. 

Thus the organism functions not merely by responding to the en- 
vironment, but by asking it questions. The main incentive to its ex- 
ploratory activities are novelty, surprise, conflict, uncertainty.* The 
exploratory drive may combine with, or be instrumental to, other 
drives — sex, nutrition, anxiety. But in its purest form — in play, latent 
learning, unrewarded problem-solving — 'stimuli' and responses' are 
undistinguishable parts of the same feedback loop along which 
excitation is running in a circle like a kitten chasing its tail. 'The 
scientist', wrote AJlport, f by the very nature of his commitment, 
creates more and more questions, never fewer. Indeed the measure of 
our intellectual maturity, one philosopher suggests, is our capacity to 
feel less and less satisfied with our answers to better problems.' 43 

We have thus established a broader base for the scientist's motiva- 
tion as discussed earlier on (Book One, XI). The exploratory drive may 
combine with the self-transcending mysticism of a Kepler or with the 
self-asserting vanity of a Galileo. Each original artist has an element of 
the explorer in him: the poet does not 'manipulate words' as Watson 
thought, he explores the emotive and descriptive potentialities of 
language; the painter is engaged, throughout his life, in learning to see. 

NOTES 

To p. 496. Ernest Jones says in his biography: 'Freud partook in much of the 
prudishness of his time, when allusions to lower limbs were improper*. He then 
gives several examples — such as Freud 'sternly forbidding* his fianoie to stay 
'with an old friend, recently married, who, as she delicately put it, "had married 
before her wedding" ' (Jones, 1953, Vol. I, p. 142). 

To p. 498. "The simple reflex is probably a purely abstract conception, 
because all parts of the nervous system are connected together and no part of it is 
probably ever capable of reaction without affecting and being affected by 
various other parts ... the simple reflex is a convenient, if not a probable, fiction* 
(Sherrington, 1906, p. 8). 

To p. 500. 'His thinking was particular, not general. When he thought of 
secondary drive, he thought of . . . fear or anxiety. When he thought of secon- 
dary reinforcement, he thought of such tilings as . . . tokens substituting for food* 
(Hilgard, 1958, P- 177). 

Top. 507. Uncertainty is more arousing than certainty — as witnessed by the 
universal passion for gambling which coincided with the consolidation of the 



508 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



British Welfare State. Its rudiments can be found even in the rat and pigeon— as 
Skinner himself pointed out — when rewards are given rarely and irregularly; 
this treatment induces the creature to go on trying for an astonishingly long time 
without a single reward— just as Britons will fill in week after week their foot- 
ball coupons. 



IX 

PLAYING AND PRETENDING 



Logically every book on learning theory ought to have between 
the sections on 'innate behaviour* and 'acquired behaviour* a 
chapter on 'learning through play' — or, at least, on 'ludic 
behaviour' (from ludere, to play) — a term coined by Berlyne, pre- 
sumably to make the subject sound more respectable. The role of play 
in the learning and practice of skills is too obvious to naturalists and 
pedagogues to need stressing; yet play was another stepchild of the 
Psychology of the Dark Ages. Its connotations of curiosity, explora- 
tion, frivolousness and joie de vivre did not appeal to the spirit of the 
times; its unpredictability did not fit the S.-R. schema; above all, its 
self-reinforcing motivation, dissociated from the primary physio- 
logical needs, stood in flagrant contradiction to any drive-reducing 
theory. Thus the concept of 'ludic behaviour* was objectionable on 
the same grounds as the concept of the exploratory drive; the former 
appears in fact to be the purest manifestation of the latter. 

Difficulties of Definition 

A further reason for this neglect may have been the difficulty of de- 
fining 'play'* without making the definition circular. By way of 
eHmination, let us try to distinguish between true play and vacuum 
activities during maturation. A young bird toys with straws and 
feathers 'aimlessly* before the other action-patterns of the nest- 
building instinct have matured; displays of fragmentary mating be- 
haviour before sexual maturity fall into the same category. Some of 
these activities look playful in the sense of serving no apparent pur- 
pose (although in fact they may be useful as 'practice runs' in develop- 
ing a skill); yet they can hardly be regarded as true play because they 

509 



510 THE ACT OF CREATION 

display all the rigidity of fixed action-patterns. They are performances 
of isolated bits of the animal's built-in repertory, and thus contrary 
to appearances, in the direct service of 'primary biological needs' in 
the classic sense. This implies that 'true play' is dissociated from those 
needs; that 'it does not have a biological function that we easily 
recognize'. 1 But precisely at this point the danger of circular definitions 
comes in: to say that play does not serve a primary need reopens the 
whole question of what needs, drives, motivations, should be called 
'primary'. Thus, for instance, in Drever's Dictionary of Psychology play 
is defined as an 'activity, which may be physical or mental, existing 
apparently for its own sake, or having for the individual as its main aim 
the pleasure which the activity itself yields; usually involving also a 
detachment from serious aims and ends . . .'. If we then ask 'What are 
serious aims and ends?' the answer is obviously: those which are not 
playful. The way out of the vicious etch is to 'take play seriously', 
as an activity with a definite 'primary biological function — viz. to 
give free rein to the exploratory drive. But such a view can only be 
held once it is recognized that the exploratory drive itself originates in 
a 'primary need' equal in importance to the others. 

It seems to be wrong, however, to go to the opposite extreme and 
stretch the meaning of the word 'play' so as to cover all manifestations 
of the exploratory drive—as Berlyne seems to do when he says that 
'in human beings, ludic behaviour includes everything that is classi- 
fied as recreation, entertainment, or "idle curiosity", as well as art, 
philosophy, and pure (as distinct from applied) science. . . .' 2 This, of 
course, is a matter of definitions, but I think it more expedient to use 
the word play in a more precise and restricted sense, which is closer 
to its colloquial usage. A small child, kicking a ball about, plays; a 
professional football *player' works hard for a living. When the 
monkey takes the puzzle apart and puts it together again, he 'plays'; 
when there is food inside the puzzle he Strives'. Two chess masters 
may play a friendly cafe game; in a tournament they compete. The 
examples show how fluid the borderlines are, yet the principle is clear: 
the degree of * playfulness' in an action decreases in proportion as the ex-* 
ploratory drive is adulterated by other drives; or, to put it differently: as 
the self-arousing and self-rewarding nature of the activity, charac- 
teristic of the exploratory drive, yields to striving for specific rewards. 
This foreshadows a similarly continuous, graded relationship between 
the dynamics of latent and reinforced learning, to be discussed later. 



The Ludic and the Ludicrous 



It follows from the above that play can only arise at an evolutionary 
level or in such special situations, where the organism has been partially 
liberated from the tyranny of 'primary needs' in the traditional sense, 
and can afford to 'take time off* to play. This happens among animals 
where the young mature slowly and enjoy prolonged parental pro- 
tection and care; under the sheltered conditions of domestication and 
captivity; and in human history, of course, with the increase of security 
against the hazards of the natural and social environment. To quote 
Thorpe again: 'The prolonged childhood of the human species [has] 
been of prime importance in the process of freeing appetitive behaviour 
from the primary needs. This and man's growing mastery of his 
environment have been the essential first steps not only for play but 
for all those activities which transcend mere maintenance and which 
underlie the mental and spiritual development of man; activities 
which, though originating in "play", have produced real advantages 
in knowledge and comprehension, of the scheme of things. . . ,' 3 

A related process of emancipation, namely the detachment of reason- 
ing from emotion, gave rise, as we saw, to humour. Man's emergent 
ability to perceive a thing or event simultaneously in two incompatible 
mental contexts enabled him to take the step from the 'ludic' to the 
'ludicrous'. The historic link between the two is probably reflected in 
the word 'ludicrum' — stage play. The actor's or bard's pretence of 
being himself and somebody else at the same time was at the origin of 
tragedy and epic; a similar act of magic— carving or painting a thing 
which is meant to be something else — was the origin of representational 
art. These, of course, are activities on an incomparably higher level 
than the play of kittens and birds; yet as Lorenz has pointed out, both 
imitation and pretence occur already on the animal level. When 
puppies fight in play, they do not hurt each other or their masters; 
they conform to certain 'rules of the game'. Whether these have their 
phylogenetical origin in the ritualized fights of their wild ancestors or 
whether they are acquired by social learning, the fact remains that such 
fights are 'not in earnest' and necessitate 'bringing in the "higher" or 
more psychological concept of "pretence" '. 4 

Equally suggestive is the so-called 'sub-song' of birds. As distinct 
from the true or full song which is fixed and species-specific, the sub- 
song is 'a somewhat amorphous, rambling utterance'. 6 Birds indulge 
in it when their 'primary needs' are not pressing — before the mating 

511 



512 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



season or in captivity — as a kind of vocal play which might either 
represent practice for the true song, or else a form of 'pretending': 
some birds which never imitate alien species in their true song do 
so in their sub-song. Thorpe compares this vocal imitation to the 
process by which human infants learn to speak — from 'amorphous' 
babblings to the imitation of sounds produced by their elders (echo- 
lalia). Thus imitation, pretence, as well as art, seem to have their pre- 
cursors in the playful activities of the higher mammalia and birds. 

To sum up: 'exploratory behaviour is motivated by the exploratory 
drive'. In play, its purest form, it is generalized, non-specific, and in- 
discriminate — a puppy let into an unfamiliar room rushes to and fro, 
sniffs at every corner, picks up any object, beside itself with excite- 
ment under the incentive of novelty. On the other hand, when the 
exploratory drive is canalized towards more specific targets, it results 
in latent learning and, still higher up, in problem-solving. While play 
is self-rewarding, in problem-solving the search itself may also be self- 
rewarding to varying degrees, but the principal reward is finding the 
solution. In this broader sense, of course, the law of effect remains 
valid; but the reward, the pleasure derived from success, is specific to 
the exploratory drive — its 'consummatory act' as it were — and not a 
premium extraneous to its nature. If the problem was an easy one, the 
solution may be both a reward and an incentive to have a go at another 
problem at once; if the drive was obstructed, involving stress, the 
solution is tension-reducing. And, of course, the solution may carry 
supplementary rewards — the carrot of satisfied ambition, for instance. 

In laboratory experiments the animal's exploratory possibilities are 
restricted, and artificial motivations replace the drive as it operates in 
freedom. At the same time, animals in the laboratory are induced to 
pay attention to, and discriminate between, stimuli which under 
normal circumstances would be biologically irrelevant to them; or 
else to perform motor actions (e.g. Skinner's ping-pong playing 
pigeons) which are outside their natural repertory. Tricks of this kind 
can be taught only by stamping in; and attempts to build a universal 
theory of learning on such methods carry the danger of confusing a 
travelling circus with Plato's Academy. 

NOTE 

To p. 500. The Concise Oxford Dictionary gives no less than thirty-four 
meanings of the word. 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



I must now switch from animal to man, and later back again. The 
manner in which animals learn holds important lessons for man; 
but in order to interpret the data the experimenter must make 
certain minimum assumptions regarding the animals' experiences; and, 
whether he is aware of it or not, these assumptions are based on his 
own human experience. We talk about the animal's pain-reaction or 
fear-reaction because we have experienced pain and fear; we interpret 
certain signs as meaning that the animal is alert or apprehensive by in- 
ferences which are often unconscious and contain an unavoidably 
anthropomorphic element. Even Lloyd Morgan's canon acknowledged 
this; it merely said that one should not be more anthropomorphic than 
one could help.* 

Now, learning involves perception and memory; and since we know 
incomparably more about both in man than in cats or rats, we must 
discuss some aspects of man's perceptual and sensory-motor skills 
before we turn to learning in animals. Instead of the over-worked 
province of visual perception, I shall start, for a change, on hearing. 

Screening the Input 

It has been said that visitors to Stalin had to go through seventeen suc- 
cessive screenings: at the outer gate of the Kremlin compound, at 
several inner gates, and so forth, until the last corridor and the last 
door leading to the inner sanctum. *Inputs* which aspire to become 
'stimuli' apparently suffer a similar fate. Where hearing is concerned, 
the brain's stimulus-screening activity starts in the ear. Efferent, in- 
hibitory fibres from higher centres to the cochlea of the cat were dis- 
covered by Galambos in 1956. In a series of remarkable experiments 1 

513 



514 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the cat's auditory nerve was tapped and wired to an amplifier, so that 
impulses passing from ear to brain were direcdy recorded. The im- 
pulses were caused by the clicking of a metronome. But the moment 
a mouse in a glass jar was shown to the cat the firings in the auditory 
nerve were diminished or ceased altogether: the cat was turning a 
'deaf ear* on the metronome. The point of the experiment was to 
show that the process of stimulus-selection is centrally controlled, but 
sets in at the periphery— the outer gate of the Kremlin compound. 

Attitude and expectation — the pattern of the behavioural matrix to 
which the organism is attuned at the time — determine what shall con- 
stitute a stimulus and what shall not. On a happy family evening, when 
people are talking while the radio is playing, junior is crying, and the 
dog is begging to be let out, each of these simultaneous inputs may be 
perceived as 'signal' and the rest as 'noise'. In audition, at least, the 
'figure-background relation' seems to be more complicated than the 
Gestalt school suggests; it is not something innate in perceptual organi- 
zation, but dependent on past experience and present state of mind. 
Women were known to sleep soundly through an air-raid but to 
awake at the slightest cry of their babies; people deeply asleep show 
sharp EEG reactions when their own name, or the name of a girl- 
friend, is read out in a list of other 'background' names. 2 

The point has also an indirect bearing on the controversy whether 
discrimination is based on the 'absolute' or relational properties of 
stimuli. 3 The answer seems to be, briefly, that absolute stimuli do not 
exist — short of sticking a knife into somebody. Yet even on the 
primitive level of pain, the matrix influences perception— as wit- 
nessed by the General in the American Civil War who, in the heat of 
battle, did not notice that his middle finger was shot away; not to 
mention anaesthesia by hypnosis in dentistry and child-birth— or the 
even more remarkable phenomena of hysterical conversion blindness. 

Thus the higher centres exercise a selective influence on sensation and 
perception; those aspects of the input which are irrelevant will be treated 
as noise, and forgotten 'without leaving a trace'. But the criteria of rele- 
vance depend on the 'rules of the game' which the organism is playing 
at the time. 

Stripping the Input 

Selective control of the input is the first stage in the process of ex- 
tracting information from the chaotic noises and other sensations which 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



515 



bombard the organism's receptors; without it, the mind would be in 
a kind of Brownian motion. This first stage is followed by the proces- 
sing of the input in a series of relaying operations, each of them designed 
to strip the input of what appears to be irrelevant—according to the 
criteria of relevance which operate along that input-channel. One 
might call this a process of de-particularization. It is a clumsy word, but 
it conveys what is really implied in the terms 'generalization or 'ab- 
straction', with their multiple connotations. 

The most familiar examples of 'de-particularization' are, of course, 
the visual constancies. The triangle, or the letter "W", is stripped of the 
irrelevancies of retinal position, size, etc. Thanks to colour constancy 
the accidents of light and shadow are discarded; thanks to size con- 
stancy, my moving hand does not seem to shrink or grow — changes in 
perspective size are 'dis-regarded' by the regard. Yet the criteria of 
relevance and irrelevance depend, even in these cases of apparendy 
spontaneous perception, to a considerable degree on interpretative 
frames — on perceptual matrices acquired by past experience. When 
an object of the appearance of a tennis ball is inflated against a homo- 
geneous background, it will be seen as if it were retailing its size and 
approaching the observer. 4 This is different from size constancy be- 
cause in this case the observer has to accommodate his eyes and make 
them converge at a closer range so that the ball gets out of focus and 
should be seen as a blurred double image. Yet the knowledge that 
tennis balls behave reasonably and do not grow into footballs some- 
how manages to compensate for this, and to discard the anomalies in 
the situation as irrelevant noise. To quote Bartlett once more: 'Even 
the most elementary perceptions have the character of inferential 
constructions/ The Baconian ideal of observation without theorizing 
is undermined by the mechanism of observation itself. Perception is- 
polluted by implied hypotheses. To look, to listen, to taste, means to 
ask questions; and mostly they are leading questions. 

To obtain a more detached view of the living organism's methods 
of coding and storing its experiences, let me make a naive comparison 
with a typical engineering procedure. Exairiining a modern gramo- 
phone record with a niagnifying glass, you see a spiral curve with 
lateral oscillations of varying amplitude and spacing — a curve where 
the abscissa represents time, and the ordinate the amplitude of the 
needle's oscillations. And yet this two-dimensional curve, with a 
single independent variable, can reproduce any sequence of sounds, 
from the Sermon on the Mount to the Ninth Symphony performed by 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



orchestra and choir, including the buzzing of a fly and a cough in the 
audience. In fact the entire range of human knowledge and experience 
could be expressed by the function of this one independent variable, so 
that one is tempted to ask why the nervous system does not produce 
engrams in this simple type of code, instead of the incomparably more 
complicated methods it uses. The answer is, that a 'linear* memory 
trace of this type would be completely useless for the purposes of 
analysing, recognizing, and matching new inputs, and for working 
out the appropriate responses. It would merely represent the 'blooming, 
buzzing confusion of pure sensation sans organization which, in the 
words of William James, is the new-born infant's world. Before it 
can be more or less permanently stored, the input must be processed, 
dismantled, and reassembled in various ways, which the following 
examples may serve to illustrate. 



Dismantling and Reassembling 

Let the input be fifty instruments and fifty voices performing a choral 
part of Beethoven's Ninth. On the gramophone record, and in the air- 
waves which make the ear-drum vibrate, the pitch, timbre, and loudness 
of the individual voices and instruments have all been superimposed 
on each other— scrambled together into a single variable pulse. The 
individuality of soprano, flute, viola, is lost in the process; it requires 
a human nervous system to reconstitute it. 

The pulse is transmitted and amplified by the bones of the middle 
ear and enters through the oval window into the cochlea. Here the 
basilar membrane, based in viscous fluid, starts the process of un- 
scrambling the acoustic omelette. This is done, partly at least, by a 
kind of Fourrier-analysis of the oscillatory curve, which breaks it down 
into its spectrum of basic frequencies.* The parallel fibres of the basilar 
membrane form a kind of spiral harp; each fibre responds to a specific 
frequency. This analysing mechanism operates over a range of twenty 
to twenty thousand cycles per second, and auditory discrimination 
varies from about 0.05 at low frequencies to 0.02$ at 2,000 c/s (Piccolo 
flute). Each frequency has its separate 'place' on the spiral membrane. 
Each place' is presumed to be connected by a separate group of fibres, 
rwuiing through several relay stations, to a presumably fixed location 
in the primary reception area in the auditory cortex — area 22. 

But this mechanism of transmission by fixed pathways and non- 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



517 



specific impulses is only half of the story; the other half is transmission 
of the lower frequencies by Volleys* in a bundle of fibres firing in turn 
at the specific frequency of the input. 5 The details of both theories are 
still controversial, but the available evidence indicates that they com- 
plement each other. We have, then, here one more instance of the 
complementary character of two types of nervous function: conduction 
by specific pathways, and conduction by specific signals over equi- 
potential pathways. 

We now have our fifty singers and fifty instruments decomposed 
into a constantly changing mosaic pattern of excitations in area 22 
where each point (or region or circuit) 6 represents the frequency of 
one pure tone, and in some form also its intensity — regardless of the 
instrument or voice in which it originated. This state of affairs bears no 
resemblance to any conceivable neural model based on S.-R. theory 
— or on the Gestalt physiology of Kohler and Koff ka.* In fact the 
whole physiological theory of Gestalt, and many of its psychological 
postulates, break down when we come to audition. This is not sur- 
prising since Kohler concentrated entirely on visual perception; and 
in the seven hundred-odd pages of KofFka's Principles of Gestalt Psy- 
chology exactly one page (p. 200) is devoted to 'other (than visual) 
senses'. Even on this one page, the only reference to audition is the 
statement that 'sound' and 'stillness' have a reversible figure-back- 
ground relation. 

At the auditory projection area we must assume the dismantling 
process to end and the reassembling to start. When we listen to the 
symphony we do not hear an ensemble of the pure tones into which 
it has been broken up in the cochlea, but an ensemble of individual 
instruments and voices: that is, of organized sub-wholes. The individual 
timbre of an instrument is determined by its overtones— the series of 
partials which accompany the fundamental, and the energy-distribu- 
tion of them. By superimposition of the sine curves of the partials, we 
obtain the periodic curve characteristic for each instrument. When we 
identify the sound of a violin or flute by picking out and bracketing 
together its partials— which were 'drowned' among thousands of other 
partials in the air-pressure wave — we have achieved 'timbre constancy', 
comparable to visual figure constancy. This, of course, is based on past 
experience and involves an act of recognition by the 'trained ear* of 
instruments previously heard in isolation, 



'Coloured Filters 9 



Since all but the most elementary perceptions interact with past ex- 
perience, it seems a rather unsound procedure to discuss perception 
divorced from the problem of memory. The question, then, is how 
the 'trace' was originally acquired which enables me to recognize an 
instrument or voice on subsequent occasions. Let us assume that I am 
hearing an exotic instrument for the first time, and that I am interested 
at the moment only in its timbre, not in the melody played on it 
(which, in the case of a Japanese koto or samisen, would be above my 
head anyway). As I am listening, the mathematical relations between 
the partials remain constant and enduring, whereas their pitch and 
loudness are changing all the time. This stable and enduring relation- 
pattern (the fixed ratios between the part-frequencies) will be treated 
by my nervous system, which is processing the input, as relevant, 
whereas the changes in the relata (the absolute frequencies) are dis- 
carded as irrelevant. When this filtering-out process is completed, the 
input will have been finally stripped of all irrelevant detail, according 
to the demands of parsimony, and reduced to its invariant pattern — 
to formation' purified of noise*. If an input has undergone these 
transformations and was permitted to progress this far without being 
blocked somewhere on its way (as, for instance, the voices of irrelevant 
strangers at a cocktail party are) then it will tend to leave a lasting 
'trace* — which will enable the nervous system to recognize in future the 
same voice or instrument. 

We have witnessed, as it were, the formation of the code of a new 
perceptual skill. The organism feeds on negative entropy; in com- 
munication theory, entropy* becomes noise*. The sensorium ab- 
stracts information from the chaotic environment as the mitochondria 
extract, by a series of dismantling and reassembling processes, a specific 
form of energy from food. The abstracting and recording of informa- 
tion involves, as we have just seen, the sacrifice of details which are 
filtered out as irrelevant in a given context. But what is considered as 
irrelevant in one context, may be relevant in another; and vice versa. 
We can recognize an instrument regardless of the tune played on it; 
but we can also recognize a tune regardless of the instrument on which 
it is played. The tune is abstracted and recorded in a memory-trace 
de-particularized of timbre; timbre is recorded de-particularized of 
tune. Thus the filtering-out of redundancies as the input is relayed 
from periphery to centre does not proceed along a single channel, but 

518 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



519 



along several channels, each with its series of filters of different colour, 
as it were. The different colours represent the criteria of relevance in 
different perceptual hierarchies. Each hierarchy analyses the input 
according to its own criteria of relevance; but the loss of detail in- 
curred in the process of memory-formation along a single channel is 
partly counteracted by the fact that information rejected as irrelevant 
by its coloured filters may be admitted as relevant by another channel 
belonging to a difierent hierarchy. We shall see that this principle of 
multi-dimensional analysis is of basic importance in the phenomena of 
recognition and recall. 

A Digression on Engrams 

The neurophysiological problems of memory are beyond the scope of 
this book, but the following remarks may help to forestall possible 
misunderstandings. Perceptual codes of the type which enables us to 
recognize an instrument are devices which analyse complex acoustic 
inputs by some unknown process of 'matching' or 'resonance'. The 
quotes indicate that these words are used as metaphors only; the 
process must of course be incomparably more complicated than 
acoustic or electric resonance. What matters is that a memory-trace 
cannot be visualized as a mechanical record like a gramophone groove, 
'stamped* into the brain and activated by specific pathways. Such an 
arrangement would be as useless for purposes of auditory analysis as 
it would be useless for the visual recognition of shapes to have an 
archive of photographic engrams. Instead of this, we must hypothesize 
some kind of 'attunement' of a cluster or clusters of neurons, with a 
hierarchic ogranization and containing sub-wholes which are equi- 
potential in their response to one specific pattern of excitation and to 
that pattern only. Pringle 7 assumed that memory-traces function like 
'coupled resonators*; Hyden's 8 theory of RNA changes which deter- 
mine selective responsiveness to frequency-modulation sequences of 
excitation seems more plausible. Whatever the mechanism is, it must 
combine the principle of fixed but partly equipotential spatial con- 
nections, with selective responses to specific excitation patterns, to 
account for the hierarchic organization of perceptual, conceptual, and 
motor skills. Weiss' excitation clang was an approach in that direction. 
Hebb's phase sequences in neuron assemblies was another. The Pitt- 
McCullough model of a scanning analyser to account for figure con- 
stancies should show that basically similar principles can be applied in 



520 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



vision as in audition to the problem of analysing and matching the 
input. 

The matrix of a complex skill — such as the maze-running skill of 
Lashley's rats— may be no more 'localized* than the programme of a 
political party is localized by the addresses of all members who adhere 
to it. If some members or groups of members are ehniinated, other 
groups may take over. Simpler and more primitive matrices, however, 
are perhaps rather like the professional guilds of craftsmen concentrated 
in one area of a medieval town; if that area is destroyed, the skill is 
lost. 

Tracing a Melody 

We have seen that recognition of a voice or instrument is based on an 
invariant relation (the fixed ratios between partials or formants) which 
has been extracted from the variable relata. Once the instrument is 
perceived as a recognizable whole, the relation becomes a relatum — 
e.g. 'a violin* — regardless whether a verbal symbol is attached to it 
or not. This relatum then enters into relations with the sound of other 
instruments, which are analysed on higher levels according to the 
criteria of more complex rules of the game — harmony, melodic, and 
contrapuntal form— in which several perceptual hierarchies participate. 

A tune is defined by rhythm and pitch. Rhythm derives from the 
hierarchic organization of beat-cum-accentinto measure, measure into 
phrase. To qualify as a tune, the pitch-variation sequence must con- 
form to certain codes of modality, key, harmony. These codes must 
also be represented in the listener's perceptual organization, otherwise 
there would be no musical experience, only the sensation of a medley 
of sounds— as when a European listens for the first time to Chinese 
opera. The melody itself has the structural coherence of a closed figure 
as distinct from an open, linear chain. It is either 'taken in' as a whole 
in the specious present, or learned by the integration of sub-wholes, 
that is of entire phrases — but never by chaining note to note in the 
m a nn er of learning nonsense-syllables (though even these tend to form 
patterns). A chain of notes could not be transposed from one key or 
instrument to another; nor recognized after transposition. 

A tune is a temporal pattern of notes in a given scale. The notes are 
the relata; by humming it in a different key, or playing it on a different 
instrument, the relata are changed but the relation remains invariant 
in all transformations. On a higher level, the tune as a whole again 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



521 



becomes a relatum which enters into relations with other tonal pat- 
terns; or with itself in symmetrical reversal; or contrapuntally with 
other themes. 

Most people are capable of learning and recognizing simple melodies, 
and equally capable of recognizing the sound of various instruments 
— but few mortals share the privilege of 'absolute pitch', of being 
able to identify single notes. In other words, retention of a pattern of 
stimuli is the rule, retention of an isolated stimulus the exception. If 
the pattern is relatively simple, it is 'take in at a glance', as a whole: 
as a rule, listening to the first two transients is sufficient to identify an 
instrument. 9 But the more complex the pattern, the more difficult it 
becomes to 'take the whole in at a glance', and it can be retained only 
by dint of a certain amount of rote learning. 

Conditioning and Insight in Perception 

Once more, however, the items memorized are not discrete bits, but 
organized sub-wholes; and they are not summated in an open chain 
but interrelated in a closed figure. Thus the first movement of a sonata 
will fall into three sub-wholes: statement of themes, development, 
recapitulation; and the first of these is usually subdivided into the ex- 
position of two themes in the order A-B-A; while in the rondo we 
usually have ABACA. 

Similar considerations apply, for instance, to the learning of a 
poem. Rhythm, rhyme, grammar, and meaning provide patterns or 
'grids' superimposed on each other — matrices governed by already 
established codes; and the memorizing that remains to be done is not 
so much a 'stamping in' but a 'filling of gaps'. This is shown by the 
typical way of 'getting stuck' in reciting a poem; e.g.: 

'. . . Cannon to left of them / Cannon in front of them / ( ) 

and thundered'. A word has fallen out like a piece from a jigsaw 
puzzle — but it merely leaves a gap; it does not break the 'chain*. The 
old-fashioned method of teaching history by reigns and battles is an 
obvious example of stamping in. Even so, the data often show some 
rudimentary organization into rhythmic or visual patterns, acquired 
spontaneously or by some memorizing trick such as rhyming jingles. 
Calculating prodigies memorize long series of numbers, not by chain- 
ing but by ordering them into familiar sub-groups. Nonsense syllables 
are easier retained by twisting them into a semblance of words, and 



522 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



weaving these into a story. 10 The position of thirty men on a chess- 
board is easier retained than of five chessmen lying in a heap on the 
floor. 

How do we recognize complex patterns? Take a professional musi- 
cian who has turned on his radio in the middle of a programme: 'It's 
a string quartet. . . . Something by Beethoven. . . . It's a quartet of 

the middle period It's the second Rasoumovsky It is probably 

played by the Amadeus Quartet. . . The input has been matched in 
rapid succession against the very complex coded constancies in several 
interlocking hierarchies — timbre, melody, rhythm, accent, phrasing, 
volume, density, etc. — until the last drop of 'information' has been 
extracted from it. Each independent hierarchy of 'coloured filters* 
activated by the input adds an additional dimension to understanding. 

Perception cannot be divorced from past experience. What I have 
said so far already foreshadows a continuous scale of gradations between 
opposite methods of perceptual learning. At one end, in classical con- 
ditioning, we shall find stamping-in, under artificial conditions, of 
excitation-patterns which outside the laboratory would be treated as 
biologically irrelevant and would accordingly leave no trace. Outside 
the laboratory, edible things do not emit signals by metronome-clicks, 
or by displaying the figure of an ellipse on a cardboard. The dog's 
perceptual organization is not 'attuned* to this kind of input-signal; 
it lies outside all recognized rules of the game; and there will be no 
inherent tendency in the naive dog to abstract information from the 
rate of metronome-clicks. However (see below, Chapter XII), even 
the artificial stamping-in of a trace in this type of experiment is not 
purely mechanical, and not comparable to the action of the recording 
needle on the gramophone disc. 

In the intermediary ranges of the scale we find blends of varying 
proportions between *bit learning' and 'whole' or pattern-learning; 
and lastly, at the opposite end, the input is analysed in all its relevant 
aspects by the various competent* perceptual hierarchies, until it is 
saturated, as it were, with meaning. This, I shall suggest, is what we 
mean by 'insight-learning'. Insight thus becomes a matter of degrees 
— and not, as the Gestalt school seemed to hold, an all-or-nothing 
process. 

The key-word in the previous paragraph was 'competent'. The 
amount of 'stamping in* needed, and the type of learning which will 
occur, depends on the animal's (native and acquired) perceptual organi- 
zation—in other words, on its 'ripeness' for that particular kind of 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



523 



task. If this sounds like a truism, one still wonders how conditioning 
— 'classical' or 'operant'— could ever have been regarded as the para- 
digm of all learning. 

Abstract and Picture-strip 

Memory of a sort is found on every organic level, from protozoa 
upwards. The human nervous system we assume to be equipped with 
a hierarchy of memory-systems operating on various levels: from 
short-lived, unstable modifications in the receptor organs, to stable 
and enduring central 'engrams' and the codes of complex skills. Since 
perception and memory-formation proceed in a continuous series, and 
since perception filters the input, we are led to the apparently para- 
doxical conclusion that the most enduring memory-traces must be 
those which have been most thoroughly de-particularized — that is to 
say, impoverished. This seems indeed to be the case at least in so far as 
one important category of hierarchies is concerned: the abstractive 
category. 

When one is watching a play at the theatre the successive sounds 
emitted by the actors must be retained by short-term memory until 
they can be bracketed together into words or larger syntactic sub- 
wholes. The psychological present embraces various-sized chunks of 
the immediate past (by means of a 'mnemic afterglow', of reverber- 
ating circuits, or what-have-you). By the time the actor utters his 
next line, the perceptual relata— the speech-units — of the previous line 
have already been forgotten, and only the wording is still retained. 
A few lines further the exact wording of the first phrase is also wiped 
off the memory slate, and only its content is still stored on some 
higher level of the hierarchy. The next day one still has a fairly detailed 
recollection of the actual sequence of scenes in the play; a few months 
later only an outline of the plot as a whole remains in the 'store'. 
Parsimony in memory-formation demands that only a mere skeleton 
of the complex original experience should be retained on the highest 
level of a given hierarchy; and vice versa, that the trace which an 
input leaves shall be the more enduring, the higher the level to 
which it has attained by successive stages of de-particularization and 
re-coding. 

The example I described was of an abstractive hierarchy governed 
exclusively by logical analysis. A computer built on these lines, after 
being fed a number of West End plays, would probably filter down 



524. THE ACT OF CREATION 

all that it found worth retaining, to a formula such as: isoscele marriage 
triangle with pet-dog at centre of gravity, or: whodunit with five in- 
dependent variables (suspects). 

Let us assume that at each stage of this serial abstractive process, the 
input activates some particular scanning- or filtering-device which is 
'attuned' to that particular input. The receiving end of that device 
corresponds to its 'matrix' aspect: it is potentially responsive to a great 
many inputs which have one specific feature or pattern in common, 
and are thus equipotential in that respect. When an input is 'recognized* 
by the matrix as conforming to that pattern, it will emit a code- 
signal to the higher echelons. But while the matrix is 'attuned' to a 
great number of variations in the input pattern, the code merely signals 
the invariant aspect of it, e.g. 'a triangle', 'an octave', 'a fly', a denial'. 
The size and position of the triangle, the particulars of the fly, the 
wording of the denial are lost in the coding, and cannot be retrieved by 
reversing the process within that particular hierarchy (though it may 
have been preserved by another). 

Thus the analysing-devices behave like analogue-to-digital com- 
puters, and in other respects, too, the order of events is the exact re- 
verse — as one would expect— of the processes we have observed in 
motor-hierarchies. When an animal engages in some skilled action, 
the co-ordinating centre activates a matrix of equi-final motor patterns; 
which particular sub-skill will be called into activity depends on cir- 
cumstances. Thus the 'roughed-in' action-programme becomes more 
and more particularized in the course of its descent to the periphery — 
while contrariwise, the peripheral input is more and more de-particu- 
larized or 'skeletonized* in its ascent towards the centre. The first is a 
process of progressively spelling out implicit orders; the second an 
equally stepwise process of abstracting the meaning implied in the 
mosaic of sensations. Both processes are irreversible: the exact words 
of the actors in the play cannot be retrieved. 

It can also happen, however, that one has quite forgotten what that 
play, seen years ago, was about— except for one particular detail, an 
inflection of voice, an imploring gesture of the heroine which, torn 
from its context, remains engraved on one's memory. There exists, 
indeed, a method of retention which seems to be the direct opposite 
of memory-formation in abstractive hierarchies. It is characterized by 
the preservation of vivid details, which, from a purely logical point , 
of view, are often quite irrelevant; and yet these quasi-cinemato- 
graphic details or 'close-ups', which seem to contradict the demands 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



525 



of parsimony, are both enduring, strikingly sharp, and add texture and 
flavour to memory. 

Bartlett, in a classic experiment, made his subjects read an Indian 
legend and then reproduce it on repeated occasions at intervals of in- 
creasing length — ranging from fifteen minutes after the first reading 
to several months or years. The story was about thirty lines long; it 
concerned a young Indian who got involved in the 4 War of the Ghosts', 
and was wounded in the process. The last paragraph read: 

He told it all, and then became quiet. When the sun rose he fell 
down. Something black came out of his mouth. His face became 
contorted. The people jumped up and cried. He was dead. 10 * 

Twenty subjects were tested. Their written recollection of the story 
shrank with the passage of time to a few lines which, in most cases, 
distorted its content almost * beyond recognition\ But, with one ex- 
ception, all the spaced-out versions of all subjects, even after several 
years, contained the lines: 'Something black came out (or "issued" or 
"rushed" or "jumped out") of his mouth.' The one exception wrote 
(after four months): 'My remembrance was in visual terms ... of 
breath somehow materializing into a ghost.' 

Fiction and autobiography abound with examples of such Vivid- 
fragment-memories' : the mole on Granny's chin, the fly crawling over 
the lump of sugar at the moment of the dramatic climax. Let us call 
this the picture strip' type of memory — although, of course, the 
'vivid fragment' may be auditory or olfactory, or even a whole 
'cinematographic sequence' — like the detailed, auditory-visual se- 
quences which Penfield evoked in his patients through electric stimu- 
lation of their exposed temporal lobes (see below). 

Obviously the formation of such 'picture-strip traces* must also be 
preceded by some filtering process; but in this case the criteria of rele- 
vance and parsimony are different, and often directly opposed to those 
of the abstractive hierarchies. The vivid detail is usually described as 
'striking', 'attractive', 'evocative', 'nostalgic*, 'frightening'; it always 
has some emotional significance. It is mostly on a pre-verbal level; but 
even verbal fragments — of a poem, of a chill warning or whispered 
endearment — are retained because of their affective quality. The filter- 
matrices that operate in these hierarchies must be emotionally 'attuned* 
— let us say to some hypothalamic controls. We may further assume 
that such picture-strip memories are formed on lower (prc-conceptual) 



526 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



levels than memories of the abstractive kind; they may be symbolic, 
but their symbolism too is often pre-verbal, and perhaps related to 
the symbolism of the dream; they may even obey their own special 
brand of parsimony. We have seen that occasional regression to lower 
levels of tie hierarchy is a conditio sine qua non of creativeness; the com- 
bination of the abstractive and picture-strip type of memory may serve 
the same purpose — vide Coleridge and Kekule. 

We are thus led to assume the existence of various hierarchies in 
perception and cognition, whose criteria of relevance are determined 
by the attitudes, drives, emotions, which they serve; they interlace 
with each other on every level, and thereby provide the multi-dimen- 
sionality — or multi-colouration — of experience; at the same time they 
also compensate for the impoverishment of experience in the process 
of memory formation. The outstanding memory which some geniuses 
are said to have possessed may possibly be due to their niany-dimen- 
sional ways of analysing and storing experiences. 



Learning to See 

Let us turn to vision. 

Innate perceptual organization provides no more than the primitive 
foundation on which learning can build. The long controversy be- 
tween Behaviourists and the nativistically inclined Gestalt school 
whether perceptual organization is innate or learned has finally been 
superseded by the more realistic question how much is innate and how 
much acquired by early learning. The consensus seems to be that 
colour and brightness constancy, and the recognition of line, angle, and 
texture are innate in rats as well as men. u So is primitive unity' (Hebb) 
— the segregation of simple figures as coherent entities from the back- 
ground (for instance, a black splash on a white card). But when it 
comes to more complex figures where the contrast is less marked, even 
the figure-ground relation is strongly influenced by learning and ex- 
pectancy. I have quoted examples from the neglected field of auditory 
perception where the relativity of figural unity is obvious. The radio- 
logist whom experience has taught to see a peptic ulcer or a lesion of 
the lung, treats die much sharper contours of the ribs as 'background'. 
When you hunt for a collar-stud in a drawerful of miscellaneous ob- 
jects, that small, insipid form, poor in Gestalt Pragnanz, will 'stick out 
a mile'; the reniaining contents of the drawer are 'background*. 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



527 



Thus even figural coherence is influenced by past experience and 
present attitude. When it comes to the identification and recognition of 
visual Gestalten, it has been shown that even the simplest of them — 
triangles, squares — require an element of learning. The behaviour of 
chimpanzees reared without pattern vision, of human beings with 
congenital cataract who had to learn to see* after they were operated 
on, and the cumulative evidence from other experiments indicate, in 
Hebb's words, 'that the normal human infant goes through the same 
process, and that we are able to see a square as such in a single glance 
only as the result of complex learning'. 12 The learning process seems 
to depend mainly on visual exploration: a two-year-old child will 
recognize a triangle that has been rotated by 120 degrees only after 
rotating its own head; 13 but even in the adult, perception is bound up 
with exploratory motions of the eyes, from conscious movements to 
the involuntary, minute motions ('drift', 'flick', 'tremor') which move 
the image across the fovea when the eye seems 'fixed' on a stationary 
object. Identification of a triangle or square seems to depend on serial 
scanning of its contours. 14 With practice, the scanning motions may 
become summary or subliminal; but when scanning is artificially 
eliminated by a mechanical device, the image disintegrates into frag- 
ments. ' Wir tasten mit unserem Blick das Sehfeld ab\ Exner wrote in 
1891 15 (We finger over the visual field with our gaze). 

Thus with the exception of brightness and colour constancy, and a 
few other primitive 'innate skills', visual perception is inextricably 
bound up with learning, i.e. with memory. What we perceive in 
audition is not the linear pulse of pressure-variations arriving at the 
eardrum, but an 'inferential construct' of individual voices, instru- 
ments, musical or verbal phrases; and what we perceive in vision is 
not the camera-image on the retina but the 'inferential construct' of 
people and objects which preserve their constant shape and size, regard- 
less of angle and distance. The eye may be a camera, but immediately 
behind its lens there is a series of compensating, correcting, and re- 
touching devices — the perceptual matrices of skilled vision. 



Knowing and Seeing 

The best-known among these are the matrices responsible for the 
visual constancies and illusions which are found in every elemen- 
tary textbook. Less attention has been paid to the modification of 



528 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



automatically functioning perceptual matrices by verbal learning and 
verbal suggestions, by attitude and expectation. 16 Mitscherlich, an 
outstanding observer, had denied that there existed any structural 
difference between the two types of tartaric acid of opposite optical 
activity. Pasteur, using the same apparatus, saw at once the asymmetric 
facets on the tartar crystals because his hypothesis on molecular struc- 
ture demanded that they should be there. 17 

Perceptual matrices function not only autonomously, but display 
considerable 'self-assertion*. This is shown in a simple but drastic 
manner by the difficulty of breaking the arrow illusion: 

a b 

< » < *=b 

Another example of 'self-assertion is the tiresome insistence with 
which a tune will go round and round in your head; or the infuriating 
messages — 'I told you so' — 'I told you so* rapped out at the rate of 
once per second by the wheels of your railway-carriage. A more ad- 
vanced but equally typical illustration for 'knowing is seeing' is this 
quote from Babbage: 'I will prepare the apparatus, and put you in 
such a position that [Fraunhofer's dark lines] shall be visible, and yet 
you shall look for them and not find them: after which, while you 
remain in the same position, I will instruct you how to see them, and 
you shall see them, and not merely wonder you did not see them 
before, but you shall find it impossible to look at the spectrum with- 
out seeing them.' 18 

A pretty illustration of perception impregnated by previous know- 
ledge is in the drawing opposite. 

The bear climbing on the other side of the tree is purely inferential. 
Yet you see the semi-circles plus four strokes as his paws. 

Levels of Memory 

Perception and memory cannot be un-scrambled. Let us consider 
briefly a few types of 'mnemic processes which intervene on various 
levels of the hierarchy. 

On the lowest, peripheral level we find automatisms designed to 
reduce redundancy and to 'compress' the input It would be unecono- 
mical if each receptor in the retina would signal to report stimulation 




from a uniformly illuminated area; hence lateral inhibition between 
neighbouring receptor units, combined with light-adaptation, will 
filter down the input to signals which report only the relevant spatial 
differences in illumination---i.e. the contours of the iHuminated area. 19. 
Likewise, the eye adapts to uniform motion— as seen in the illusion 
of reverse movement when the real movement stops (the 'waterfall- 
illusion'). These automatisms could be called memory processes con- 
fined to the psychological present (in the broad sense of 'memory = 
modification of responsiveness by experience'). 

More lasting are after-images — once regarded as the prototypes of 
'photographic' memory. In fact, however, the after-image 'improves' 
on the original by achieving greater regularity and simplicity. Goethe 
was the first to observe that the after-image of a square will gradually 
become transformed into a circle—a figure of greater symmetry. 
Rothschild's 20 experiments showed that only regular figures with 
good* contour produce stable after-images; that figures with gaps in 
their contours appear 'closed' in the after-image; that small irregulari- 
ties disappear, and elements which 'do not belong' to a figure, such as. 

529 



530 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



a squiggle or tail attached to a square, become detached from it and 
come and go as independent units. Thus the reproduction is far from 
mechanical, and is controlled both by intrinsic codes and from higher 
centres. 21 

There are some significant parallels between after-images and 
images which have been artificially stabilized on the retina. The latter 
are obtained by a tiny projector, mounted on a contact-lens worn by 
the subject. The iUuminated target-figure is fixed at the other end of 
the projector; it moves with the involuntary scanning motions of the 
eyeball, and its projection remains thus fixed on the same spot of the 
retina—subtending a visual angle of two degrees in a patch of light of 
five degrees, with darkness all round. Under these conditions the per- 
ceived image will vanish and reappear much as after-images do — either 
as a whole, or it will disintegrate into parts. If the latter is the case, the 
fragments will be meaningful in one way or the other: a human face 
will break up into its specific features or groups of features — profile or 
top of the head; and a composite monogram will break up into the 
individual letters and numbers which were hidden in it. Conversely, 
the elements in a meaningless pattern of curlicews will at first fade and 
reappear in various combinations; but after a while they will organize 
themselves into stable sub-wholes. Central processes fraught with past 
experience exert an obvious influence on these phenomena; and so 
does the subject's attitude. 

The next step leads to eidetic images. These occupy an intermediate 
place in the memory hierarchy between after-images and the picture- 
strip' type of recall. In their direct sensory impact they are comparable 
to hypnagogic images and close to hallucinations. The experimenter 
directs the subject to inspect a picture for about thirty seconds without 
staring (to eliminate after-images), then to look at a grey screen. The 
average person sees nothing; the eidetic projects' the image onto the 
screen and behaves as if the picture were actually there. He can focus 
on a detail, point out its exact position on the screen, count the buttons 
on a coat, the number of spokes on a wheel, and read' the letters in a 
foreign-language text forward or backward. 22 It seems, therefore, that 
eidetic images 'are seen in the literal sense of the word'. 23 Eidetic 
recall may be limited to a short interval after inspecting an object or 
picture, or extend to 'minutes, days, years'. 2 * Analogous phenomena 
seem to exist in other sense-modalities: Beethoven, Mozart, Wagner, 
and Elgar were supposed to be able to 'hear at will the full texture of 
an orchestra'. 25 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



531 



Eidetic memory, though rare in adults, seems to be quite common 
in children before puberty; 'in certain regions/ according to Kluever, 
'eighty to a hundred per cent of the children are reported eidetic. 26 
This is a striking confirmation of the commonplace that the child lives 
in a world of images of great vividness, whereas the average adult's 
images are grey shadows. The eidetic type of memory seems to be 
irretrievably lost, in all but exceptional cases, with the transition from 
the perceptual and affective to the conceptual and symbolic mentality. 
Pictorial memory, as we saw, belongs to a phylogenetically and onto- 
genetically earlier level of the mnemic hierarchy. 

Yet if we expect the eidetic image to be a true photographic record, 
we shall again be disappointed. All reports agree that the development 
of the image on the screen depends on the child's interest in the picture 
as a whole, and in its details. Exciting details come out sharply, while 
adjacent parts may remain blank, blurred, or even appear in com- 
plementary colours. Pictures which have no meaning for the child do 
not appear on the screen. 27 The objects in the image can be moved 
about, and their colour and size can be changed at will, or in response 
to verbal suggestions. Synaesthetic phenomena also enter: if the 
subject's arms are pulled while he is inspecting a horizontal line, the 
eidetic image of the line will be lengthened; images of the Mueller- 
Lyer illusion may be lengthened 'by as much as two yards'. 28 

Image r and Meaning 

A further step upward in the hierarchy leads to what I have called the 
'picture-strip' kind of memory with emotive significance; and lastly 
we arrive at the phenomena referred to as 'memory images' in ordinary 

An image is defined in Drevers Dictionary as 'a revived sense ex- 
perience, in the absence of the sensory stimulation'. But since most of 
the sensory stimulation has been irretrievably lost in the filtering- 
processes of memory formation, only some exceptionally sharp, 
vivid details are perhaps capable of being 'revived' or 'reproduced'; 
the remainder of the experience must be 'reconstructed'. It has been 
known for a long time that introspective reports on 'visual memory 
images' are largely based on self-deception. Visual recall— as Semon 
once wrote — 'renders only the strongest lights and shadows'; 29 but 
strictly speaking, even shadows are absent from visual images — as they 



532 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



are from Chinese paintings; and so are, as a rule, all but the crudest 
shades of colour. The normal adult's memory-images are much vaguer, 
sketchier in outline than he is wont to believe; in most cases when he 
believes that he possesses a visual image of a thing, he is really referring 
to aggregates of simplified perceptual schemata, held together by 
conceptual links. 

This has been amply demonstrated (cf. Book One, pp. 346 seq) . In the 
Binet-Mueller test 30 the subject is directed to memorize a letter square 
(comprising sixteen or twenty-five letters in random distribution) until 
he thinks that he has formed a visual image of it, and can 'see' it in his 
mind's eye. But when he is asked to read the letters in his image in 
backward order or diagonally, he will take up to ten times longer than 
when reciting them in their proper serial order from left to right. 

Another classic test is the drawing of elephants by patients suffering 
from a form of aphasia which impairs symbolic thought but leaves 
perceptual faculties intact— a test first used by Pierre Marie, and later 
by Henry Head: 31 

Case No. 8 ('semantic asphasia): Asked to draw an elephant, he 
moved his pencil about aimlessly, saying 'I can't get the idea'. Then 
he suddenly drew the outline of the head, back and belly, adding the 
four legs and an eye; the tusks were indicated but he omitted the 
trunk. I asked 'What is the characteristic of an elephant?' To this he 
replied, 'Its trunk; I see I have omitted to put in his trunk'. 

Case No. 11 . . . made an incomplete drawing of an elephant to 
order. Asked if he had left out anything, he replied 'His ear', and 
made a mark on the side of the head. When I inquired 'Has an 
elephant got anything else?', he answered 'Trunk, eye, tail, toes', 
marking in each object in turn as he named it; but he forgot the 
tusks. 

Case No. 21 (a woman of high intelligence with some semantic 
disorder): When I requested her to draw an elephant she produced 
a picture distincdy resembling this animal, except that she gave it a 
bushy tail and forgot the tusks. After she had finished she exclaimed 
'I haven't put the tusks in. I can't remember where they come. 
They come from just below the eye, I think; but I don't know. I 
believe they are teeth and should come out of the top of the jaw 
really.' 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



533 



The quotations show that the visual image of the elephant was not 
in fact a 'perceptual whole* but a melange of perceptual and conceptual 
entities; die glue which held the visual parts, together was meaning. 
Thus in a number of drawings the tusks at first appeared on top of the 
elephant's head as if they had been horns; and only when their function 
was remembered were they put in their correct place. 

"We have now reached the boundary between the perceptual and 
symbolic hierarchies — the highest level of perceptual integration, where 
symbolic coding must take over if further progress in learning is to 
be achieved. The schematized visual forms of trunk, legs, tusks, seem 
to be the upper limit of the patient's capability of forming true per- 
ceptual Gestalt-traces. When it comes to reproducing the 'image' of 
the complete elephant, the visual pattern of the tusk is manipulated as a 
symbolic unit, labelled a 'tusk'. It is, once more, a double-faced entity: 
one side is a complex and flexible perceptual whole, the other is a 
semantic unit which signals the word 'tusk' and is activated by the 
same signal. 

Klangbild and Wortschatz 

A similar frontier is found in audition, where perception of sound 
patterns turns into interpretation of language. Here one face of the 
entities which pass the frontier is a Klangbild, the other belongs to 
the Wortschatz — a distinction between 'sound-picture' and 'word- 
treasure' (i.e. vocabulary) — which Wernicke made in 1874. 32 

There is considerable doubt whether the discrete elements or 
'segments' of speech are phonemes, syllables, or even larger units. Let 
us assume for argument's sake that the segments are characteristic 
vowel-consonant combinations — digrams or trigrarns* and call these 
the perceptual units (the 'sound-pictures' of speech). In whatever way 
you define your unit, when it comes to the transition from perceiving 
the sound-picture to interpreting its speech-value, a considerable degree 
of ambiguity creeps in. Thus the, speech-value of a vowel (the o-ness 
of an o) is independent of the frequency of its fundamental, and 
depends on the characteristic frequency-ranges of its two formants 
(its dominant partials). But these formant-ranges overlap; and accor- 
dingly 'a sound with a particular spectrum will be recognized as / 1 / 
on one occasion and / e / on another'. 33 Most consonants, on the 
other hand, vary their pitch according to the vowel with which they 



534 



THB ACT OF CRBATION 



are associated, and are characterized not only by pitch but also by the 
change, and rate of change of pitch. 34 Thus the identification of 
language units depends to a considerable extent on their meaning- 
context; experimental subjects confuse m and n in nonsense syllables 
more frequently than when listening to meaningful speech; and the 
ambiguity of the input can only be resolved with reference to the pre- 
ceding and following inputs in the psychological present. In discussing 
the practical feasibility of robots for translating speech into typescript, 
Fry and Denes concluded: 'It is unlikely that the mechanical speech- 
recognizer will be successful without the use of some form of lin- 
guistic ^formation/ 35 It is the same as with ambiguous visual stimuli, 
whether they are riddles of the face-hidden-in-the-tree kind, or 
Frauenhofer-lines in the spectroscope. 'Es hort dock jeder nur was er 
versteht\ Goethe noted in his Maximcn. 

If scanning is an aid to vision, articulation is an aid to hearing. 
When we try to remember a tune, we hum it. The decisive factor in 
the emergence of human speech was not the development of the ear, 
but of the vocal organs and of the speech area in the motor cortex. 
The multiple feedbacks of auditory-vocal coordination exceed even 
those of oculo-motor co-operation. The child learns words by articu- 
lating them; adults learning a foreign language follow a similar pro- 
cedure. Reading is more often accompanied by sub-vocal articulation 
than by images in the ear (except if you know intimately the author of 
what you are reading). The analysis of speech-sounds by matching 
them against innervation-patterns of the vocal tracts is a much simpler 
procedure than the acoustic analysis of the ambiguous sound spectra. 
However complex and variable the wave form of a vowel which 
reaches the ear, its identity as a language unit depends on its two for- 
mants, which in turn depend only on the resonance effects produced 
by the alterations of shape of two vocal cavities, mouth and pharynx. 
Paget 36 proposed that 'in recognizing speech sounds the human ear 
is . . . listening ... to indications, due to resonance, of the position 
and gestures of the organs of articulation'. More recently a team of 
American experimentalists in the Haskins Laboratories have come to 
the same conclusion that 'speech is perceived by reference to articula- 
tion—that is, that the articulatory movements and their sensory 
[proprioceptive] effects mediate between the acoustic stimulus and the 
event we call perception'. 87 Lastly, Lawrence (1959) has described a 
method of speech-analysis which specifies such details as the fre- 
quencies of resonance of the vocal tract and the vibration frequencies 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



535 



of the vocal chords — a method of analysis 'which preserves all per- 
ceptually valuable features, but is vastly simpler than the acoustic 
wave form. From an information theory point of view it is a tre- 
mendous reduction in the bit rate — it is a reduction of the order of 
thirty to one. It may well be that speech is held in the short-term 
memory in a form like this/ 38 

Once again we find confirmed that perception is Something the 
organism does, not something which happens to the organism'; 39 
that responses enter at every level of the hierarchy into the processing 
of stimuli; and that motor activities intervene to analyse the input 
long before it has achieved its full status as a 'stimulus' — before it has, 
for instance, become a meaningful word capable of stimulating the 
central process which is to mediate the 'response'. As Drever, Jr., has 
so nicely put it: 'Assodationist learning theory, where it has tried 

to hold to a stria S >R pattern, appears to be lapsing into an 

esoteric scholasticism. Where it has abandoned S >R in favour of 

S >X >R, there are complaints that it is struggling to say 

things which must be said, but doing so in a language which is no 
longer appropriate/ 40 



Perceptual and Conceptual Abstraction 

One last example of a frontier where perceptual organization can do 
no more for you, and symbolic thought has to take over. 

When a number of objects is projected by lantern slide on a screen 
just long enough to be fully seen but not long enough to be counted, 
few people can correctly tell how many objects they have seen if the 
number exceeds seven; and many reach their limit of 'number per- 
ception at five. 41 Surprisingly enough, the remarkable experiments of 
Otto Koehler revealed that pigeons, jackdaws, paroquets, and 
budgerigars can do as well, and that specially gifted jackdaws have a 
'number sense' with the upper limit eight— just as the most gifted 
humans. 

The experimental procedure consists, briefly, in training birds to 
open that box among several other boxes whose lid shows the same 
number of spots as the number of objects shown to the bird on a cue 
card. The sizes and spatial arrangements of the spots on the lid and of 
the objects on the card are not related in any way;- and the rigorous 
experimental conditions and controls seem to have established beyond 



536 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



doubt that birds have a 'prelinguistic number sense'; that they 'are 
able to abstract the "concept" of numerical identity from groups of up 
to seven objects of totally different and unfamiliar appearance'. 42 
Among mammals, squirrels have been shown to have the same 
ability. 43 The evidence suggests 'that men and animals may have a pre- 
linguistic "counting" ability of about the same degree, but that man's 
superiority in dealing with numbers lies in his ability to use, as symbols 
for numbers, words and figures which have not the same, or indeed 
any, numerical attributes.' 44 The symbolic coding of number Ges- 
tagen seems indeed a decisive step towards the formation of cardinal 
numbers; I shall return to the subject later (Chapter XV). 

Sound-pictures, printed letters of the alphabet, number-configura- 
tions, are all complex perceptual wholes, and at the same time ele- 
mentary parts of symbolic thought: one might call them (to change 
the metaphor) 'amphibian' entities. They signal the transition, in 
mental evolution, from the aquatic' world of perception which keeps 
the organism submerged in a fluid environment of sounds, shapes, and 
smells, to the dry land of conceptualized thinking. The highest forms 
of purely perceptual abstraction on the pre-verbal level are like bubbles 
of air which aquatic creatures extract from the water; conceptualized 
thought is dry and inexhaustible, like the atmosphere. 

This is not meant of course to belittle the formidable powers of 
perceptual abstraction found in some animals. The innate (or im- 
printed) releasive mechanisms, for instance, may be regarded as 
phylogenetically acquired skills which enable the animal to combine 
the colour, shape, and movement of the stimulus-pattern into a single 
'constancy'. The rat learns to make a 'mental map' of the maze in its 
head (Chapter XII); and it has always been a mystery to me how my 
dog recognizes another dog on the opposite sidewalk at sight without 
using his sense of smell-— for the typical reactions of staring, straining 
at the leash, whining, occurs at the very instant of catching sight. The 
other dog may be a miniature Peke, a dolled-up Poodle, or a Great 
Dane; how does my dog identify that apparition as a kinsman— how 
did he abstract the universal 'Dog'? Perhaps at a distance he merely 
reacts to four legs and one or two other Gestalt characteristics common 
to all amines, which account for their Mogginess'— though we would 
be at a loss to define them. 



Generalization, Discrimination, and Association 



We have discussed various forms of 'filtering' codes, both innate and 
acquired, which de-particularize or strip the input for purposes of 
recognition and storage according to the criteria of relevance in a given 
hierarchy. The mcoming pattern is thus subjected to 'generalization' and 
discrimination at the same time; the two are complementary aspects of 
the same process. (The word 'generalization is often used in two different 
senses: (a) extracting invariant features from a variety of experiences, 
(b) the 'spreading* of responses. I am using it in the first sense.) 

Native equipment and early learning provide the basic foundations 
on which the different hierarchies are built, designed to filter out more 
and more sharply defined features. The coarse-meshed 'perceptual 
sieves' of the tyro acquire fine-meshed sub-analysers: perceptual 
learning progresses 'from the seeing of gross differences to the seeing 
of fine differences' (pp. 490 f.). All connoisseurship— -from the 
chicken-sexer's to the handwriting expert's, from the wine-taster's to 
the art historian's, depends on the hierarchic build-up of analysing, 
matching, scanning codes which extract subtle similarities and make 
precise discriminations. 

This leads to the hoary problem of the nature of 'similarity'. The 
simplest answer would be to elirninate it altogether from the vocabu- 
lary of psychology and to substitute 'equipotentiality' for it. Two per- 
cepts are equipotential if both can pass a given filter in a given hierarchy 
— if they satisfy its criteria according to the rules of the game that is 
played at the time; in other words, if 'for one intent and purpose' (but 
not Tor all intents and purposes') they are the same thing. Sultan dis- 
covered the 'similarity' between a branch on the castor-oil bush and a 
stick because they were equipotential for his purpose. A paperclip is 
'similar* to a hair-pin when I have to mend a blown fuse. The answer 
to the old classroom question whether a red circle is more similar to a 
green circle than to a red triangle, depends on whether I am teaching 
geometry or colour-theory. In the first case, the two circles are for 
my purpose, 'the same thing'; in the second, the two colours are 'the 
same thing.'* 

The width of the span within which two stimuli are perceived as 
'the same thing' depends on the precision of the analyser— the gauge 
of the sieve through which they must pass. To talk of the 'spreading* 
of response ('generalization' in sense (b) ) is confusing; the equi- 
potentiality of circle and ellipse to the naive Pavlov dog is not due to 

537 



538 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



any spreading of reactions from circle to ellipse, but to the absence of 
discrimination between two figures which for the 'intents and purposes' 
of the untrained animal are the same — as for my intents and purposes 
one sheep is the same as another. Similar considerations apply to 
'transfer* (Chapter XV). 

'Association by similarity' of perceptions would accordingly mean 
that an input-pattern A at some stage of its ascent in the nervous 
system initiates the recall of some past experience B which is equi- 
potential to A with respect to the scanning process at that particular 
stage, but not in other respects. We might say that A and B have one 
partial' in common which causes B to resonate*. 

Association by sound and visual form plays, as we have seen, an 
important part in the dream and in subconscious processes which 
enter into creativity. But in the ordinary routines of life, association 
of sensory percepts uncontaminated by conceptual thinking seems to 
be rare, and whether it occurs at all is anybody's introspective guess. 
In the Rohrschach test visual association depends on projective dy- 
namics imbued with meaning. Verbal suggestions influence the visual 
matrix and distort even the eidetic image; the ambiguities of the sound- 
picture can only be dispelled by reference to vocabulary; children and 
aphasic patients often confuse p and q, or write s and e as mirror 
images, because the cognitive glue which holds the true perceptual 
units together (verticals, loops, etc.) has not yet hardened or has 
already decayed— like the aggregate of visual and cognitive elements 
which constitutes the image of the elephant. Thus hearing is inex- 
tricably bound up with interpreting, seeing with knowing, perceiving 
with naming. By these methods the organism is enabled to build a 
model of the external world into its own nervous system, without 
having to store lantern-slides and gramophone records of complex 
perceptual forms — animal, vegetable and mineral-— which would not 
work anyway. All that the model needs in the way of perceptual 
'traces' is a modest inventory of elementary root-forms — much like 
the cubist painter's austere repertory which Cezanne recommended: 
'Everything in nature is modelled on the sphere, the cone and the 
cylinder. One must teach oneself to base one's painting on these simple 
figures — then one can accomplish anything one likes.* 45 

"What we call our visual or auditory memory probably consists of a 
limited number of such 'root traces' or 'perceptual elements' (in Hebb's 
sense). These alone may have 'real form' as perceptual wholes, and at 
the same time enter as parts into the complex, aggregate 'pseudo- 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



539 



images', held together by meaningful association. If it seems to us that 
such complex aggregates can be 'taken in* and 'recognized at a glance* 
without scanni n g and exploration, this is perhaps because we com- 
monly underestimate the span of the psychological present. In his 
review of the literature on the psychological present, Woodrow found 
that its maximum span is estimated to lie between 2*3 and 12 seconds. 46 
No wonder there is considerable disagreement about the size of the 
'discrete units of speech' in perception — whether the unit is the 
phoneme, syllable, word, or a whole sentence! A few seconds are 
ample time for those partly or wholly unconscious operations which 
make our perceptions into inferential constructions. If the psycho- 
logical present /P/ be regarded as an elementary quantum of conscious 
experience, then the processes which go on within /P/ can ex hypothesi 
not be on a conscious level; they must remain an unanalysable and un- 
compressible blur. 

Recognition and Recall 

While new matrices are formed by learning, others may decay through 
disuse like old waterways overgrown by weeds. Apart from genera- 
tion and decay, the traces left by past events in the nervous system also 
undergo dynamic changes — simplification, condensation, distortion 
on the one hand; elaboration and enrichment through the addition of 
extraneous material on the other. The 'schemata* of memory, as 
Bardett called them, are 'Hving, constandy developing, affected by 
every bit of mcoming sensational experience of a given kind'. 47 In 
other words, the past is constantly being re-made by the present.* 
To quote Bardett again: 

'Remembering is not re-excitation of innumerable, fixed, lifeless 
and fragmentary traces. It is an imaginative reconstruction, or con- 
struction, built out of the relation of our attitude towards a whole 
active mass of organized past reactions or experience, and to a little 
outstanding detail which commonly appears in image or in language 
form. It is thus hardly ever really exact, even in the most rudimentary 
cases of rote-recapitulation, and it is not at all important that it should 
be so.' 48 

True recall by imagery would be possible only if the de-particu- 
larized memory could be re-particularized, the irreversible process 
reversed. One may be- able to 'hear'— while shaving, for instance — 
the faint, pale ghost of a voice from the past singing a simple song. To 



540 THE ACT OF CREATION 

make this possible, at least three different systems of 'coloured filters', 
concerned with melody, timbre, and wording, must each have pre- 
served one aspect of the original experience. One may also recall, 
more or less distinctly, characteristic combinations of form and 
motion: the stride of a person, the roll of a boat, the waddle of a 
tortoise. But the average persons abilities of perceptual imaging are 
limited to this kind of production. Hence the paradox of what one 
might call negative recognition , : I visit a friend whom I have not seen 
for some time, look round and say: * Something is changed in this 
room' — without being able to say what has been changed. I can only 
assume that my memory of the room was determined by several 
complementary matrices — sketchy, part verbal, part visual schemata, 
such as 'Regency furniture', 'L-shaped plan*, 'subdued colour scheme', 
etc. — plus one or two 'vivid details': a picture, a flower-vase. A good 
many changes could be made in the room which I would not notice 
so long as they satisfy these criteria as 'equipotential variations'; only 
changes which offend against one of the codes will make me register 
that 'something is wrong'. My inability to name that 'something* 
indicates that the code was functioning below the level of conscious 
awareness (Cf. Book One, XIX).* 

The adjectives used to describe a face — 'soft', 'bony', 'pinched', 
'humorous', etc. — refer to part visual, part verbal schemata, some of 
which may be as, simplified as the surprisingly few linear elements 
which suffice to indicate emotional expression by the posture and slant 
of mouth and eyes. The caricaturist can evoke a face by a few strokes 
which schematize a total impression (Hitler's moustache and lock), or 
he can pick out a detail which acts as a 'sign-releaser' (Churchill's 
~~cigar). It is often easier to remember a face known only from illus- 
trations — Napoleon or Mona Lisa — than faces of living persons; per- 
haps because half of the compressing and coding of the visual infor- 
mation has already been done by the artist. Equally revealing is the 
police method of reconstructing the likeness of a criminal by the 
Identi-Kit method. This is based on 'a slide-file of five hundred and 
fifty facial characteristics containing, among other things, a hundred 
irid two sets of eyes ranging from pop to squinting, thirty-three sets 
of lips from thin to sensuous, fifty-two chins, from weak to jutting, 
and even twenty-five sets of wrinkles. Witnesses pick the individual 
features that most closely resemble their idea of the crirninal's look. 
From their selections a composite picture of all the features is then 
assembled.* 49 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



541 



If in the process of memory-formation the input is stripped down to 
bare essentials, recall requires dressing it up again. This seems to be 
done by some summary drapings, patched out with surviving frag- 
ments of picture-strip, plus some fitting garments borrowed from 
elsewhere — we all know how often 'vivid details' are incorporated 
into the recall of experiences to which they do not belong. Imaging 
involves imagining, which is a flexible skill. It is triggered-ofF by an 
impulse of central origin — a kind of 'extitation-clang' which unlocks 
'memory releasers' and sets off the feedback-circuits of 'inferential 
reconstruction; as with other plastic skills, two performances are never 
quite the same. 

Summary 

I have treated perception, recognition, and memory-formation as a 
continuous series. The sensory input is screened, dismanded, re- 
assembled, analysed, interpreted, and stored along a variety of channels 
belonging to different hierarchies with different criteria of relevance. 
A tune can be stored stripped of timbre, and vice versa. The de- 
particularization of experience in the process of memory-formation is 
compensated to some extent by the multiplicity of abstractive hier- 
archies which participate in the process, and by the retention of 
picture-strips' — vivid fragments of emotive or symbolic significance. 

Central controls and motor activities participate at various stages 
in the processing of the input; from stimulus-selection in the end- 
organ and visual scanning, through resonances from the vocal tract, 
to the interpretation of Klangbild by Wortsckatz, and of the seen by 
the known. Nowhere are 'stimuli' and 'responses' neady separable; 
they form hierarchies of loops within loops. The mechanisms res- 
ponsible for the processing are partly inborn, mosdy acquired; their 
codes have a high degree of autonomy and show their 'self-asserting' 
tendencies in the tenacity of optical illusions and of 'seeing in terms of. 

The generalization and retention of perceptual forms has an upper 
limit where symbolic coding must take over to make further progress 
in learning possible. The ability of man to form 'number percepts' is 
not significandy superior to that of some birds; memory images are 
aggregates of relatively simple schematized forms, i.e. of true per- 
ceptual elements, held together by cognitive linkages, as the 'sound- 
pictures' of speech are given coherence by their meaning. They are 
double-faced entities: complex perceptual Gestalt-wholes which enter 



542 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



as units into the symbolic hierarchy. We must assume that there are 
analysing devices of this kind active in the nervous system, 'resonators' 
which are attuned 1 to a certain configuration in the perceptual input, 
and respond to it by signals in symbolic coding addressed to the higher 
echelons. All inputs which are equipotential with respect to that con- 
figuration — e.g. 'triangularity' — are regarded by the analyser as 'the 
same thing', and reported by the same signal. The process is thus the 
reverse of the 'spelling out' activites of the motor hierarchy— which is 
in some respects comparable to the unlocking of memory-releasers in 
recall. 

'Generalization and 'discrirnination , are complementary aspects of 
the same process, and will be discussed, together with the ambiguities 
of 'spreading' and 'transfer', in later chapters. 

NOTES 

To p. 513. Cf. Polanyi, 1958, p. 364: 'Behaviourists teach that in observing 
an animal we must refrain above all from trying to imagine what we would do 
if placed in the animal's position. I suggest, on the contrary, that nothing at all 
could be known about an animal that would be of the slightest interest to physi- 
ology, and still less to psychology, except by following the opposite maxim ' 

To p. 516. This response is mediated either by resonance (Helmholz's 
theory) or, more likely, by the locus of maximum hydraulic pressure in the 
'travelling wave'. 

To p. $17. The latter assumes that in visual perception a spatial 'picture* is 
projected on to the primary optical cortex, which reproduces the retinal image. 
But the excitation-pattern in the auditory cortex has no 'contours' separating 
' figure and background, and it would be difficult to imagine 'field currents* 
created by them. 

To p. 333, There are strong arguments against the segmentation of language 
according to the letters of the written alphabet (cf. e.g. Paget 1930; Ladefoged 
in Mechanization of Thought Processes, 1959). 

To p. 537. There exist of course both innate and acquired preferences for 
choosing one system of 'coloured filters* rather than another as a criterion of 
equipotentiality. Two notes an octave apart sound more 'similar* to man and 
rat than two notes close together. Evidently the nervous system finds it for its 
own 'intents and purposes' more convenient to regard two frequencies of the 
ratio 2p : p as mote similar than two frequencies of the ratio p : (p—*r). 

To p, 539. The protracted controversy about the existence of progressive, 
systematic changes in perceptual traces ('levelling* and 'sharpening') was un- 
fortunately restricted to one type of change only— the reduction of 'dynamic 



PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 



543 



stress* in the physical trace, predicted by Gestalt physiology — see Wulf, quoted 
by Koffka (1935); Hebb and Foord (1954). No psychologist would dare to deny 
that 'memory plays us false'; but its confidence-tricks are evidently not of the 
grossly mechanical type, divorced from the subject's living experience, which 
Kohler's theory of cortical field-processes demanded. 

To p. 540. 'Negative recognition' could be called the unconscious variety of 
Woodworth's (1938) 'schema with correction'. 



XI 

MOTOR SKILLS 



In the process of becoming an expert typist, the student must go 
through the whole range of learning processes variously classified 
as instrumental conditioning, sign-learning, trial and error, rote and 
place learning, insight. He is, of course, quite unaware of these cate- 
gories — which, in fact, overlap at almost every stage. The essence of 
the process is the step-wise integration of relatively simple codes of 
behaviour into complex and flexible codes with a hierarchic structure. 
This conclusion was actually reached (although expressed in different 
words) in the 1890s by Bryan and Harter 1 — then buried and forgotten 
for nearly half a century. Woodworth was one of the few experimental 
psychologists who kept harking back to the subject. The following is 
taken from his summary of Bryan and Harter 's Studies on the Tele- 
graphic Language, The Acquisition of a Hierarchy of Habits? 

'The beginner first learns the alphabet of dots and dashes. Each letter 
is a little pattern of finger movements in sending, a little pattern of 
clicks in receiving. It is something of an achievement to master these 
motor and auditory letter habits. At this stage the learner spells the words 
in sending or receiving. "With further practice he becomes familiar 
with word-patterns and does not spell out the common words. The 
transition from the letter habit to the word-habit stage extends over a 
long period of practice, and before this stage is fully reached a still 
more synthetic form of reaction begins to appear. "The fair operator 
is not held so closely to words. He can take in several words at a 
mouthful, a phrase or even a short sentence." In sending he antici- 
pates, as in other motor performances; but in receiving, he learns to 
"copy behind'*, letting two or three words come from the sounder 
before he starts to copy. Keeping a few words behind the sounder 
allows time for getting the sense of the message.' 

544 



MOTOR SKILLS 



545 



Let us call these three stages of habit-formation the 'letter', 'word', 
and 'context* levels. The letter habit is acquired by 'serial learning'. 
But no chain-response theory can account even for this first step in 
acquiring the skill—for the simple reason that the homogeneous dots 
and the homogeneous dashes of the Morse sequence offer no distin- 
guishable characteristics for the forming of specific S.-R. connections. 
The letter V is transmitted by dot-dot-dash; the letter *w' by dot- 
dash-dash. In terms of S.-R. theory, the finger-movement made in 
sending the first dot is the initial part-response which triggers the chain, 
its kinaesthetic sensation acting as a stimulus which calls out the next 
response. But the correct response to the same stimulus will be either 
dot or dash; nothing in the nature of the stimulus itself indicates what 
the next response should be; the response is determined at this and each 
following step not by the preceding stimulus but by the total pattern. The 

habit cannot be represented by a linear series : • > > • — • 

it can only be represented as a two-tired hierarchic structure: 




Figure 17 



The related skill of touch-typing was studied by Book, 3 who wired 
his machines to time every move made by the experimental subjects. 
In this case the letter habit is acquired by pUce-learning'-— the key- 
board is hidden from the student by a screen, and he is required to form 
a 'map' of its layout in his head. This map, one supposes, is structured 
by a simple co-ordinate-system: the fixed resting position of the ten 
fingers on the third row of the keyboard; the result is a kind of simple 



54<5 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



'maze' with variable target positions. But when, after a certain amount 
of hit and miss, the letter habit had been mastered: 

further practice gave results unexpected by the learner. He found 
himself anticipating the sequence of finger movements in a short, 
familiar word. Habits were developing for groups of letters such as 
prefixes, suffixes, and short words. ... 'A word simply means a 
group of movements which I attend to as a whole. I seem to get 

beforehand a sort of feel of the whole group' The single letters 

were no longer thought of and each word became an automatic 
sequence. . . . Familiar phrases were similarly organized, the thought 
of the phrase calling out the whole series of connected movements. 4 

Yet even phrases ending with a full stop did not prove to be the 
highest units. The records showed no pauses between phrases' but 
an even flow; and here, too, 'the eyes [on the text to be copied] were 
well ahead of the hands' — to enable the typist to take in the meaning. 

As a third example let us consider learning to play the piano (though 
I could find no textbook references to this not altogether unusual human 
occupation). The 'letter habit' here becomes a note habit' — hitting 
the intended black or white key; for 'word' read 'bar' or 'musical 
phrase'; and so on to more complex integrated patterns. In this case, 
however, even the lowest unit of the skill—hitting the right key- 
displays considerable flexibility. There is no longer, as on the type- 
writer, a rigid attribution of each key to one finger; on the piano 
keyboard almost any finger can be used, according to circumstances, 
to hit any key; several keys may be hit and held at the same time; and 
a hard or soft touch makes all the difference to musical quality. (Need- 
less to say, even the typist's motion-patterns must be adaptable to small 
portables and large office niachines, and the starting position of the 
finger varies according to the preceding stroke. Flexibility is a matter 
of degrees; a completely fixed response is, like the reflex arc, an 
abstraction.) 

The skill of hitting the correct piano-key is not acquired by es- 
tablishing point-to-point correspondences, but primarily by practising 
the various scales; these superimpose, as it were, structured motions 
on to the keyboard, sub-structured into triads, septdms, etc. At an 
advanced stage, when improvization has become possible, the left 
hand will learn to accompany the right, which acts as a 'pace-maker' — 
a glorified form of the magnet effect in the gold-fish (p. 438); but the 



MOTOR SKILLS 



547 



left can also act in relative independence, according to the commands 
of the score. At this level we have approximately the following state of 
affairs: the visual input consists in two groups of parallel rows (staves) 
of coded signals, of which the upper series must be referred to the 
right, the lower to the left hand. In the course of this procedure both 
rows of signals must be de-coded and re-coded. The symbols on the 
two rows are usually in different parallel codes (Violin clef* for the 
right, 'bass clef for the left). Moreover, there are 'key signatures' — 
sharp and flat signs — at the beginning of a section, which modify the 
'face value' of the notes; there are symbols which indicate the timing 
and duration of notes; and overall instructions regarding loudness, 
tempo and mood. All these part-dependent, part-independent de- and 
re-coding operations for both hands must proceed simultaneously, in 
the psychological present, and more or less automatically. 

On an ever higher level, the concert pianist develops a repertory of 
ceuvres that he can 'trigger off' as units and play by heart — though 
some of these units may be an hour long. Once again we must assume 
that this is done by a combination of several interlocking hierarchies, 
each articulated into sub-wholes and the sub-wholes thereof. 

Then there is improvisation. It need not be creative; the bar- 
pianist who, half asleep, syncopates Chopin and trails off into some 
variation of his own, is not a composer; but he has gained additional 
flexibility — more degrees of freedom — in the practice of his skill. And 
finally there is the creative act: the composer who weaves his threads 
into new patterns, and the interpreter who sheds new light on existing 
patterns. 

The learning process is, somewhat paradoxically, cssiest to visualize 
as a reversal of the hierarchic sequence of operations which will 
characterize performance when learning is completed. When the 
typist copies a document, the sequence of operations is initiated on the 
semantic level, then branches down into successive lower levels with 
increasingly specific 'fixed action-patterns' — 'word-habits' and 'letter- 
habits'; terminating in the 'consummatory act' of the finger muscles. 
The impulses arborize downwards and outwards, whereas learning 
proceeds in the reverse direction: the tips of the twigs of the future 
tree are the first to come into existence; the twigs then grow together 
centripetally into branches, the branches merge into the trunk. It 
strikes one as a very artificial procedure; but the type of mechanical 
learning we have discussed, where the discrete base-units must be 
stamped in bit by bit, is indeed an artificial procedure. The difference 



548 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



between this method of learning through trial and error and learning 
'by insight' becomes glaringly obvious if you compare what happens 
during an elementary violin lesson and an equally elementary singing 
lesson. The choir boy can rely on his innate, multiple auditory-vocal 
feedbacks — operating through the air, through his bones, and through 
proprioceptive sensations from his vocal tract — to control his voice. 
But there exist no innate feedbacks between the violin student's cochlea 
and finger-muscles, to control their motions. No amount of theoretical 
insight into the working of the instrument can replace this handicap; 
it can only be overcome by supplementing insight with trial and 
error. In other words, human beings are biologically less 'ripe' for 
learning the violin than for learning to sing. If evolution were to 
produce a super-cricket or cicada sapiens, the opposite may be true. 

To put it in a different way: the built-in feedbacks of the auditory- 
vocal apparatus provide a direct insight into the Tightness or wrong- 
ness (singing out of tune) of the response; they permit an immediate 
'perception of relations' — which is Thorpe's definition of insight. But 
once more, this insight is far from absolute: when it comes to pro- 
fessional singing, a heart-breaking amount of drill is required. The 
pupil is often taught the proper techniques of breathing with his hand 
on the teacher's stomach — because his insight into, and control of, 
his own physiological functions is limited. Verbal instructions are of 
little help, and are sometimes a hindrance, in the acquisition of muscle 
skills; to become clever with one's hands, or one's feet in dancing, 
requires a kind of muscle training which defies classification as either 
insightful or trial-and-error learning. 

I have repeatedly mentioned the mysteries of riding a bicycle: 
nobody quite knows how it is done, and any competent physicist 
would be inclinded to deny a priori that it can be done. However, as a 
two-legged primate, man has an innate 'ripeness* for the acquisition 
of all kinds of postural and balancing skills such as skating, rock- 
climbing, or walking the tight-rope; accordingly, the hierarchy of 
learning processes in the case of the cyclist starts on a higher level of 
already integrated sub-skills, than in the examples previously dis- 
cussed. Broadly speaking, the pupil must turn the handle-bar in the 
direction he is falling, which will make him tend to fall in the opposite 
direction, and so forth, until he gradually 'gets the feel' of the amount 
of correction required. This is certainly trial-and-error learning in the 
sense that errors are punished by a fall; but the trials are by no means 
random, and the errors arc all in the right direction—they merely over- 



MOTOR SKILLS 



549 



or under-shoot the mark. The code which is formed by successive 
adjustments of the neural 'servo-mechanism* is presumably of the 
analogue-computer type— and the same applies probably to dancing, 
skating, or tennis-playing. 

But once the skill has been mastered and formed into a habit, its 
integrated pattern is represented as a unit on the next-higher level in 
the hierarchy, and can be triggered off by a single (verbal or non- 
verbal) command. To take a more complicated example: the soccer- 
player must acquire a variety of basic routines of taking command of 
the ball — 'stopping' it with foot, thigh, chest, or head; volleying it in 
flight without stopping; kicking it with the instep, the inner or outer 
side-wall of the boot; dribbling, passing, and shooting at the goal, etc. 
When these elementary, yet very complex, techniques have been 
mastered, each of them will become a self-contained sub-skill in his 
repertory, and he will be able to decide, in a split second, which of 
them to employ according to the layout of the field. The decision 
whedier to shoot or pass is based on discrete yes-no alternatives of the 
digital type; but the execution of the actual move — shooting, passing, 
etc. — seems to require an analogue-computer type of code. A further 
step down the 'analogue' process of flexing the leg-muscles for a pass 
of appropriate length is again converted into the digital on-off pro- 
cesses in individual motor units; while on the top level a fluid strategy 
is converted into discrete tactical decisions. 

It would seem that behavioural matrices on every level of a given 
hierarchy are triggered off by digital-type all-or-nothing impulses; 
if the matrix is flexible it will function as a digital-to-analogue con- 
verter; and will in its turn trigger off sub-codes at certain critical 
limits as analogue-to-digital converters. But theorizing about the 
nervous system in terms of computer models is a risky affair, and may 
yet lure psychology into a cul-de-sac — as the telephone-exchange 
model did half a century ago.* 

Summary: Rigidity and Freedom 

Let me recapitulate some points which emerge when the observations 
in the present chapter are taken in conjunction with the broader 
issues discussed in Book One. 

On the elementary levels of learning a skill a varying amount of 
stamping-in is required, depending on the organism's ripeness* for 



550 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the task; or, to put it the other way round, depending on the natural- 
ness* of the task relative to the organism's existing skills. Learning to 
type requires more stamping-in than learning to ride a bicycle; the 
former is comparable to the blindfold memorizing of a maze, the 
latter to the gradual adjustment of various interlocking servo- 
mechanisms. In both cases the learning process consists in the integra- 
tion of elementary skills — the members of the nascent matrix — into 
a single pattern which can be activated as a unit. But even in acquiring 
a mechanical skill like typing, bit-by-bit learning plays in fact a lesser 
part than seems to be the case. The typist's mental map of the key- 
board is not simply a rote-learned aggregation of twenty-six letters 
(plus numbers and signs) distributed at random; it is a 'coded' map, 
structured by a system of co-ordinates — the resting position of the 
fingers — and by the frequency-rating of letters, syllables, etc. These 
patterns, superimposed on the keyboard map, could be compared to 
the mnemonic aids used in the learning of nonsense syllables. Whole- 
learning invades bit-learning at every opportunity; if the meaningless 
is to be retained, the mind must smuggle meaning into it. 

Once a skill has been mastered so that it can be activated as a unit it 
functions more or less autonomously and automatically. This applies 
to both perceptual and motor skills, from the perceptual constancies 
and motor reflexes upwards. Learning to find the right key on the 
keyboard -requires concentration, focal awareness; but when the 
letter-habit has been acquired it becomes 'instinctive', unconscious; 
attention is freed to concentrate on meaning, and can 'let the fingers 
take care of themselves'; their control is relegated to lower levels of 
awareness and, in all likelihood, to lower levels in the nervous system. 
Thus the work of Gastaut and Beck clearly suggests that 'once we 
have learned something we no longer rely so much on our cortex 
and reticular formation. Those things we do "without thinking" . . . 
may depend more on the older primitive parts of the nervous system 
such as the limbic structures, thus releasing higher centres such as the 
cortex for other tasks. . . • Common sense indicates such a possibility; 
electro-physiology suggests it. . . .' s * 

The same skilled action — driving a motor-car or playing a nocturne 
by heart— can be performed automatically, or in semi-conscious 
absent-mindedness, or with full concentration. But the motorist who 
concentrates on driving fast along a crowded road has his attention 
focussed on matters of general strategy — e.g. whether it is safe to over- 
take or not, whereas the actual manipulation of the wheel and pedals 



MOTOR SKILLS 



551 



are still carried out automatically; and the pianist trying to give his 
best, still finds the keys automatically. We again find confirmed that 
the code which controls skilled behaviour always operates through 
sub-codes which function on lower levels of awareness. Shifting the 
focus of attention to these sub-codes produces the familiar paradox 
of the centipede'. Its equivalent in perception is the loss of meaning 
which results when a word is repeated monotonously and attention 
becomes focussed on the Klangbild (cf. 'ce-du, ce-du, ce-du\ Book 
One, p. 75 f.; even more painful is the semantic paralysis which some- 
times befalls a writer while correcting the proofs of a forthcoming 
book. 

The lower we descend in the hierarchy the more stereotyped, re- 
flex-like activities we find; and vice versa, flexibility increases with each 
step upward. The more complex the skill, the more alternative varia- 
tions it offers for adaptable strategies: a matrix on the n+ 1 level has 
more degrees of freedom than a matrix on the n level. But whether 
they will be utilized and produce varied performance, depends on the 
environment. Monotonous environments induce repetitive, stereo- 
typed habits; the degrees of freedom in the matrix freeze up. 'Over- 
learning , is the fixation, through repetition in unvarying conditions, 
of one among many possible variations in the exercise of a skill at the 
expense of all others. Thus habits become automatized (a) because 
they operate on the lower strata of the hierarchy with few degrees of 
freedom, like hitting a typewriter key or depressing the accelerator 
pedal; (b) when a complex skill is reduced through environmental 
monotony to a single-track habit. 'Monotony' is of course a subjective 
term referring to lack of change in those features of the environment 
which are relevant to the subject's interests. For all we know the 
streets of Koenigsberg through which Emmanuel Kant took his fixed 
walk at a fixed hour for forty years might have been wildly exciting 
to another person. 

The integration of motor-patterns into larger and more complex 
skills in the process of learning is paralleled by a similar progression 
on the perceptual side. The telegraphist who has advanced from 'letter- 
habits' through 'word-habits' to 'phrase-habits' in his sending tech- 
nique, has at the same time learned to take in several words and even 
phrases 'at a mouthful'. The pianist takes in a whole musical phrase 
from the score at a glance; both input and output are no longer 
measured in bits but in chunks.* The more complex the skill, the 
bigger the chunks in space or time which must be taken into account. 



552 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



The skilled soccer player keeps his eye on the ball, but is at the same 
time aware of the positions and peculiarities of the other players on the 
field. The motorist, driving to his office, chooses the least congested 
road among several alternatives by consulting the mental map in his 
head. The typist, who deliberately lags a phrase or two behind dic- 
tation, expands the duration of the psychological present to take in a 
bigger chunk of meaning. While listening tp speech or music we do 
the same; while talking we trigger off long sequences of muscular 
patterns as a whole. As we become more proficient in any skilled 
activity, we learn 'to put feedback loops around larger and larger 
segments of our behaviour'. 6 

Though motor learning proceeds, generally speaking, from lower 
to higher levels, and performance in the reverse direction, this does 
not mean that in performing we run through the whole gamut of the 
learning process in reverse gear. As one learns to play a sonata by 
heart, one needs less and less often to consult the score, and in the end 
the visual feedback which was indispensable during learning can 
be dispensed with entirely; the habit now functions autonomously. 
The skilled pianist can play blindfold, a man can knot his tie without 
looking into the mirror, the physician can tell the patient's pulse 
without looking at his watch, the adult reads without spelling out the 
letters. When the skill has been mastered, the props which served the 
learning process are kicked away — as Maxwell kicked away the 
scaffolding of his mechanical model when he arrived at his equations 
(see Appendix I). In this respect, too, the learning process is irreversible. 

The autonomy of the codes which pattern behaviour is a phenomenon 
which we have met on all levels — from the self-regulatory activities 
of the morphogenetic field, through the fixed action-patterns of 
instinct behaviour, to the perceptual frames responsible for constan- 
cies, illusions, and our ways of seeing the world through coloured 
filters, as it were. But on the level of complex skills, the 'self-assertive' 
tendencies of acquired motor-patterns are particularly striking. To 
repeat an obvious example, one cannot disguise one's handwriting 
sufficiently to fool the expert; even the skilled burglar has his indi- 
vidual style in safe-breaking which gives him away. Autonomy and 
self-government are basic principles in the hierarchy of skills. Thus 'the 
performance of very quick movements', Lashley observed, 'indicates 
their independence of current control. "Whip-snapping" movements 
of the hand can be regulated in extent, yet the entire movement, from 
initiation to completion requires less than the reaction time for a 



MOTOR SKILLS 



553 



tactile or kinaesthetic stimulation of the arm, which is about one- 
eighth of a second, even when no discrimination is involved. . . . The 
finger-strokes of a musician may reach sixteen per second in passages 
which call for a definite and changing order of successive finger- 
movements. The succession of movements is too quick even for visual 
reaction time. . . . Sensory control of movement seems to be ruled 
out in such acts.' 7 

Similar conclusions were reached, as already mentioned, by Ruch, 
concerning voluntary movement in general. In view of the rapidity 
of skilled movements which are too fast to leave room for visual or 
proprioceptive feedback control, Ruch, like Lashley, assumed the 
operation of pre-set time-tension patterns of muscle contraction in the 
nervous system: 'The cerebral-cerebellar circuit may represent not so 
much an error-correcting device as a part of a mechanism by which an 
instantaneous order can be extended in time . . . and thus reduce the 
troublesome transients involved in the correction of movement by 
output-informed feedbacks/ 8 

The tendency to reduce those 'troublesome' feedbacks to a minimuni 
is the essence of habit-formation and automatization. It follows the 
principle of parsimony; if we had to concentrate on each movement 
we made, there would be no room for thought. On the other hand, 
this inherent tendency to form neural organizations which, one might 
say, jealously defend their autonomy against interference from a 
changing outside world, makes us all, in varying degrees, the slaves of 
habit. We may reduce the degree of enslavement, but the basic pre- 
dicament is inherent in the hierarchic structure or nervous organiza- 
tion, where 'the structure of the input does not produce the structure 
of the output, but merely modifies intrinsic nervous activities that 
have a structural organization of their own'. The quotation (repeated 
from p k 434) referred to instinct behaviour and the lower motor 
functions, but it is equally applicable, as we have seen, to complex, 
acquired skills. These may have a high degree of flexibility, but they 
nevertheless operate through automatized sub-skills on the lower 
ranges of the hierarchy, which manifest themselves in the individual 
'touch' of the pianist, the 'style' of the tennis-player, the fixed man- 
nerisms, quirks, idiosyncrasies, and unconscious rituals which are our 
personal hallmarks. 

How much of his potential freedom a person puts to active use 
depends partly on environmental factors — the novelty, intensity, 
vexatiousness, etc., of the stimuli to which he is exposed. But the 



554 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



nature and amount of stimulation derived from a given input depends, 
of course, on personality structure. One type of individual will 
respond to monotonous situations with stereotyped reactions; another 
type will find monotony vexatious, that is to say, stimulating. 'Active 
boredom', as this kind of reaction may be called, can provide alter- 
natives to habituation; the subject may experience the very absence of 
change as a novelty — as prison is a novelty to the first offender; and 
since the environment refuses to offer variety, he will vary his own 
performance to provide it. Hence the apparently spontaneous changes 
in fashions and crazes, not only in human society but also in colonies 
of captive chimpanzees. 

If, on the other hand, the challenge from the environment exceeds 
a critical limit, behaviour will either become distintegrated, or the 
challenge will be met by an original, 'super-flexible' response — a re- 
structuring of the pattern of the skill. We have met examples of this 
on all levels, from the 'prenatal skills' of morphogenesis, through 
Bethe's mutilated insects to Lashley's rats and Kohler's chimpanzees. 
The complex, acquired motor-skills, which we discussed in this 
chapter, are capable of equally impressive emergency-reorganizations. 
The first aircraftsman who, when his brakes refused to function on 
landing, saved his plane by opening his parachute through the rear- 
window, achieved a true bisociation of two unconnected skills. The 
violinist who finishes his piece in spite of a broken E string; the typist 
managing on a half-broken machine; the secret tunnel-builders in 
prisoner-of-war camps; the legless war pilot winning a Victoria Cross; 
Renoir, crippled with arthritis, continuing to paint with a brush 
fixed to his forearm — they all gave proof of an unexpected, creative 
surplus-potential in the nervous system. Such accomplishments are 
more impressive than the quasi-miraculous feats performed in panic 
or rage — the latter are of a quantitative order and do not involve the 
reorganization of pattern. 

The homologous nature of the basic principles which operate on 
different levels of the hierarchy becomes evident when we remember 
the conclusions which emerged from the discussion of instinct be- 
haviour: 'At one end of the scale we find rituals, fixed action-patterns, 
vacuum and displacement activities — rigid, automatized, and com- 
pulsive, petrified habits. At the other extreme we find . . . codes which 
govern behaviour of remarkable flexibility, and original adaptations 
which lie outside the animal's normal skills and habit repertory.' 10 



NOTES 



To p. 549. See, for instance, the rather desperate footnote on p. 197 of 
Miller et al (i960) : 'One reason for much of the trouble on reaching an agreement 
about the way the brain works was that two of the authors stubbornly persisted 
in trying to talk about it in terms appropriate to the dry hardware of modern 
digital computers, whereas the third was equally persistent in using language 
appropriate to the wet software that lives inside the skull. After a decade of 
cybernetics you might think the translation from one of these languages into the 
other would be fairly simple, but that was not the case. The relation between 
computers and brains was a batde the authors fought with one another until the 
exasperation became unbearable.' 

To p. 550. Experiments by S. M. Evans (New Scientist, 2 May, 1963) have 
shown that the supraoesophageal ganglia of the ring-worm (its 'brain') are essen- 
tial for learning but not for memory storage since learned habits will be retained 
after removal of the 'brain*. Once the habit is acquired, it is apparendy trans- 
ferred 'to a storage centre which is presumably somewhere else in the nervous 
system'. 

To.p. 551. Cfalso: 'in rapid sight reading it is impossible to read the individual 
notes of an arpeggio. The notes must be seen in groups, and it is actually easier 
to read chords seen simultaneously and to translate them into temporal sequence 
than to read successive notes in the arpeggio as usually written' (Lashley in the 
Hixon Symposium, p. 123). 



555 



XII 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 
A Glance in Retrospect 

In the course of the past fifty years, learning theory has been one 
of the central battlefields of psychology. 'One may say broadly*, 
Bertrand Russell wrote in 1927, 'that all the animals that have been 
carefully observed have behaved so as to confirm the philosophy in 
which the observer believed before his observations began. Nay, more, 
they have all displayed the national characteristics of the observer. 
Animals studied by Americans rush about frantically, with an incredible 
display of hustle and pep, and at last achieve the desired result by 
chance. Animals observed by Germans sit still and think, and at last 
evolve the situation out of their inner consciousness. To the plain man, 
such as the present writer, this situation is discouraging. I observe, 
however, that the type of problem which a man naturally sets to an 
animal depends upon his own philosophy, and that this probably 
accounts for the differences in the results.' 1 

Russell's remarks remain true, even though some eminent psycho- 
logists deny that they have a philosophy at all and hold all theory- 
making to be 'wasteful and misleading'. 2 Not only the choice of 
problem, but also the choice of animals is characteristic of the ex- 
perimenter's bias. Kohler, desirous to prove insight and intelligence, 
concentrated mainly on chimpanzees. Skinner's best-known books 
are called The Behaviour of Organisms (1938) and Science and Human 
Behaviour (1953); but — as Hilgard said — 'neither title betrays that the 
precise data were derived largely from experiments on rats and pigeons. 
It is somewhat anomalous that a systematist who refuses to predict 
what a rat or pigeon will do — because such prediction does not belong 
in a scientific study of behaviour — is willing to make confident 
assertions about the most complex forms of human behaviour, eco- 
nomic, political, religious'. 8 

55<5 



THE PITFALLS OP LEARNING THEORY 



557 



Hull's attempt to create an all-embracing theory of behaviour 
was almost entirely based on the bar-pressing activities of rats. This 
was considered by Hull and his school as a sufficiently solid basis to 
derive from them 'the basic laws of behaviour . . . including the social 
behaviour of man'. 4 

Lasdy, the German school of ethologists — Lorenz, Tinbergen, etc. 
— concentrated mainly on highly ritualized forms of animal life in 
birds and insects. Thus each school developed its special universe of 
discourse, moving in a closed system, concentrating on their favourite 
animals in their favourite experimental situations — dogs dripping 
saliva through fistulae, cats raging in puzzle-boxes, rats rurining 
through mazes, geese being 'imprinted' by Dr. Lorenz ambling on 
all-fours. 

But the data from these highly specialized, experimental trends did 
not add up to a coherent picture, and each school had a tendency to 
ignore what the others were doing. Thus, for instance, in Skinner's 
Science and Human Behaviour, which was intended as a textbook, the 
index contains neither the word 'insight', nor the names of Kohler, 
Koffka, Lewin, Tolman, Hull, Lashley, or Lorenz; only Thorndike 
and Pavlov are mentioned by name as theorists of learning with some 
merit. And vice versa, I have searched in vain for the name of Pavlov 
in the indices of Kohler's and KofFka's books. 5 Thus much of the 
controversies in learning theory resembled less a battle than a game of 
blind man's buff. 

How, just at a time when the mechanistic conceptions of the nine- 
teenth century had been abandoned in all branches of science, from 
physics to embryology; how just at that time, in the 1920s, the concept 
of man as a rigid mechanism of chained reflexes could become fashion- 
able in cultures as different as the United States and the Soviet Union 
is a fascmating problem for the historian of science. The Pavlovian 
school in Russia, and the Watsonian brand of Behaviourism in 
America, were the twentieth-century postscript to the nineteenth 
century's mechanistic materialism, its belated and most consistent 
attempt to describe living organisms in terms of machine theory. 



The Denial of Creauitity 



Nearly half a century has passed since the publication of Watson's 
Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviourist (i$tf0), and few students 



558 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



today remember its contents or even its basic postulates. In Watson's 
second book (1924) there is a chapter entided: ' Talking and Thinking — 
Which, When Rightly Understood, Go Far In Breaking Down the Fiction 
That There Is Any Such Thing As "Mental" Life.' In this chapter, the 
behaviouristic view on the creative activities of man is set down in a 
simple and striking way (all italics are Watson's) : 

How the new comes into being: One natural question often raised is: 
How do we ever get new verbal creations such as a poem or a 
brilliant essay? The answer is that we get them by manipulating words, 

shifting them about until a new pattern is hit upon It will help us to 

go to manual behaviour. How do you suppose Patou builds a new 
gown? Has he any picture in his mind' of what the gown is to look 

like when it is finished? He has not He calls his model in, picks up 

a new piece of silk, throws it around her; he pulls it in here, he pulls 
it out there, makes it tight or loose at the waist, high or low, he makes 
the skirt short or long. He manipulates the material until it takes on 
the semblance of a dress. . . . The painter plies his trade in the same 
way, nor can the poet boast of any other method. 6 

The key word is 'ru^pu^on, defined by Watson as an 'instinctive 
tendency sometimes exalted by calling it constructiveness. That there 
is an original tendency to reach out for objects, to scrape them along 
the floor, to pick them up, put them into the mouth, to throw them 
upon the floor, to move back and forth any parts which can be moved, 
is one of the best grounded and best observed of the instincts/ 7 That 
is all we learn about manipulation. It is a random activity, which, 
through elimination of useless movements by the trial-and-error 
method, gradually develops into ordered habits. The rat, put into an 
unknown maze, goes on manipulating its motor-organs at random 
until it hits upon the food in the same way as (the comparison is 
Watsons own 8 ) Patou manipulates the piece of silk until he hits upon 
a new model; likewise, the poet or essayist 'shifts about' words 'until 
a new pattern is hit upon. It is expressly denied that Patou, the poet, 
or painter has any 'picture in his mind' of the kind of thing he is 
planning; he simply goes on manipulating his units until the model, 
poem, or drama is 'hit upon. At that moment the stimulus 'to arouse 
adjuration and condemnation ceases to be active, and manipulation 
stops — 'the equivalent of the rat's finding food'. 9 

Obviously, viewed from this angle, psychology presents no prob- 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 



559 



lems. Yet the matter is of more than historical interest, because, 
although the cruder absurdities of Watsonian behaviourism are for- 
gotten, it had laid the foundations on which the later, more refined 
behaviouristic systems were built; the dominant trend in American 
and Russian psychology in the generation that followed had a dis- 
tinctly Pavlov-Watsonian flavour. 'Each of these systems', Hilgard 
wrote (referring to the immensely influential schools of Guthrie, 
Hull, and Skinner*) 'represents in its own way a fulfilment of the 
behaviouristic programme originally proposed by Watson.' 10 The 
methods became more sophisticated, but the philosophy behind them 
remained the same. Originality and creativeness have no place in it. 

For Guthrie, the original solution of a problem 'must be in the 
category of luck, and hence He outside of science'. 11 In Skinner's 
works, as I have just said, the word 'insight' does not occur; and the 
technique of problem-solving is, in Skinner's view as in Watson's, 
'merely that of manipulating variables which may lead to the emission 
of the response. No new factor of originality is involved/ 12 Hull 
expressly postulated that the differences in the learning processes of 
man and rat are of a merely quantitative, not of a qualitative order: 

'The natural-science theory of behaviour being developed by the 
present author and his associates assumes that all behaviour of the 
individuals of a given species and that of all species of mammals, 
including man, occurs according to the same set of primary laws.* 13 
The verbal and mathematical symbolism of man, verbal communica- 
tion and written records, were considered to differ only in degree, 
not in kind, from the learning achievements of the lower animals, 
epitomized in the bar-pressing activities of the rat. 'Hull did not 
intend merely to systematize the account of rat lever-pressing, from 
which most of the data for his later set of postulates derived. He in- 
tended to arrive at the basic laws of behaviour, at least the laws of the 
behaviour of mammalian organisms, including the social behaviour 
of man/ 14 ** 

The state of affairs in that period has been succinctly summed up 
by Osgood: 

Lloyd Morgan's canon — that the behaviour of animals should not 
be explained in terms of human attributes if it can be explained on a 
lower level — was designed to counteract the common tendency to 
put oneself in an animal's place and explain its actions in terms of 
what we would do in that situation It is interesting that through 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the behaviouristic phase in which American psychology has been 
moving, Lloyd Morgan's canon has been subtly inverted. Many 
present-day psychologists are loath to attribute to humans any 
characteristics that cannot be demonstrated in lower animals. 15 

In other words, for the anthropomorphic view of the rat, American 
psychology substituted a rattomorphic view of man. 

The Advent of Gestalt 

A turning point seemed to have been reached with the publication 
of Kohler's Mentality of Apes in 1925. The Gestalt school had been 
steadily growing in Germany since Wertheimer's first papers in 1912. 
As already mentioned, the German edition of Kohler's ape book 
appeared in 1917, but the first American translation only eight years 
later. Imagine Einstein's General Relativity theory, also published in 1917, 
reaching America with an eight years' delay! Yet physicists are supposed 
to have a limited, psychologists a broad and open-minded, oudook. 

The historical merit of the Gestalt schbol was, beside its concrete 
discoveries about perceptual organization, to crystallize the convergent 
trends towards a new, dynamic conception of the organism as a living 
whole — and not merely as the sum of its parts. Such trends had been 
developing since the beginning of the century, independently from one 
another, in biology, embryology, neuro-physiology, and in psycho- 
logy itself. But only when the new terms 'Gestalt', 'configuration', and 
'functional whole' became fashionable slogans comparable to Rela- 
tivity and the Oedipus Complex — did this silent revolution penetrate 
into the broader public's mind and convey some vague idea of a new 
orientation towards the problems of organic life and the human 
intellect. 

However, the great expectations which Gestalt aroused were 
only partly fulfilled; and its limitations soon became apparent. 
Gestalt-explanations seemed to flourish only in the area of their 
origin, visual perception; when it was attempted to transplant them 
into the fields of cognition, memory, neuro-physiology, even the 
other sense-modalities, they seemed to wilt away. Some of these 
limitations I have already mentioned in previous chapters; the am- 
biguities of the central concept of 'insight' will be discussed in the 
next one. The result was a kind of abortive Renaissance, followed by a 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 



behaviourist Counter-Reformation. The neo-Behaviourists, having 
incorporated some of the Gestalt findings into their theories, had 
indeed a remarkable come-back; the Gestaltists remained more or 
less firmly entrenched in their positions which displayed good 
closure' all round. The experimental evidence was mostly inconclusive; 
some of it proved damaging to one school, but without directly con- 
firming the contentions of the other. Each camp was divided in itself; 
and (apart from the 'lone voices' of the elder generation) a 'third 
force' began to make itself increasingly felt, comprising such out- 
standing freelances as Tolman and Hebb, who stood with one foot in 
each camp, as it were. Hebb has compared the situation to 'the running 
battle between the Left and Right' 16 where each party, while shouting 
its own slogans, tacitly keeps adopting ideas originally advanced by its 
opponents. All this, of course, refers to the American scene; but in 
England, at least, developments followed similar lines. 

In spite of this rapprochement, and the new outlook of a younger 
generation (cf. the chapter on Motivation), some basic differences 
still divide learning theory into two broadly outlined camps — differ- 
ences not on points of fact, but on their interpretations — on explicidy 
stated or tacidy implied axioms, general oudook and selective em- 
phasis. These can be briefly schematized as follows: 

S.-R. Theories contra Cognitive Theories 

Conditioning Insight 



Chained responses, 
stamped in bit by bit 

Gradual learning by 
trial and error 

Acquisition of habits and 
skills through reinforcement 

Emphasis on peripheral, 
sensory motor activity 

Emphasis on discrete 
stimuli, cm parts aixd 
perceptual elements 



Patterned, flexible 
responses adapted to the 
total situation 
Sudden learning and 
problem-solving through 
insight. 

Acquisition of knowledge 
(Cognitive structures') 
through latent learning 
Emphasis on central 
cognitive processes 

Emphasis on relation- 
patterns, wholes, 
perceptual Gestalten 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



S.-IL Theories 
Motivation = reinforcement 
by need- or drive-reduction, 
or anticipation thereof 

Continuous linear gradient 
leading from rat to man 



contra Cognitive Theories 

Motivation by exploratory 
drive, or its combination 
with other primary drives 

Hierarchic levels of 
organization 



This schema follows (except for the last two points) by and large 
Hilgard's classification of 'issues on which learning theories divide*. 17 
Only a few prominent psychologists would subscribe to all the 
principles listed in either of the two columns; but a majority of them 
would probably subscribe to the majority of the principles in a single 
column. 

The core of the controversy could be summed up in shorthand as 
'drill* versus 'insight*. The answer, already suggested, seems to be 
that the various methods of learning form a continuum extending 
from classical conditioning at one end to spontaneous, intelligent 
problem-solving at the other, while in the intermediary ranges we 
find various combinations between drjUed-in and insightful learning, 
depending on the animal's ripeness for the task to be learned. This 
approach, which aims at synthesis, not compromise, is of course by no 
means original; it is shared — though for somewhat different reasons — 
by 'functionalists' like Woodworth, behaviourists like Hebb, and 
ethologists like Thorpe. Thus Hilgard wrote on the 'functionalist 
outlook': 'laming is not blind on the one hand and insightful on the 
other; there are degrees of understanding involved from a minimum 
at one extreme to a maximum at the other, with most cases falling 
between these extremes.' 18 However, the definitions of 'insight' and 
'understanding* vary, which leaves us with the same problem, only in 
a different formulation. Let us try to get closer to it by considering 
some typical examples of animal learning. 



Conditioning and Empirical Induction 

A newly hatched chick will peck at grains, worms, caterpillars in its 
neighbourhood. If a so-called cinnabar caterpillar is now placed before 
the chick, of which species it has no previous experience, it will peck 
at it as at any other small object, but reject it at once with signs of dis- 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 5<$3 

taste. With the majority of chicks one single experience is enough to 
make it in the future avoid caterpillars by sight (The cinnabar cater- 
pillar has a distinct black and gold colouring, a visual pattern easy to 
retain.) Thus the chick has acquired a new skill, the avoidance of 
caterpillars, after a single experience (or one repetition in the case of 
less gifted chicks); and moreover, that skill, or 'cognitive structure', 
or knowledge, or whatever you call it, is a correct replica, in the 
chick's nervous system, of the relation between the visual appearance 
and disgusting nature of caterpillars. Must we ascribe insight to the 
chick; or shall we adopt the opposite viewpoint, according to which 
the single try was sufficient to eliminate the error of pecking at cater- 
pillars and to establish the avoidance reaction; and are we faced with a 
real alternative or merely a verbal quibble? Let us, for the time being, 
leave the question open. 

A dog is an animal of much greater intelligence than a chick, and 
yet in Pavlov's laboratory dogs require long series of repeated ex- 
periences for learning to relate certain perceptual signals to the immi- 
nence of food. Weeks of stamping-in are often necessary to make the 
dog differentiate between the food-signal values of a circle and an 
oval, whereas a single experience is sufficient to make the chick 
differentiate between the signal values in the appearances of a worm 
and a caterpillar. 

The reason for this contrast has already been discussed (Chapter X). 
Caterpillars belong to the natural environment of the chick; the per- 
ception of the striped creature is a biologically relevant input while the 
chick is engaged in pecking; its horrid taste makes it even more rele- 
vant; the visual input will accordingly be allowed to pass through the 
filters of the memory hierarchy, where it will be encoded and serve 
as an analyser-device for future inputs. On the other hand, gongs, 
bells, metronomes, tuning forks, cardboard figures, red lights, and 
electric shocks have no biological relevance to the species dog, nor 
to the individual dog outside the laboratory. In its natural environ- 
ment the dog would pay no attention to them, but pursue some 
exciting scent; the cardboard ellipse would never have a chance to 
form a stable trace in the dog's perceptual organization. 

How should one explain, then, that the experimenter nevertheless 
succeeds in stamping in the response? In the first place, a Pavlov dog 
in its restraining harness is not a dog, but a preparation, which can 
only be found in laboratorio. It is immobilized on the experimental 
"platform, in a soundproof laboratory, alone, cut off from all natural 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



stimuli and habitual activities; it is, so to speak, isolated under a glass 
bell. This state creates a particular stress in the animal, called the 
dog's laboratory attitude', which is sharply distinguished from its 
behaviour outside the lab. Deprived of all other stimuli and activities, 
the ticking of the metronome or the figure on the cardboard are the 
only events on which the dog's attention can focus; there is no com- 
petition between different inputs; and thus the originally irrelevant 
stimuli are gradually transformed into relevant stimuli and encoded 
in stable traces. Relevant to what? To the only biologically important 
events which are allowed to occur under the glass bell: the periodic 
appearance of meat-powder by remote control. The dog's laboratory 
attitude is dominated by this periodically repeated event; and as his 
perceptual hierarchy becomes slowly readapted to pay attention, in 
the absence of other stimuli, to the irrelevant sound of the bell, die 
nascent trace of the bell-sound will become incorporated into the 
feeding hierarchy. If the sound of the bell always overlaps with the 
appearance of the meat-powder, then the sound will eventually trigger 
off the feeding code, as the first two bars of the Marseillaise will trigger 
off the following bars; the dog will begin to salivate. But salivation 
is merely the first, anticipatory act of its feeding behaviour, and if no 
meat-powder is actually presented, it will stop there; the dog will not 
chew and snap at nothing. In the absence of food, the feeding habit 
gets no 'environmental feedback', and the activity comes to a halt at 
the expectant, salivatory stage. It is quite untrue, therefore, to say that 
the 'conditioned stimulus', e.g. the bell, has been 'substituted' for the 
'unconditioned stimulus', the meat-powder. What happened was that 
the dog has learned, by the cumulative effect of its past experience, 
to expect the appearance of the meat-powdef after lie bell, because 
that is the 'rule of the game*. He* salivates, not because he confuses the 
bell with food, but because he expects the food, signalled by the bell. We 
can say, with Polanyi, 19 that the dog has arrived at a correct empirical 
induction; or with Craik, that the dog's nervous system is now func- 
tioning 'as a calculating machine capable of modelling or parallel- 
ing external events' which is 'the basic feature of thought and of 
explanation'; 20 or in our own terms, that the invariant factor in 
a repeated sequence or experiences has been encoded in the dog's 
brain. 

All this is a far cry from the conception of reflex arcs in which USs, 
CSs» URs, and CRs are mechanically coupled together or substituted 
for each other like railway carriages in a shunting yard. In fact, the 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 565 

dog's behaviour in the strange, artificial universe where red lights 
portend food and metronomes electric shocks, is erriinently 'logical'; 
and the reason why it takes so long to stamp in the lesson is that the 
dog must readapt its entire attitude and hierarchy of values— -of what 
is important in life and what is not — to that universe, where natural 
law is replaced by Pavlov's law; a kind of Nietzschean Umwertung 
alter Werte. Perhaps the highest achievement of the dog is learning to 
discriminate between more or less flattened ellipses — for unlike its 
sharp pitch-discriniination, based on native equipment, geometrical 
forms must represent the height of irrelevance in canine eyes. Yet once 
relevance has been revalued, and the perceptual analyser-devices have 
been established, the development of sharper sub-analysers or dis- 
criminatory filters must follow the stages outlined in Chapter X.* 

In a seemingly casual aside, Hebb has remarked that 'the characteris- 
tic adult learning (outside of psychological laboratories) is learning 
that takes place in a few trials, or in one only'. 21 The implication is 
that the stamping-in of responses under artificial conditions in dogs, 
cats, or rats is quite uncharacteristic of the normal learning process. 
To try to base a human psychology on these procedures was a rather 
perverse approach. 

Do Insects have Insight? 

The work of Baerends, de Kruyt, Tinbergen, and Thorpe was rarely 
mentioned in the controversies to which I have referred, as if wasps, 
bees, fishes, and birds belonged to the fauna of another planet. As 
Thorpe remarked wistfully: 'Perhaps the arguments as to whether 
certain performances of rats in mazes represent insight or trial-and- 
error learning would have been somewhat less prolonged if the 
abilities of some of the "lower animals", such as insects, had been 

known While it surprises no one that something like latent 

learning should be displayed by mammals and by birds with their 
proverbial powers of orientation, it may come as something of a shock 
to comparative psychologists who work primarily with mammals to 
find learning of this kind displayed at a high level among inverte- 
brates. It is true that, with the confirmation of the work of von Frisch 
on the orientation of the hive-bee, we are now prepared to believe 
almost anything of bees, but there are certainly many insects other 
than bees, and many invertebrates other than insects, in which latent 



566 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



learning and similar performances can be discerned. The neglect of the 
study of invertebrate behaviour has given the impression that insight- 
learning is a characteristically human faculty hardly to be expected in 
a sub-primate mammal and, of course, out of the question in an 
arthropod. We now see what an astonishing misconception this is.' 22 
While behaviourists denied the rat the capability to acquire a mental 
map of a maze, the ethologists have shown that this is precisely what 
insects do. Their work merits consideration in some detail — which is 
done best by textual quotation. Tinbergen and de Kruyt have trained 
wasps to find their way to the nest by a configuration of certain land- 
marks (such as fir-cones and twigs). When these training marks were 
moved, and the wasp might have been expected to show complete 
disorientation, it 'will suddenly utilize new landmarks completely un- 
related to the previous orientation marks on which it had apparently 
been trained — a result which has interesting and suggestive simi- 
larity to Krechevsky's work on hypotheses in maze-learning. Many 
such examples lead us imperceptibly to what we may consider as 
insight-learning. Ammophila hunts caterpillars which are too heavy 
to be brought back on the wing, and which may thus have to be 
dragged for a hundred yards or more across and through every imagin- 
able natural obstacle. Here the original learning of the territory has 
probably been in the main affected by observation from the air, and 
yet the return has to be made on foot. Although the insect may from 
time to time leave her prey and take short survey flights, this is by no 
means invariable . . . and quite often the wasp seems able to maintain 
orientation while on the ground as a result of earlier aerial recon- 
naissance/ 23 When large obstacles (metal screens 50 by 120 centi- 
metres) were placed in its path, 'the insect diverged just enough to carry 
it round the obstacle on a perfectly smooth, even course of maximum 
economy of effort. On one particular occasion the experiment was 
immediately repeated twice with the same results, but the third time 
the insect walked straight at the screen, climbed with perfect ease to 
the top and, without ever letting go of its caterpillar, flew down to 
the ground on the other side and continued its journey. On subsequent 
occasions this insect would adopt now one type of behaviour, now 
another, but in no instance did she ever show trial and error. The 
solution to the problem was always smooth, unhesitating, and eco- 
nomical. 

*This and other individuals which behaved in the same way were 
then caught and transported in a dark box to a new site, a process 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 567 

taking less than a minute. On release the insect might have been ex- 
pected to be at least momentarily disorientated. On the contrary, it 
appeared quite unperturbed and without any orientation flight set 
out at once on its new course. It was again given the detour test three 
times on its new course, but it reacted as efficiendy as before and with- 
in a few minutes had arrived exactly on its nest. Although the insect 
too, on occasion, shows some evidence of disorientation, nevertheless 
the overwhelming impression given (as also recorded by Baerends 
(1941) and other workers) was one of almost uncanny knowledge of 
the details of the terrain.' 24 Thorpe concludes: 'In some instances it 
is possible that the homing faculty depends on no more elaborate 
sensory mechanism than that involved in simple taxes or light-com- 
pass reactions. Nevertheless, it is certain that in a large number of 
examples this is inadequate and that we have a true place memory.' 25 
In the case of at least the honey-bee, the memory is communicable. 
The orientation dance of the bee is certainly as striking an example as 
one could wish for, of place-learning encoded and re-coded into a 
symbolic motor-pattern. Yet again the question arises: if, following 
Thorpe, we call the behaviour of these insects 'insightful', have we not 
stretched the word into a kind of rubber concept? And once more the 
only description which implies neither too much nor too litde seems 
to be that the organism has contrived to build a coded model of the 
invariant and significant aspects of the territorial environment into its 
nervous system. 

The Controversial Rat 

Munn's Handbook of Psychological Research on the Rat, published in 1950, 
contains a bibliographical list of over two thousand five hundred titles; 
its rate of growth since then is anybody's guess. A considerable portion 
of this research was devoted to maze studies. Not even Newton, as 
Bertrand Russell remarked, 26 could learn a maze by any method other 
than trial and error; yet what the rat learns is not a chain of responses, 
but the pattern of the maze as a whole — as shown by the experiments 
with mutilated rats, and in others where the rat takes prompt ad- 
vantage of short-cuts when a wall is removed, and avoids newly 
created cul-de-sacs. The evidence is equally conclusive that the rat 
is capable of latent learning and of forming 'hypotheses' by 'pro- 
visional tries'. Yet the Great Rat Controversy was kept going — partly 
because S.-R. theorists kept coming up with ingenious alternative 



568 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



interpretations of the evidence, and partly because of the weighted 
character of much of the experimental procedure itself. A good 
illustration for this was the 'continuity versus non-contmuity* dispute, 
where Spence and others represented the behaviourist view against 
Krech, Lashley, etc. The results could be interpreted either or neither 
way; but — as Osgood wrote, in surnming up the controversy: 'It is 
significant with respect to methodology in psychological experi- 
mentation that, almost without exception, the studies supporting the 
Lashley view have used the jumping stand, while those supporting the 
continuity view have used a Yerkes-type discrimination box.' 27 

Not only the experimental conditions, but the experimenters' 
subjective attitudes seemed to exert their influence on the data ob- 
tained. In this respect Rosenthal's experiment on experimenters' must 
have come as a shock to students who had taken at least the 'hard and 
fast* quantitative data (if not the interpretations) of nearly half a 
century of rat experiments for granted. Rosenthal gave one group of 
his research workers rats which, he explained, were 'geniuses' specially 
bred from a stock with exceptionally good maze-learning records. 
To a second group of researchers he gave what he explained were 
'stupid rats'. La fart, all rats were of the same common-or-garden 
breed; yet the score-sheets of the 'genius rats' showed unmistakably 
that they learned to run the maze much faster than the 'stupid rats'. 28 
The only explanation Rosenthal could offer was that the bias in the 
research-workers' minds had somehow been transmitted to the rats — 
just how this was done he confessed not to know. These and other 
experiments by Rosenthal caused one science editor to comment: 
'The results throw a pall over the entire range of psychological tests 
as reported by the psychologists over the last fifty years.' 29 

Thus I shall have little more to say about the bar-pressing and maze- 
running experiments with rats. In spite of the impressive mathematical 
apparatus, and the painstaking measurements of 'rates of response', 
'habit-strength', 'fractional anticipatory goal-responses', and the rest, 
rarely in the history of science has a more ambitious theory been built 
on shakier foundations. 

The Cat in the Box 

The cat in the puzzle box, in Thorndike's classic experiments, is also 
put into a situation so designed that it can be solved only by trial and 
error. The box is equipped with contrivances such as rings, loops, 



THE 2IXFAJKEJS OF LEARNING THEORY 569 

turning bolts, pedal boards, etc., and with a door which opens, accord- 
ing to the experiment, when the animal operates one of these con- 
trivances, or several of them in a given order. Thus the cat may have 
to turn bolt B which, however, becomes loose only after bolt A has 
already been turned; or it may have to pull a string, or a loop, in order 
to free itself. When the cat is put into the box, it 'tries to squeeze 
through any opening; it claws or bites at the bars or wire; it thrusts 
its paws out through any opening, and claws at everything it reaches; 
it continues its efforts when it strikes anything loose and shaky; it may 
claw at things within the box. It does not pay very much attention 
to the food outside, but seems simply to strive instinctively to escape 
from confinement. The vigour with which it struggles is extraordinary. 
For eight or ten minutes it will claw and bite and squeeze incessantly/ 30 
The cat's behaviour is typical of that phase in a 'blocked* situation, 
where organized behaviour disintegrates and yields to more or less 
random trials. The solution — pushing a bolt or pulling a loop or even 
licking itself—will be first hit upon by chance, and after a number of 
repetitions, it will be retained; the learning curve will be more or less 
continuous or it may show a sudden, sharp drop. The objections 
against this kind of experimental design are essentially the same as 
against classical conditioning: they create an artificial universe. 'The 
solution of Thorndike's problems demanded behaviours that were 
quite beyond the animal's normal repertoire. Cats do not get out of 
boxes by pressing buttons or by washing themselves; rather they try 
to squeeze through narrow openings or scratch at the barriers, and 
Thorndike's animals were observed attempting just such solutions as 
part of their early trial and error. In other words, the correct response 
in a situation like Thorndike's could only be hit upon by sheer, blind 
chance.' 31 

The conclusion which Thorndike and his followers drew from 
these experiments — 'that animals are incapable of higher mental pro- 
cesses such as reasoning and insight — that they are limited to the 
"stamping-in" and "stamping-out" mode of trial and error' — is one 
of the most astonishing examples of question-begging in the history 
of modern science. One might just as well adapt Thorndike's method 
of reasoning to human education, teach children nonsense syllables 
which can only be learned by rote, and then conclude that children 
are only capable of learning by rote. And yet, to quote Hilgard: 'for 
nearly half a century one learning theory dominated all others in 
America, despite numerous attacks upon it and the rise of its many 



570 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



rivals. It is the theory of Edward L. Thorndike.' 32 Tolman, writing 
forty years after the publication of Thorndike's Animal Intelligence, 
went even further: 

The psychology of animal learning — not to mention that of child- 
learning — has been and still is primarily a matter of agreeing or dis- 
agreeing with Thorndike, or trying in minor ways to improve upon 
him. Gestalt psychologists, conditioned-reflex psychologists, sign- 
Gestalt psychologists — all of us here in America seem to have taken 
Thorndike, overtly or covertly, as our starting point. 324 

Cat experiments of a type diametrically opposed to Thorndike's 
were carried out by Adams. It is amusing to compare the description 
of the behaviour of Thorndike's cats which I have just quoted, with 
the behaviour of Adams' cats: 

*A piece of liver is suspended from the top of a wire-cage, so that 
the liver rests on the floor inside the cage, loosely held by the thread. 
A hungry cat in the room with the cage, but outside it, sees the liver 
and walks over to the cage. It hesitates for a time and its head moves 
up and down as though it is studying the string. Then it jumps on top 
of the cage, catches the string in its mouth, raises the liver by joint 
use of mouth and paw, and leaps down with the stick at the end of the 
string in its mouth.' 33 

The behaviour of Adams' cat, first 'thinking out' the solution of the 
problem, then acting it out in an unhesitating, smooth, purposeful 
manner, is of the same kind as Kohler's chimpanzees'. The contrast 
between this type of intelligent problem-solving, and Thorndike's 
stamping-in process seems to be complete. Yet the cat's learning in the 
box is by no means the blind, random process which Thorndike and 
his followers read into it. In the first place we must realize that the cat's 
handicap lies not only, as in classical conditioning, in the irrelevance 
of the clues which in its natural environment the cat would ignore; 
but also in the fact that the clue — say, a loop hanging from the ceiling 
— is hidden or 'drowned' among other equally irrelevant clues — latches, 
bolts, etc. The unnaturalness of the tasks set in these experiments is 
illustrated by the 'lick-yourself-to-escape* type of rule. Yet even in 
this surrealistic universe, the cat's behaviour testifies to a remarkably 
high I.Q. After the initial bewilderment, as adjustment to the labora- 
tory situation progresses, the range of the cat's tries will be narrowed 
down, and loops, bolts, etc., will be paid an increasing amount of 



THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 



571 



attention, as members of the nascent matrix. The cat develops, like 
Pavlov's dogs, an attitude of expectancy, of 'Means-End Readiness* 
(Tolman); it begins to form 'hypotheses'. 34 Thus, when the cat has 
learned to get out of the box by clawing at a loop, and the loop is 
then displaced from the front to the rear wall of the box, it will learn 
to free itself much quicker than before it had abstracted the loop- 
Gestalt from other clues. If, however, the loop is replaced by a small 
wooden platform hung in the same place which the loop occupied 
before, the animal will free itself after a short while by striking at the 
platform; in this case, the location is the clue. Thus the 'loop hypothesis' 
can exist side by side with the 'place hypothesis'— just as Krechevsky's 
rats, who had to guess whether the food was hidden by a door of a 
given colour, or of a given location, formed first a colour hypothesis, 
then a place hypothesis. 35 

At this stage, the cat's behaviour can be described as a series of 'pro- 
visional tries'. 36 These tries, far from being governed by chance, show 
great plasticity: if the cat has learned to escape by pulling a string with 
its foot, it may on the next occasion free itself by pulling the string with 
its teeth, which requires an entirely different sequence of motions. 
Even where the 'correct' response was the perverse action of licking 
its own fur, the act is reduced in the final trials 'to a mere symbolic 
vestige.' 37 

Whichever way we look at it, the cat's behaviour is most fittingly — 
if somewhat metaphorically— described as learning the rules of Thorn- 
dike's game by a process of elimination and empirical induction. The 
learning curve is a function of several variables: it will show gradual 
or sudden progress, continuity and discontinuity, according to the 
experimental conditions, individual learning capacity, fatigue, and 
chance. 

NOTES 

To p. 559. Hilgard calls Hull's system 'the most influential of the theories 
between 1930 and 1950, judging from the experimental and theoretical studies 
engendered by it, whether in its defence,its amendment or its refutation' (Hilgard, 
1958, p. 192). 

To p. 559. The objection to this is not that Hull postulated a continuous 
series linking rat to man, but that his 'primary laws' are epitomized by the bar- 
pressing act of the rat, which he regarded as the atomic unit of behaviour. The 
fallacy of this reasoning seems to be derived from Hull's implied notion of 
mental progress from rat to man as a linear gradient. Theories of this kind fail to 
take into account the hierarchic principle in mental evolution — reflected in the 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



hierarchy of levels in the nervous system. If instead of linear gradients, we think 
in terms of levels of increasing complexity, then a difference in degrees does 
become a difference in kind. Since the basic mechanisms of sexual reproduction 
are common to all mammalian species, Hull's postulate seems to imply that 
detailed study of sexual behaviour in the rat would eventually yield the 'primary 
laws' underlying the Kinsey reports on the sexual behaviour of the American 
male and female. Homologue principles (such as the part-whole relation, or 
control by feedback) do operate on all levels, but they are general principles, 
not specific 'units' or 'atoms' of behaviour. 

To p. 565. Coding is an irreversible act, and once the code is established, it 
will be relatively permanent— until it decays. If, however, the dog is fooled 
repeatedly and in quick succession ('massed practice'), i.e. food is withheld after 
the buzzer has sounded, a negative code will superimpose itself on the previous 
one. The first few times the response will stop at salivation short of chewing; but 
soon it will stop short of salivation. After a few hours' rest, however, salivation 
is restored by 'spontaneous recovery' — a paradox which has bedevilled learning 
theory for a long time. Perhaps the explanation may be sought on the following 
lines. The whole attitude of the dog, as it has become adapted to the laboratory 
situation, is based on the expectation that all stimuli are events relevant to food; and 

that the negative code (buzzer > no food), if it has been quickly superimposed 

on the positive one (buzzer >food), is of a more temporary and brittlenature 

than its opponent. If, however, the unrewarded signals are spaced out over a 
greater length of time, i,e. if the extinction-drill approximates in thoroughness 
the original drill, extinction becomes final (Cf. e.g. Hebb, 1958, pp. 134-5, 147). 



XIII 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 
More about Chimpanzees 

If the S.-R. theorist's method, of designing experiments seems to 
be aimed at printing a wiring circuit into the animal's nervous 
system, Kohler's method was to provide it with a do-it-yourself 
kit. The main task of the experimenter, as K6hler saw it, was to 
arrange for his chimpanzees conditions which favour original discovery 
by placing the necessary paraphernalia in their cage — solid and hollow 
sticks, crates, etc.; and to make the task just difficult enough to exceed, 
by a fraction as it were, the limit of the animal's repertory of skills. 

I have mentioned a few typical examples of the chimpanzees' 
achievements in Book One (Chapter V). In the use of tools the 
decisive factor was the discovery that a previously acquired playful 
technique M x could be applied as a mediating performance to solve a 
problem in the blocked matrix M 2 . Nueva applied her stick — which 
previously she had used only for pushing things about in play — to rake 
in a banana placed beyond her reach outside the cage. In similar ways, 
the chimpanzees used sticks as jumping poles to get at fruit hung high 
from the ceiling; as implements to make holes in the wire-netting of 
the cage, to dig up roots in the earth or to prise open the lid of a 
water-tank; they used sticks as traps to capture crowds of succulent 
ants, and as weapons for stabbing at fowls and killing lizards. Each 
of these new achievements was based on the combination of two or 
more already existing skills, and some of them on serial sequences of 
'Eureka processes': when a chimp had discovered the use of a stick as 
a rake, a short stick was then used to rake in a longer stick to rake in 
the bananas. 

In the making of tools we saw similar bisociative processes at work. 
Sultan's star achievement was the fitting of two hollow bamboo- 
rods together into one long rod, by pushing the end of the thinner rod 

573 



574 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



into the opening of the other. Let me describe this experiment in some 
detail: 

Sultan is given the two sticks, and the banana is placed at a distance 
from the bar greater than the length of each single stick. For quite a 
while he tries to reach the banana with one stick or the other (M 2 
obstructed, random trials). He then pulls a wooden box, which has 
been used in a different type of experiment, to the bar (fumbling for 
some M 2 to provide the 'mediating performance'). He pushes the use- 
less box away again, pushes one stick outside the bar on the ground as 
far as it will go and prods it with the second stick towards tie banana 
(M 3 : Sultan learned long ago to push a longer stick about with a 
shorter one). He succeeds in pushing the first stick into contact with 
the banana, but obviously cannot pull the banana in. Nevertheless, he 
repeats the procedure: when he has pushed one stick out of his reach 
and it is given back to him, he starts once more. 'But although, in 
trying to steer it cautiously, he puts the stick in his hand exactly to the 
cut (i.e. the opening) of the stick on the ground, and although one 
might think that doing so would suggest the possibility of pushing one 
stick into the other, there is no indication whatever of such a prac- 
tically valuable solution [no "insight"]. Finally, the observer [i.e. 
Kdhler] gives the animal some help by putting one finger into the 
opening under the animal's nose (without pointing to the other stick 
at all). This lias no effect [still no insight]; Sultan, as before, pushed 
one stick with the other towards the objective. . . .' 

He finally abandons the attempt altogether. These tries have lasted 
over an hour. The chimp was then left in the keeper's care, who 
reported later on: 

Sultan first of all squats indifferently on the box, winch has been 
left standing a little back from the railings; then he gets up, picks up 
the two sticks, sits down again on the box and plays carelessly with 
them. While doing this, it happens that he finds himself holding one 
rod in either hand in such a way that they He in a straight line; he 
pushes the thinner one a little way into the opening of the thicker, 
jumps up and is already on the run towards the railings, to which he 
lias up to now half turned his back, and begins to draw a banana 
towards him with the double stick. I call the master: meanwhile, one 
of die animal's rods has fallen out of the other, as he has pushed one 
of them only a little way into the other; whereupon he connects 
them again. 1 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



575 



Henceforth Sultan never had any difficulty in connecting two rods; 
and later on even three. 

At first sight, Sultan's achievement appears not as an integration of 
existing skills, but as the invention of a totally new one. However, 
commenting on the keeper's report, Kohler says: (my italics) *The 
keeper emphasized the fact that Sultan had first of all connected the 
sticks in play and without considering the objective [the banana]. The 
animals are constantly poking about with straws and small sticks in 
holes and cracks in their play, so that it would be more astonishing if 
Sultan had never done this [i.e. poking the thinner rod into the hole 
of the other], while playing about with the two sticks/ 2 

Thus the discovery again followed the familiar pattern of a playful 
habit being connected with a blocked matrix, with chance acting as a 
trigger. Later on, a third matrix was added: Sultan had learned long 
ago to sharpen sticks by biting off splinters, so that they could be used 
to poke in keyholes; now this skill was used to make two sticks fit 
together. Obviously, Sultan would never have invented this sophisti- 
cated method of tool-making if each of the three component skills 
(raking, poking, sharpening) had not been pre-existing items of his 
habit-repertory. The more familiar and well exercised each of the 
matrices, the more likely it is that the animal will solve the problem 
and, other things being equal, the less it will depend on the helping 
hand of chance. (In the case of the two bamboo rods which 'happened' 
to fit each other — a chance which the animal will rarely encounter in- 
the woods — we have an example of 'guided learning': the experi- 
menter serves as a match-maker in lieu of the favourable chance event; 
the rest is up to the pupil.) 

Uniform Factors in Learning 

Sultan's original achievements cannot be explained either by 
stamping-in, or by spontaneous inspiration out of the blue; they are 
integrations, of existing, flexible skills, of previously unconnected 
codes of behaviour into more complex codes of a higher order. In 
conditioning and rote-learning, the new code has to be formed more 
or less from scratch, more or less bit by bit. This 'drilling in is a 
gradual, cumulative process; whereas the bisociation of two matrices 
appears as a sudden fusion. But in between these opposite extremes 
we find a graded series of learning methods, with certain basic 



57<5 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



features common to all. Let me enumerate a few of these common 
features. 

The chimpanzee, straining to reach a banana behind the bars, 
remembers the stick lying out of sight; he runs to get it and uses it as a 
rake. This has been mentioned in the early Gestalt literature as one of 
the criteria of insight learning. But memory enters into all learning 
processes. Thus retention in delayed reaction tests has been shown to 
last in cats from three to thirteen hours, in chimpanzees up to forty- 
eight hours. 3 Another feature which we find in all types of con- 
ditioning and learning, from Pavlov upward, is expectancy and 
anticipatory behaviour. Once the stage of initial bewilderment or 
frustrated rage is passed, and the animal has embarked on learning to 
learn', random trials are superseded by less random 'fumbling tries'; 
and these in turn by hypotheses. At the Tumbling' stage, Sultan's 
behaviour in the stick-connecting experiment shows no more insight 
than the cat's: his fetching of the wooden box and attempts to push 
one stick with the second, were quite inappropriate. On the other 
hand, however, we have met with plenty of examples of comparable 
fumblings among human geniuses — of wild guesses and inappropriate 
tries preceding the act of discovery. If we remember that Kepler spent 
seven years of trial and error, pursuing false inspirations and wrong 
hypotheses before the discovery of his First and Second Laws, we are 
led to realize the subdeties and wide applications of the try-method 
— and how completely wrong it is to equate it with blind random 
behaviour. The range of learning by trial and error extends from 
relatively haphazard tries through the whole graded series, to the 
relative certainty of inductive inference. On the lower reaches the 
trials are explicit and often temperamental, like the frantic attempts of 
Thorndike's cats to get out of the box; on the higher reaches, they 
assume more and more the character of implicit hypothesis — Adams' 
cat moving its head up and down as it 'works out' the means of 
getting at the liver suspended from the string. Lastly, at the top of the 
series, the inventor toys with an idea in his head before taking the 
more explicit step of trying out several alternative sketches on paper; 
after which he may proceed to making a rough model — an even more 
explicit, but nevertheless merely symbolic try. The writer, groping 
for the right adjective, will sample several with his literary taste- 
buds; even the Lord Almighty, according to Genesis, proceeded by 
trial and error, as witnessed by the painful episode of the Flood. 



Criteria of Insight Learning 



So far, then, we have a continuous series of learning methods, where 
the amount of required stamping-in decreases in proportion to the 
animal's ripeness for the experimental task. But, according to the 
contentions of the Gestalt school, there is a decisive break in the con- 
tinuity of the series which puts insightful learning into a category apart 
from other methods of learning; and this break is said to be reflected 
in the animal's characteristic behaviour at the moment the true in- 
sightful solution occurs. In this view, Sultan's trial-and-error behaviour 
was merely a preliminary to the true solution, which emerges with 
dramatic suddenness and all in a piece; whereas in trial-and-error 
learning it emerges gradually. 

The chief descriptive characteristics of 'insight' which have been 
proposed by various authors are as follows: (a) dramatic suddeness; 
(b) 'the appearance of a complete solution with reference to the whole 
layout of the field'; 4 (c) the smooth, unhesitating manner in which 
the solution is 'suddenly, directly and definitely' 5 carried out; (d) the 
solution of the problem precedes the actual execution of it; 6 (e) the 
solution is retained after a single performance; (f) novelty of the 
solution. 7 It is furthermore generally assumed that 'insight' is closely 
related to, if not synonymous with, intelligence and understanding 
and, by implication, that trial-and-error learning is not so or to a 
lesser degree so. This last point, however, I shall discuss later; first let 
us turn to the purely descriptive aspects of 'insight learning'. 

When Kohler's experiments are discussed, the authors usually 
select the star performances of Sultan, and it is often overlooked that 
these were rather in the nature of rare limit cases. In the experiment I 
am going to describe, a young chimpanzee, Koko, was faced with the 
problem how to get a banana hung high from the wall. The only 
solution was to push a wooden box underneath the banana and to 
climb on the box. Though Koko is described by Kohler as 'just as 
gifted as Sultan', it took him no less than nineteen days to learn this — 
whereas he had learned to rake in a banana with a stick in a few minutes. 
The use of sticks is part of the chimpanzee's repertory of habits — but 
there are no wooden boxes lying about in the forest. However, before 
the experiment was started, Koko was given a small wooden box as a 
toy; 'he pushed it about and sat on it for a moment*. He was then 
removed to another cage and in his absence the banana was suspended 

577 



578 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



from the wall, three or four yards away from the wooden box (the 
italics are KohlerV. by 'objective' he means banana): 

Koko . . . first jumped straight upwards several times towards the 
objective, then took his rope in his hand, and tried to lasso the prize 
with a loop of it, could not reach so far, and then turned away from 
the wall, after a variety of such attempts, but without noticing the 
box. He appeared to have given up his efforts, but always returned 
to them from time to time. After some time, on turning away from 
the wall, his eye fell on the box: he approached it, looked straight 
towards the objective, and gave the box a slight push, which did not, 
however, move it; his movements had grown much slower; he left 
the box, took a few paces away from it, but at once returned, and 
pushed it again and again with his eyes on the ohjective, but quite gently, 
and not as though he really intended to alter its position. He turned 
away again, turned back at once, and gave the box a third tentative 
shove, after which he again moved slowly about. The box had 
now been moved 10 centimetres in the direction of the fruit. The 
objective was rendered more tempting by the addition of a piece of 
orange (the non plus ultra of delight!), and in a few seconds Koko was 
once more at the box, seized it, dragged it in one movement up to a 
point almost directly beneath the objective (that is, he moved it a 
distance of at least three metres), mounted it and tore down the fruit. 
A bare quarter of an hour had elapsed since the beginning of the 
test. 8 

All's well that ends well. But it does not. A few minutes later the 
experiment was repeated — after the banana had been moved about 
three yards from its former position, while the box was left standing 
where Koko had dragged it. When Koko was led back onto the stage: 

he sprang at the new banana in the same manner as before, but with 
somewhat less eagerness; at first he ignored the box. After a time he 
suddenly approached it, seized and dragged it the greater part of the 
distance towards the new banana, but at a distance of a quarter of a 
metre he stopped, gazed at the banana, and stood as if quite puzzled 
and confused. And now began a tale of woe for both Koko and the 
box. When he again set himself in motion it was with every sign of 
rage, as he knocked the box this way and that, but came no nearer to 
the objective. After waiting a little the experiment was broken off. 9 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



579 



This tale of woe continued for nineteen days during which the 
experiment was repeated at varying intervals; and even afterwards, 
when the new skill was firmly established at last, its performance still 
alternated for a while with random trials. 

Does Koko's behaviour satisfy the descriptive criteria of insight 
learning? 

(a) Suddenness. Yes, it does — because at the climactic moment of the 
first experiment, the solution did appear suddenly and all of a piece. 
No, it does not— because prior to it Koko had made several half- 
hearted attempts at the correct solution and yet abandoned them, 
(b) 'Complete solution with reference to the whole layout to the field'. 
The answer is, No. (c) 'Smooth, unhesitating, direct and definitive' — 
on one occasion, Yes, on the others, No. (d) 'Solution precedes exe- 
cution of solution' — yes and no. (e) 'Solution retained after a single 
performance' — definitely No. (f) Novelty—yes. 

Kohler's own comments on this experiment are revealing. Although 
in The Mentality of Apes he stresses that the gulf between Trial-and- 
Error and Insight is unbridgeable ('the contrast is absolute' 10 ), his 
comment on Koko's initial hesitations and rumblings with the box is: 
'there is only one expression that really fits his behaviour at that 
juncture: it's beginning to dawn on him!' u Let us note that for about 
ten days after that first success, Koko kept manipulating the box, 
sometimes aimlessly, sometimes angrily, and during this whole 
period 'no trace of a solution appeared, except an equivalent of the 
words: "there's something about that box".' 12 In another passage 
Kohler says (italics Kohler's): 'It may happen that the animal will 
attempt a solution which, while it may not result in success, yet has 
some meaning in regard to the situation. "Trying around" then 
consists in attempts at solution in the half-understood situation.* 13 



Preconditions of Insight 

No more need be said to prove that if we apply the descriptive criteria 
which I have ennumerated, we find a graded series from 'trying 
around', through the 'dawning' of the solution, to the limit case of 
the sudden solution. But limit cases at the end of a graded series do 
not require a separate set of postulates to explain them. The break in 
actual behaviour, the discrete and unitary character of the solution in 
these cases can be explained in terms which are also applicable to other 



58o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



forms of learning. Thus with regard to criterion (a) we can say that 
the suddenness of the solution is due to the trigger action of chance in 
a situation which was ripe for solution — that is to say, where the 
animal's repertory comprises all the requisite single skills, and where 
all that is needed is a link to combine them into a complex skill — e.g. 
Sultan accidentally pushing one rod into the opening of the other. In 
other cases — Sultan turning round to pick up the, remembered stick 
— where chance plays no part, memory provides the link; but memory 
enters into all forms of learning. Regarding (c) and (d) (smooth, 
unitary execution of the act, indicating that it has been thought out 
before being acted out), we may say that the animal has formed a 
hypothesis, or carried out an implicit try, followed by explicit per- 
formances of the act. Rats, cats, and dogs also show this brief suspension 
of activity, this 'attitude of concentrated attention' 14 before they act 
out a hypothesis — which may or may not be the correct one. (e) 
Retention after a single performance can be interpreted as 'induction 
based on a single case* — as the chick, from a single experience, draws 
the correct empirical inference that all cinnabar caterpillars are to be 
avoided. Lasdy, (f), novelty is of course also achieved when the cat 
learns the open-sesame trick in the puzzle-box. To argue that the cat's 
novel response was acquired by Trial and Error, the chimp's by 
Insight, is to argue in a circle, since novelty itself is supposed to serve 
as a differential criterion. 

Thus Sultan's Eureka processes, once we have got rid of thinking in 
S.~R. schemata, are interpretable in terms of the same theory which 
covers all lower forms of learning. They make a spectacular impression, 
because (since the separate skills which had to be integrated into the 
new skill were well-exercised items in his repertory of habits), the 
problem to be solved was just one step beyond the limits of that 
repertory, and all was set for a single spark to trigger off the 
fusion. 

At the opposite end of the learning scale, the dog in Pavlov's 
laboratory is not equipped with pre-existent rules of the game which 
could be combined with each other; it must construct a new code of rules, 
starting more or less from scratch. Therein lies the main difference. 
The dog must start with an agonized reappraisal of which environ- 
mental events are relevant and which are not; then extract and codify 
the recurrent invariant features from the stimuli promoted to signi- 
ficance; then discriminate between finer features within those features. 
The rat must piece together, bit by bit, his cognitive map of the maze; 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



581 



the cat must gradually extract, by empirical induction, the rules of 
Thorndike's game from a surrealistic universe. 

The 'missing link' in between the cat and Sultan is provided by 
Koko. He does not have to start from scratch; he has already played 
with the box; he has sat on it and pushed it about. Was his first success- 
ful solution of the problem a random try? Certainly not. It had all the 
'dramatic suddenness, smoothness, directness and definiteness , that one 
can wish for. It was more than a provisional try', rather like a hypo- 
thesis which carried implicit conviction; yet on the other hand, it had 
been preceded by hesitant action along the correct lines which was 
abandoned; and it was succeeded by forgetting all but a fragment of 
the successful solution— the fragment 'there is something about that 
box'. 

The reason for this paradoxical behaviour is evident. Koko had to 
combine two skills; the reachmg-jumpmg-climbing skill M 1} and dis- 
placing the box to serve as a platform, M 2 . But M 2 is not part of the 
chimp's habit-repertory; in all Kohler's experiments with manipu- 
lating boxes and putting them on top of each other, his chimps proved 
surprisingly stupid.* Thus the skill of manipulating boxes is not a well- 
exercised, 'ready-made* item in Koko's repertory; and Koko is not 
really ripe for the task set for him, because M 2 is still too tentative and 
unstable to become firmly attached to M x ; linking did occur in a lucky 
moment, but the link broke again. This description presupposes that 
the box-manipulating skill was developing independently from banana- 
collecting, as a purely playful occupation — as it did in fact when 
Koko was made to play with the box before the experiment started. 
And it further presupposes that if Koko had been given sufficient time 
to become proficient in that playful skill, then he would have become 
ripe for a true bisociative act. Instead of this, however, he was led to 
form a 'premature linkage* between boxes and bananas (cf. Book 
One, IX). 

This interpretation differs from K5hler's appearance of a complete 
solution with reference to the whole layout of the field*; or rather, it 
specifies the condition under which such a 'complete solution has a 
chance to occur. But our interpretation is borne out by later experiments 
by others, in which chimpanzees were given the same raking task as 
set by Kohler. One cHmpanzee out of six had previously used sticks 
in play; this animal was the only one which had the 'insight* to rake in 
the food placed outside the cage; the other five failed, although the 
stick was lying in plain view. For the next three days all six chimps 



582 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



were given sticks to play with. They used the sticks, as usual, to push 
and poke, but never as a rake. Then the experiment was repeated— and 
all six sticks turned into rakes instantly. 15 Experiments with dogs reared 
in isolation and then set 'insight situation tasks, gave similar results. 16 
It may seem pedantic to lay so much stress on the independent 
primary development of skills which are later combined in the 
'moment of truth*. But the point does become relevant on higher 
levels. The experimental sciences of electricity and magnetism de- 
veloped independendy, and the discovery of electro-magnetic in- 
duction was a truly bisociative act; in comparison to it the subsequent 
improvements of electromagnets were a pedestrian procedure. The 
previous independence of the cognitive structures which are made to 
fuse in the creative act is, as we saw before, one of the criteria of 
originality; I shall return to the subject in the final chapter. 

The Ambiguities of Gestalt 

The Gestalt theory was developed in Germany, before Wertheimer, 
Kohler, and KofTka settled in America; and the original German term 
for insight was 'Einsicht'. In a footnote on page 291 of the English 
translation of The Mentality of Apes we read (my italics) : 'The German 
word" Einsicht" is rendered by both "intelligence" and "insight" through- 
out this book. The lack of an adjective derived from the noun "in- 
sight", apart from other considerations, makes this procedure neces- 
sary.' 

In this casual footnote we find the clue to the sad confusion which 
has bedevilled the controversy from its beginning: Gestalt theorists 
used the word 'insight' mdiscriminately to mean either (A) intelli- 
gence, understanding, judgement, knowledge in general, or (B) 
specifically the acquisition of new understanding and knowledge 
under the sudden and dramatic circumstances specified in the previous 
section. By equating (A) with (B), the Gestaltists were led to regard 
(B) as the only type of 'intelligent' learning, eveiything else as 'blind' 
learning; and their explanations of why and how learning of type (B) 
occurs become unavoidably tautological Thus K5hler writes: 

We can, in our own experience, distinguish sharply between the 
kind of behaviour which from the very beginning arises out of a 
consideration of the structure of a situation, and one that does not. 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



583 



Only in the former case do we speak of insight, and only that 
behaviour of animals definitely appears to us intelligent which takes 
account from the beginning of the lay of the land, and proceeds to 
deal with it in a single, continuous, and definite course. Hence 
follows this criterion of insight: the appearance of a complete solution 
with reference to the whole layout of the field. 17 (Kohler's italics). 

But a few pages further we read: ' "trying around" consists in 
attempts at solution in the half-understood situation; and the real solu- 
tion may easily arise by some chance outcome of it, i.e. it will not arise 
from chance impulses, but from actions, which, because they are 
"au fond" sensible, are great aids to chance'. 18 Kohler further speaks 
of the 'dawning' of the solution and of good errors'— that is, tries in 
the right direction vaguely sensed. Thus Kohler admits that insight 
in the sense (B) is a matter of approximation, and may be achieved 
in several steps, consisting of more or less 'sensible' hypotheses and 
tries; yet in other passages he asserted the exact opposite, namely that 
the criterion of insight was 'the appearance of a complete solution . . . 
in a single continuous and definite course'. 

To get out of this confusion, let me distinguish between two 
problems; firstly, what constitutes understanding or Insight A; and in 
the second place, how new understanding or Insight B is acquired. 
Regarding the second problem, we have seen that the dramatic 
Eureka process is not the rule, but rather an exceptional limit case; 
and that understanding or Insight A enters to varying degrees into all 
forms of learning. 

Let us examine for a moment the Gestalt school's answer to the 
first problem: the nature of understanding or Insight A. On page 219 
of The Mentality of Apes we read that it is based 'on the grasp of a 
material, inner relation of two things to each other . . .'; 'relation' 
being further defined as an 'interconnection based on the properties 
of these things themselves, not a "frequent following each other" or 
"occurring together" \ The meaning of these formulations becomes 
clearer in Kohler's later book (1949). There this 'material' 'inner' 
relation between two things is expressed as 'our feeling of something 
naturally depending on something else'. 19 'Between the attitude and 
its sensory basis we experience what in German is called ihr sachlicker 
Zusammenhang . . .'; and sachlicher Zusamtnenhang is translated, with 
some hesitation, as 'intrinsic connection'. This again is used synony- 
mously with 'experienced determination' such as that prevailing 



584. THE ACT OF CREATION 

'between a disease and its germ'. 20 Again: 'Here not only the result is 
experienced, but also very much of its "why" and "how" is felt in 
just the actual context. Wherever this is the case we apply the term 
insight* But 'very much' is a relative term, and its use as an all-or-none 
criterion — 'wherever this is the case* — again confuses the issue. Turn- 
ing to KofFka, we fmd that he explains the difficulties confronting the 
cat in the problem-box by the fact that the actions which it must per- 
form to gain release are to the cat 'objectively meaningless', that they 
have 'no sort of internal connection with release', that they have no 
'material relation* or 'intrinsic relation' with the opening of doors, 
and so on. 

It should be clear by now that all these somewhat obscure terms 
are shamefaced references to physical causality, and that the position of 
the Gestalt school boils down to the tautology that the animal's be- 
haviour is the more intelligent the more insight it has into causal 
relations. Nobody will quarrel with this statement; but it entirely 
begs the central question of learning theory: namely, by what pro- 
cesses and methods that insight into causal relations is acquired. The 
loop in the puzzle-box, at the beginning of its training, means nothing 
to the cat; at the end of its training it means escape. How is this mean- 
ing acquired? Through trial-and-error learning, hypotheses, etc. The 
problem can now be re-formulated as follows: can learning by trial 
and error result in 'genuine' solutions, can it provide a correct, or true, 
or meaningful representation of the causal connection between loop 
and door? We can even go one step further and ask the same question 
with regard to classical conditioning. If the dog could express itself 
in Kdhier's terminology, it would no doubt answer that the sound 
of the gong 'signals' or 'means' food, that an 'objectively meaningful 
connection', an 'mtrinsic connection* or sachlicher Zusammenhang, 
exists between the two. And this statement would entirely correspond 
to fact, because in the laboratory universe this sequence is natural law. 
Of course some connecting links are missing in the dog's inner model 
of that law: the intentions of God Pavlov who has decreed it are un- 
known to the dog. But such gaps occur on all levels of cognitive pro- 
cesses. When the average citizen turns on his radio he has about as 
much insight into the 'intrinsic connections* between the knob and 
the sound, the 'whys' and 'hows', the 'interconnections based on the 
properties of the things themselves', the 'total layout of the field' as 
Pavlov's dogs have. 

Understanding is a matter of approximation. If we hold, with 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



585 



Craik, that the basic achievement of the nervous system is derived 
from its power to parallel or model external events, 21 then the cat 
which has learned to open the door by tugging at the loop can be 
said to have made a correct, if crude, model of a causal sequence. The 
crudeness of the model is mainly due to the fact that the rope connec- 
ting the loop and the door is hidden from the cat's sight — whereas 
under normal conditions the cat can 'see what it is doing*. But this 
difference is one of degree not of kind; and it is not justifiable to argue 
— as Gestalt theorists have occasionally done — that because the cat 
cannot see the connection, it has no 'insight'. Because sight is our main 
sense organ, we have come to use the words 'I see' as synonymous 
with 'I understand'. The Gestalt school with its strong emphasis on 
visual perception has carried this tendency to extremes, and thus came 
to believe that to have all relevant facts of a situation or problem laid 
out before one's eyes is both necessary and sufficient for its under- 
standing. 22 In fact, of course, it is neither. Rats learn to know a maze, 
and to form a mental map of it — which amounts to as complete an 
understanding of the situation as one could wish for — without having 
been offered a bird's eye view of it. Nor is seeing a sufficient condition 
for knowing in chimpanzees or humans, even if the 'whole field' 
containing all the necessary clues is laid out in full view. Thus Sultan 
establishes a visual connection with the banana outside the cage by 
pushing one stick towards it with a second stick, but that procedure 
does not testify to much insight. In other experiments, where a string 
is attached to the banana and one or more strings are laid out in the 
vicinity, Sultan will pull at random at any of the strings, although 
he can clearly see which string is connected to the banana, which is 
not.* The young child behaves in similar ways; Piaget has called this 
phenomenon 'optical realism'. It 'consists in considering things as 
being what they appear to be in immediate perception and not what 
they will become once they have been inserted in a system of rational 
relations transcending the visual field. Thus the child imagines that 
a stick can draw an object because it is beside it or touches it, as though 
optical contact were equivalent to a causal link.' 23 

Adults are also quite often unable to understand how a simple 
mechanism works although it is laid bare before their eyes. The visual 
concurrence of all elements which belong to the problem facilitates 
understanding (in various degrees according to species, see previous 
note), but does not guarantee or imply it; it does not provide a 
'direct and complete' insight into the causal connections of the situation, 



586 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



nor, except in certain cases, does it occasion a 'complete answer accor- 
ding to the total layout of the field'. Even in relatively simple situa- 
tions there are always gaps in understanding the 'intrinsic material 
relations' between things. Why can I pull but not push an object with 
a string? What are the whys and hows of rigidity, flexibility, cohesion, 
etc.? Why is a hemp-cord stronger than a paper-cord, and less elastic 
than a rubber-cord? Our insight into the 'inner material relation of 
phenomena' is full of missing links, so to speak; the model of the out- 
side world which we form in the matrix of our minds represents, by 
the very nature of that matrix, not a point-to-point correspondence 
but a point-to-blur correspondence, a more or less rough approxima- 
tion. Not only this blurred microstructure, but even the macro- 
structure of the universe, and the laws which govern it, put us into 
much the same perplexed condition as the cat which has to infer, by 
empirical induction, the laws which Thorndike made in his wisdom. 
And the cat's behaviour in the box is, in fact, a first approximation 
to the methodology of exact science as formulated by Craik: 'in- 
duction supported by experiments to test hypotheses'. 24 

It is necessary to remind ourselves of these truisms, because the 
controversies in learning theory have almost made us lose them from 
sight. The extreme wing of the Behaviourists has tried to banish the 
concepts of understanding, memory, purpose, consciousness, hypo- 
thesis, from the groves of Academe, to interpret trial and error as a 
random process, and human induction as an equally mechanical affair. 
Classical Gestalt theory sinned in the opposite direction; its attitude is 
epitomized, e.g. in the passages from Kohler already quoted: accord- 
ing to which true understanding can be derived only from 'an inter- 
connection based on the properties of the things themselves, not a 
"frequent following each other" or "occurring together'V To pay 
attention to the 'frequent following each other' or 'occurring together' 
of two events, which is so contemptuously dismissed here,, is the very 
essence of inductive inference. To quote Russell again: 'Let there be 
two kinds of events, (a) and (b) (e.g. Hghtning and thunder), and let 
many instances be known in which an event of the kind (a) has been 
quickly followed by one of the kind (b), and no instances of the 
contrary. Then either a sufficient number of instances of this sequence, 
or instances of suitable kinds, will make it increasingly probable that 
(a) is always followed by (b), and in times the probability can be 
made to approach certainty without limit. . . ,' 25 Instances of a very 
suitable, clear-cut kind — that is to say, situations for which the animal 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



587 



is 'ripe', may then lead to inductive certainty derived from a single 
occurrence — the chick inferring that all caterpillars of appearance (a) 
are accompanied by a disgusting taste (b). 

The mistake of the classical Gestalt school was to identify triat-and- 
erroT learning with chain-reflex theory — a historically understandable 
mistake since the two were lumped together in the S.-R. schemata of 
Thorndike, Pavlov, Watson, Guthrie, etc. Yet the history of science 
abounds with examples of brilliant discoveries which were preceded 
by long periods of more or less fumbling tries in half-understood 
situations. To try is to adventure; and to quote Russell once more: 
'If an induction is worth making, it may be wrong/ 26 

The same kind of bias led to the Gestalt school's uncompromising 
rejection of any assocktionist theory of learning. Again this radical 
attitude is historically understandable as a reaction against mechanistic 
interpretations of associations as rigid neural connections, fixed path- 
ways, conditioned reflex arcs and the rest. But the Gestalt school did 
not succeed in offering any valid alternative of its own for associative 
memory. Kohler's trace theory, elaborated by KofFka, does not give 
even a remote clue as to how a visual percept — say a caricature of 
Nelson, which is 'pictured' by an electrolytic field-current in the op- 
tical cortex — will activate, 'by similarity' the auditory trace of the word 
'Trafalgar'. The influence of past experience on the present is mini- 
mized by Kohler wherever possible, and learning is virtually reduced 
to spontaneous 'Insight B\ where new knowledge emerges all in a 
piece like Minerva in full armour from Jupiter's head. 

According to Kohler, association has to be given up as a special 
and independent theoretical concept. It is not more than a name for the 
fact that organized processes leave a trace picturing their organiza- 
tion and that in consequence of it reproductions are possible. . . . 
Our conclusion is, that association depends upon organization because 
association is just an after-effect of an organized process/ 27 'Organiza- 
tion' in this context means perceptual orgariization-— that is to say, the 
animal's innate faculty to order its perceptions into Gestalt-configura- 
tions which arise spontaneously as the 'experienced direct determina- 
tion' of 'objectively meaningful mtrinsic connections' based on the 
'whys and hows of the interaction of the properties of the things them- 
selves' — and so on. Gestalt has become the ultimate panacea. As one 
critic remarked: 'The Gestalten thus become primary realities, existen- 
tial intimates, in terms of which all events should be comprehended/ 28 

As so frequently in the history of science, a school of outstanding 



588 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



achievements has succumbed to the magic power of a unifying formula. 
That formula, in its turn, is based on a metaphysical assumption: the 
existence of an a priori correspondence, or co-ordination, between the 
physico-chemical processes in the nervous system and the events in 
the outside world. Owing to Kohler's theory of psycho-physical 
isomorphism', the sight of a square gives rise to a field current in the 
cortex, and 'this cortical process must have the structural characteristics 
of the square.' 29 The 'intrinsic', 'material', or causal relations in the 
outer world are automatically mirrored by isomorph electro-chemical 
Gestalt processes in the brain, and 'insight* turns out to mean the spon- 
taneous operation of the isomorph faculty. Thus the organism does not 
have to build a symbolic model of reality in the nervous system by the 
processes of learning — such as scanning, coding, abstraction, gradual 
approximation through inductive hypotheses; the isomorph model 
in the head is pre-figured, potentially given in its native perceptual 
organization, and need only be activated by 'spontaneous insight'. To 
quote Polanyi: 'From this principle (isomorphism) it would follow 
that the whole of mathematics — whether known or yet to be dis- 
covered — is latent in the neural traces arising in a man's brain when he 
looks at the axioms of Principia Mathematical and that the physico- 
chemical equilibration of these traces should be capable of producing 
a cerebral counterpart (a coded script) comprising the entire body of 
mathematics.' 30 

Thus the metaphysical assumptions of Gestalt psychology lead us 
(as Koffka somewhat reluctantly admits) 31 back to the kind of 'faculty 
psychology' abandoned about a century ago; and ultimately to Plato; 
whereas Behaviourism leads us ultimately back to the atomism of 
Democritus combined with the scepticism of Ecclesiastes. Kohler's 
chimps look at the world through the 'eyes of the soul'; Hull's rats 
are wired marionettes jerked about by a non-existent puppet player. 

Putting Two and Two Together 

Contiguity is the Deus ex machina of Behaviourists such as "Watson and 
Guthrie, and the bete, noire of Gestaltists, who reject association by 
contiguity as 'blind* and 'meaningless'. 

'There is not a single example', writes Kohler, 'of an effect pro- 
duced by the interaction of two things or processes quite independently 
of their properties. Nevertheless this is the character of the classical 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 



589 



law of association as we find it stated in most textbooks.' 32 I cannot 
remember having seen anywhere the law stated in quite that form, and 
Kohler s description is obviously a caricature; how can two things 
interact 'independently of their properties'? Does not the term 'inter- 
action imply that properties of the interacting processes are involved? 
Contiguity — the overlapping of two events in spacetime — of a regular, 
recurrent kind is the base on which inductive inference can build. This 
applies, impartially, to the dog learning that the gong is a signal for 
food, and to Kepler observing that the tides follow the moon. Kepler 
concluded that there must be a causal connection between the moon 
and the tides, although his ideas of gravity were of the most erratic 
kind; and his was a correct approximation, followed by the closer 
approximations of Newton and Einstein — though we are perhaps as 
far as ever from grasping the intrinsic, material relations' between 
bodies acting at a distance. More often than not, the starting point of 
the scientist's inquiry is 'post hoc, ergo— let's hope— -propter hoc. Even 
in the rare limit case of the Eureka process, contiguity — the simul- 
taneous activity in the mind of the two matrices which are to 
be integrated — provides the link; and the provider may even be 
'blind chance' — a fungus sailing through the window into Fleming's 
laboratory. 

Learning, then, in the most general sense of the word, consists in 
putting two and two or A and B together. It may be done gradually, 
by plodding through hypotheses and eliminations; or all of a sudden, 
following upon a single implicit try. A and B may stand for recurrent 
features abstracted from a series of perceived events; or A may be a 
signal-pattern requiring the correct choice of reaction B among other 
possible choices; A and B may be codes of behaviour or universes of 
discourse, each complete in itself and adequate for routine tasks; but 
to solve a certain new task they must be put together. If the subject is 
ripe for the solution, the putting together can occur in a single flash. 
But let me repeat that such hghtning inductions based on a single case 
are possible only if both M x and M 2 are well-established, flexible 
matrices which the subject knows 'inside out'. Only those chimpanzees 
discovered spontaneously the use of a stick as a rake who had previously 
played with sticks; those who had not, though of equal intelligence, 
failed to see the light. 

There is a rather striking parallel between the present interpretation 
of discovery as a bisociative process, and the conclusions which Hebb 
reached regarding the sudden appearance of new insights:* 



590 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



The sudden activation of an effective link between two concepts 
or percepts, at first unrelated, is a simple case of 'insight' . . . 88 

Insight, as a sudden perception of new relationships, can result 
from the simultaneous activity of two conceptual cycles in adult 
learning. 34 

The insightful act is an excellent example of something that is not 
learned, but still depends on learning. It is not learned, since it can be 
adequately performed on its first occurrence; it is not perfected 
through practice in the first place, but appears all at once in recog- 
nizable form (further practice, however, may still improve it). On 
the other hand, the situation must not be completely strange; the 
animal must have had prior experience with the component parts of 
the situation, or with other situations that have some similarity to 
it. ... All our evidence thus points to the conclusion that a new 
insight consists of a recombination of pre-existent mediating processes, 
not the sudden appearance of a wholly new process. [Hebb's italics] 

Such recombinations must be frequent in man's everyday living, 
and in a theoretical framework we must consider them to be original 
and creative. . . .** 

Hilgard (1958) came to similar conclusions: 'Because all learning is 
to some extent cognitively controlled, the distinction between blind 
learning and learning with understanding becomes one of degree.' 36 

NOTES 

To p. $8t. Kohler made a distinction between one-box experiments and 
the building of two- or three-storey structures. In the latter additional difificulties 
arise from what he called the chimp's *lack of a feeling for statics'. This handi- 
cap no doubt adds to the animal's perplexity; but Koko's and Sultan's behaviour 
in experiments of this kind (c£ pp. 47, 118, 122 ff) indicates that not only the 
problem of balance, but the whole box-building business goes against the 
chimpanzee's grain. 

To p. 585. The importance of visual clues varies of course with different 
species. Adams' cat immediately saw that the piece of liver can be hauled up by 
the string to which it was attached. Kohler tried a similar experiment with his 
dog: a basket, containing food, was suspended from a rope outside the barred 
window of the room so that the dog could easily have hoisted it up with herteeth 
or paws. But she 'did not even attempt this simple method of self-help, and paid 
no attention to the string which was lying just under her nose— whilst at the same 
time she showed the liveliest interest in the distant basket. Dogs, and probably, 
for instance, horses as well . . . might easily starve to death in these circum- 
stances which offer hardly any difficulty to human beings — or to chimpanzees' 



THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 591 

(Kohler, 1957, p. 31). Far be it from me to suggest that cats are more intelligent 
than dogs; what the experiment shows is that cats are phylogenetically more 
ripe for this type of perceptual and manipulative skill than dogs. 

To p. S8g. Hebb's Organization of Behaviour was published in the same year 
as Insight and Outlook; his A Textbook of Psychology in 1958. 



XIV 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 

Intending and Saying 

Preparing to say something, whether it is a single sentence or a 
public lecture, is to set a hierarchy in motion. 
*. . . And has the reader never asked himself*, 'WiDia.m James wrote 
in 1890, 'what kind of a mental fact is his intention of saying a thing before 
he has said it? It is an entirely definite intention, distinct from all other 
intentions, an absolutely distinct state of consciousness, therefore; and 
yet how much of it consists of definite sensorial images, either of words 
or of things? Hardly anything! Linger, and the words and things 
come into the mind; the anticipatory intention, the divination is there 
no more . . . [The intention] has therefore a nature of its own of the 
most positive sort, and yet what can we say about it without using 
words that belong to the later mental facts that replace it? The intention 
to say so and so is the only name it can receive. One may admit that a 
good third of our psychic life consists in these rapid premonitory per- 
spective views of schemes of thought not yet articulate.* 1 

In other words, before the verbal hierarchy is set into motion, 
there is an ideational process of a highly conscious character, an inten- 
tion or active expectation, which itself is not yet verbalized. Consider 
what is involved in preparing an ex-tempore lecture. The first step is 
to jot down the principal arguments or themes in key-words — in 
'symbols of the second remove' so to speak. Each theme is then treated 
as a sub-whole, a flexible matrix of ideas with an invariant code: the 
logic of the argument to be conveyed. But the ways of putting it 
across are many: factually, whimsically, by concrete examples. My 
strategical choice is governed by the lie of the land: the character of 
the audience; and by feedback from implicit tries: their anticipated 
reactions. If I have decided on concrete examples, I must search for 

592 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



593 



them in my memory, and then again make strategical choices. The 
next question is where to start, to decide on the sequential order, and 
the approximate time allotted to each of the various subjects so as to 
make a balanced whole. In this quasi-architectural planning, the argu- 
ments are still treated as sub-wholes or building blocks, whose 'con- 
tents are known but are present without adequate verbal designation\ 2 
All this is still a long way from the choice of actual words; in fact the 
hazy intentional situation described by James repeats itself on several 
levels. 

But as we approach the actual formation of sentences, automatisms 
begin to intrude, indicating that we are nearing the bottom of the 
hierarchy — the consummatory acts of language which terminate the 
appetitive behaviour of thought. The sub-codes of grammar and 
syntax, which now enter into action, are almost wholly automatized; 
and when we finally arrive at the formation of syntactic units — indi- 
vidual words patterned into phrases — there is a good chance that these 
will be 'fixed action-patterns* — verbal formulae, cliches, mannerisms, 
stereotyped turns of phrase, which remind one of the fighting rituals 
of the stickleback (e.g. 'the evidence tends to show*, 'as we have seen 
before', 'we must bear in mind, however*, etc.). Technical papers and 
bureaucratic utterances are conspicuous by their narrowness of vocabu- 
lary and rigidity of phrasing. Fortunately, there exist non-abstractive 
hierarchies whose criteria of relevance are aesthetic or emotional, 
which cc^letermine the tactics of verbal choices and counteract the 
tendency towards automatization. 

Having gone through all these implicit motions, we end up by 
spelling out the actual sounds or ink marks, vocal patterns or type- 
written letters. Yet even on this automatized level, hierarchic organiza- 
tion prevails; the phonetic sequences or manual patterns are triggered 
off as wholes and perceived as wholes; nowhere, in the course of our 
descent through the hierarchy, do we strike rock-bottom, made of 
hard 'atoms of behaviour*. 

Thus 'verbal behaviour* is initiated by unverbalized intentions at 
the top of the language hierarchy, and terminates, in deverbalized 
sensory-motor activities; at each level it is governed by rules which 
elude verbal definition, and modified by extraneous factors acting on 
the plastic matrices of language. Each time we slice behaviour 'ver- 
tically* — instead of horizontally on a single level — we arrive at a series 
which at the top recedes into an elusive blur and at its base vanishes in 
the twilight of awareness. 



594 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



The above description may have seemed unnecessarily verbose, 
since the hierarchic structure of language is so obvious that it need 
not be stressed. After all, nearly half a century has passed since Watson 
proclaimed that speech consists in the manipulation of words, and 
thinking in the sub-vocal manipulation of words. However, if the 
reader thinks that the cruder forms of Paleo-Behaviourism are a 
matter of the past, he should turn to the first Note* at the end of this 
chapter (which will also provide some light relief ). It is an excerpt from 
a textbook for College students, published in 1961, which starts with 
the sentence: 'For many of you, this is your first encounter with psy- 
chology as a science.' One wonders what this £.rst encounter will do 
to the mind of the trusting student who is here quite literally led to 
believe that human discourse consists in the chaining of S.-R. units 
which are best studied by bar-pressing experiments 'under the more 
ideal conditions in the laboratory'. 



The Dawn of Symbol Consciousness 

The previous section referred to speech as a performance. Learning to 
speak proceeds more or less in the opposite direction — from the 
bottom to the top of the hierarchy. But only 'more or less', because 
bit-learning plays here a much lesser part than in the acquisition of 
mechanical skills like typing. Let us take a closer look at a few charac- 
teristic aspects of the process. 

The first vocal ventures of the child confirm the now-familiar 
principle (cf. Chapter II) that spontaneous motor activity precedes 
sensory control. The child, too, 'acts on the environment before it 
reacts to it* — as parents must learn in sleepless nights; cooing and 
babbling are spontaneous expressions of joie de vivre, in which a sur- 
plus of energy is discharged, as in the waving of arms and wriggling of 
toes. 

At the early stages these spontaneous babbling sounds are the same 
whether they are produced by an American white or a Negro baby 
(i.e. the frequency spectra of the phonemes are practically identical). 3 
At five to six months, however, when syllabic, speech-like sounds 
become increasingly frequent, the spectrum shifts noticeably towards 
the sound patterns produced by the adults in the child's environment; 
and at twenty-four months the resemblance is close. Thus the originally 
^distinguishable phonetic matrices of infants from different language- 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



595 



groups become differentiated by the imitative repetition of adult 
sound-patterns. Imitation is at first probably automatic, the auditory- 
vocal feedback apparatus being excited by the input as in the young 
singing bird; then shades into a more or less conscious response — 
from 'echolalia' to 'metalalia'. 

The first correlations between a sound pattern and an object or 
person are probably 'stamped in* by the parents at an age when the 
child's nervous system is not yet mature for them. In Book One (pp. 
220-3) I have mentioned two examples at opposite extremes: Watson 
conditioning an infant less than six months old — Le. much too early — 
to say da each time it was given the bottle; and Helen Keller's sudden 
and dramatic discovery, at the age of seven — i.e. when she was over- 
ripe for it — that 'everything had a name and each name gave birth to 
a new thought'. In the average, normal child the dawn of symbol 
consciousness seems to be a gradual, cumulative process. From 
approximately the eighteenth month onward there is a sharp increase in 
the child's vocabulary (Book One, p. 221) and somewhere around that 
time it makes that 'most important discovery of its life*, that verbal 
labels can be attached not only to particular things and events, but 
that everything under the sun has a name. The universe of words, and 
the universe of things, have become integrated and will remain in- 
separable. Henceforth, every word must mean something and every- 
thing must have a name. 

With the emergence of language, we have attained a new level of 
the cognitive hierarchy, which represents a sharp break in the con- 
tinuity of learning processes in animals and man. Homologue laws 
still operate: 'All things have names' may be regarded as yet another 
case of empirical induction which we have seen operating on all levels; 
and verbal symbolism may be regarded as an extension of sign situa- 
tions. Dolphins can be taught to respond to verbal or visual commands; 
dogs and chimps can make their wishes be known to their masters; 
cats will learn that bolts and loops mean escape; bees can communicate 
their experiences by dancing. But such communication by signs ex- 
tends only to a few particular situations; it is generalized to some extent 
in the laboratory situation, when it seems to dawn on the cat that 'all 
these contraptions are means of escape', as it dawns on the child that 
'all these words are means of getting one's way'. But at this point 
the cat has reached the limit of its abstractive capabilities, whereas the 
child has only got to its first inkling of what words can do for you.* 

Their first, obvious advantages to the child are that they can be 



596 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



utilized both as labels, and as levers which make things happen, that 
they serve both the progressive socialization and internalization of 
behaviour — communication and inner discourse. This is well-covered 
ground which needs no further labouring. But another phenomenon 
of early language behaviour is rarely emphasized: the appearance of 
the naming question or 'naming mania'. The child points at anything 
it sees, asks 'This—?' or 'What that?', and is visibly satisfied to learn 
the answer, without any utilitarian reward. Alternatively, it points at 
things, calls out their name or, if it has forgotten it, invents a new one. 
Here is a true paradigm of latent learning, of the exploratory drive, or 
oil* art pour I* art behaviour— whatever one wants to call it. To quote 
Piaget: 'It is ... no exaggeration to say that sensory-motor intelligence 
is limited to desiring success or practical adaptation, whereas the func- 
tion of verbal or conceptual thought is to know and state truth.' 4 

But there is another aspect to the 'name-expectation: henceforth 
the child's concept of a tiling or event will be experienced by it as 
incomplete if there is no verbal label attached to it. The concept will 
behave like a molecule with a free valency, as it were. "We can perhaps 
recapture an echo of this when we hunt for the forgotten name of a 
person. Also, when we learn a new language, we suddenly have a 
whole class of free valencies: we feel actually frustrated when we dis- 
cover that the French have no word for 'snobbery' or 'understate- 
ment', and are tempted to exclaim like a child: 'But surely they must 
have a name for it?' 

The behaviour of the rat exploring a maze or of the monkey fear- 
fully peeping into the box with the snake, could be described as inter- 
rogatory, and the same description could be applied to the puzzled 
expressions and actions of a small child before it has learned to speak. 
But its first explicit, verbal questions refer to the names of things, promp- 
ted by the need to 'saturate' the free valencies in its pre-verbal object- 
concepts. Is it too speculative to assume that this origin of the question- 
ing habit must influence the whole later development of thought? The 
fact that each naming question can be readily answered by adults, may 
implant the implicit belief into the child that all questions are both 
meaningful and answerable; that the nature of explanation is based on 
the same kind of simple and direct connections as that between 'thing' 
and 'name'. This implicit belief seems to have been one of the factors 
responsible for the aberrations of human thought. 



Concepts and Labels 



I have talked of (pre-verbal) 'concepts' to wtrich the verbal label 
becomes attached. The Concise Oxford Dictionary defines a concept 
as an 'idea of a class of objects; general notion; Webster as 'a mental 
image of a thing formed by generalization from particulars'; Hilgard: 
'When a symbol stands for a class of objects or events with common 
properties, we say that it refers to a concept 9 ; 5 Piaget 8 regards the de- 
velopment of 'object concepts' as one of the principal achievements 
of the 'sensory-motor intelligence' which precedes the rise of 
verbal intelligence in the child's first two years. He distinguishes six 
stages in the attainment of stable object-concepts, which he defines as 
'a system of perceptual images endowed with a constant spatial form 
throughout its sequential displacements and constituting an item which 
can be isolated in the causal series unfolding in time.' 7 It is interesting 
to compare Piaget's rather abstract formulations with the lucid 'in- 
cisiveness' of Wilder Penfield— a neuro-surgeon. He too starts by 
securing his flanks with quotes from Webster and Oxford; then he 
goes on: 

'The concept may be a butterfly. It may be a person he has known. 
It may be an animal, a city, a type of action, or a quality. Each concept 
calls for a name. These names are wanted for what may be a noun or a 
verb, an adjective or an adverb. Concepts of this type have been formed 
gradually over the years from childhood on. Each time a thing is seen 
or heard or experienced, the individual has a perception of it. A part of 
that perception comes from his own concommittant interpretation. 
Each successive perception forms and probably alters the permanent 
concept. And words are acquired gradually, also, and deposited some- 
how in the treasure-house of word memory — the corticothalamic 
speech mechanisms. Words are often acquired simultaneously with 
the concepts. ... A little boy may first see a butterfly fluttering from 
flower to flower in a meadow. Later he sees them on the wing or in 
pictures, many times. On each occasion he adds to his conception of 
butterfly. 

'It becomes a generalization from many particulars. He builds up a 
concept of a butterfly which he can remember and summon at will, 
although when he comes to manhood, perhaps, he can recollect none 
of the particular butterflies of past experience. 

'The same is true of the sequence of sound that makes up a melody. 
He remembers it after he has forgotten each of the many times he 

597 



598 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



heard or perhaps sang or played it. The same is true of colours. He 
acquires, quite quickly, the concept of lavender, although all the 
objects of which he saw the colour have faded beyond the frontier of 
voluntary recall. The same is true of the generalization he forms of an 
acquaintance. Later on he can summon his concept of the individual 
without recalling their many meetings/ 8 

Thus the pre-verbal concepts of the child are formed by a series of 
operations continuous with those described in previous chapters: the 
de-particularization, filtering, and coding of percepts according to 
those of their common features which are relevant to a given con- 
ceptual hierarchy; the formation of colour- shape- and object-con- 
stancies; the development of sensory-motor skills such as the grasping 
of objects, bringing them close to the eye, visual and tactile explora- 
tion, etc.; lasdy, according to Piaget's schema, the 'objectification of 
space and time, the gradual separation of the self from the non-self, and 
the beginnings of the transition from magical to more objectified 
kinds of implied causality. Most of these processes can be found, to a 
greater or lesser degree, in animal learning; but with the addition of a 
verbal label, the concept acquires a new dimension as it were, and the 
continuity of the series of learning processes in animal and man is 
broken. No extrapolation is possible from the behaviour of the rat to 
that of man. 

This can be demonstrated even in maze-learning experiments with 
humans, where the advantages of verbalization are not at once ob- 
vious. In a famous experiment by Warden 9 forty subjects were seated 
in front of a table with a grooved maze on it. The maze was of the 
same type as in rat experiments, with various cul-de-sacs; the subject 
had to thread his way through it with a stylus in his hand, by purely 
tactile guidance, for the maze was hidden from his view by a screen. 
The number of trials required until the maze was completely learned 
varied, according to subject, between 16 and 195 (!). At the end of the 
experiment each subject had to report whether he had memorized the 
maze by the 'feel' of it, that is by motor-kinesthetic imagery; or by 
making a 'visual map'; or by a verbal formula — e.g. 'first left, third 
right, first right', etc. 

The results were as follows: out of 60 subjects, 17 adopted the 
'motor* method. These needed an average of 124 trials (ranging from 
72 to 195 according to subject) to learn the maze. Eighteen adopted the 
'visual* method; average trials: 68, ranging from 41 to 104. Twenty- 
five adopted the Verbal' formula; average trials: 32, range: 16 to 62. 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



599 



Thus, in round figures, the visualizers learned twice as fast, the ver- 
balizers four times as fast as the motor learners. 

This reminds one of Otto Koehler's experiments (mentioned on 
p. 535 f.), which showed that clever jackdaws have a 'pre-linguistic 
number sense' almost equal to man's and are 'able to abstract the 
concept of numerical identity from groups of up to seven objects*; 
which 'suggests that many animals may have a prelinguistic "counting" 
ability of about the same degree, but that man's superiority in dealing 
with numbers lies in his ability to use, as symbols for numbers, words 
and figures'. 10 The dependence of counting and calculating abilities 
on verbal processes is further illustrated by Penfield's studies on 
aphasia, about which later. 

Even voluntary movements (as opposed to automatized skills) 
seem to be to some extent dependent on guidance by internal ver- 
balization. Some of Head's patients with speech disorders due to brain 
lesions were unable to imitate correctly Head's gestures — such as 
touching an eye or an ear with the left or right hand— while they 
were sitting face to face with Head; but had no difficulty in doing so 
if standing in front of a mirror with Head standing behind them. In 
the mirror test, of course, the task is reduced to pure imitation, whereas 
sitting opposite the experimenter 'left' and 'right' are reversed and the 
patient cannot see himself: V: 

'When the patient sitting opposite to me attempts to imitate move- 
ments of my right or left hand brought into contact with one or other 
eye or ear, internal verbalization occurs at a phase of the normal act. 
No word may be uttered, but the words "right" and "left", "eye "and 
"ear", are essential to correct imitation of this kind. For the same reason 
these patients may find considerable difficulty in carrying out the hand, 
eye, and ear tests when the command is pictorial (given by a drawing 
on a printed card) although they can execute them correctly when 
asked to do so by word of mouth (or even by printed command). 
Their difficulty is in evoking the words they require, and the verbal 
command supplies the necessary want.' 11 

Thus Head's patients, with their impaired command of words, 
were virtually reduced from the level of the verbalizers to that of the 
motor-learners in Wardens maze experiment. We must conclude that 
verbal symbolism enters even into the learning of complex motor 
skills— just as it provides the mortar for holding together complex 
visual pseudo-images (p. 53 1 rE). 



Ideation and Verbalization 



Owing to the immense benefits derived from verbalization, the verbal 
symbol, which at the dawn of symbol-consciousness was at first no 
more than a label attached to a pre-existing conceptual schema, soon 
becomes its focal member, its centre of gravity, as it were. As words 
are the most convenient and economical means not only of com- 
munication but also of internal discourse, they soon assume a central 
role in the child's mental life, whereas images and other forms 
of unverbalized thought are gradually pushed towards the peri- 
phery, the fringes of awareness, or sink slowly down below its 
surface. 

This tendency of verbal thinking to dominate and monopolize 
consciousness has its blessings and its curses, though the latter are less 
obvious than the former. Some of the dangers of thought becoming 
enslaved to words have been discussed in Book One, VII. Woodworth's 
remark, 'often we have to get away from speech in order to think 
clearly' 12 was seen to apply to a wide range of creative activities — 
from mathematics and physics to philosophy, and there is no need to 
labour the point further. What needs stressing once more is that words 
are symbols for perceptual and cognitive events, but they are not the 
events. J'hey are vehicles of thought, but the vehicle should not be 
confused with the passengers. 

Let me recapitulate, (i) The child has formed a variety of pre-verbal 
concepts of persons, objects, and recurrent events to which later verbal 
symbols become attached as labels; without the previously existing 
person-concept, the symbol 'Mama* would have nothing to refer to; 
it would remain meaningless — an empty vehicle without passenger. 
(2) At a later stage, the word and the concept may be acquired simul- 
taneously: 'Mummy, what does seductress mean?' 'A very bad 
woman who uses too much make-up.' (3) The concept 'seductress' will 
undergo drastic changes during adolescence and later years; the word 
seductress remains unchanged. It is a vehicle with a fixed, im- 
mutable structure; whereas the passengers are constantly changing, 
getting in and out of the bus. We may even distinguish between 
passengers of first and second class: trim denotations, furtive connota- 
tions, and stow-aways hidden under the seats. Dr. Watsons sugges- 
tion that the passengers themselves are subliminal omnibuses was not 
a helpful one. (4) The word seductress refers to different con- 
cepts in different people. (5) The word which is attached to a concept 

600 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



60 1 



may become detached from it, leaving the concept more or less un- 
impaired. This last point needs elaboration. 

One may of course forget the name of a person without forgetting 
the person, i.e. without losing one's concept of him or her. But does 
the same apply when the word refers to an abstract concept? 

A certain class of Head's aphasic patients confused the names of 
numbers, but nevertheless carried out the correct numerical operations. 
The patient would call a card 'nine of hearts' when he meant 'seven of 
hearts', and yet play a correct game. On doing a multiplication he 
would say aloud 'seven nines are fifty-six' and yet write down '63' 
correctly. This shows that his number-concepts remained intact, 
although he attached the wrong verbal labels to them; he probably 
catalogued them by their visual labels (the written figures), but this 
did not impair the efficiency of his symbolic operations. The trouble 
of the jackdaw is not that it cannot attach verbal symbols to its number- 
concepts, but that it cannot symbolize them in any other way either. 
One has only to think of deaf-mutes to remind one that a symbolic 
language is not necessarily an auditory-vocal language.* 

The clinical phenomena of aphasia are frequently open to more than 
one interpretation; but on the particular point under discussion this 
is not the case. After surveying the literature on the subject, Humphrey 13 
concluded: 'the general argument from aphasia for the independence 
of thought and language seems, on reading the evidence, overwhelm- 
ingly strong'. ('Independence' manifested in pathological cases does 
not, of course, prevent interaction under normal conditions.) 

More recently, Penfield and Roberts, reviewing the literature and 
their own case histories, came to the same conclusion: 'It is obvious 
that in many cases the aphasic patient is able to perceive accurately. 
He knows what an object is used for; he recognizes it. He must, there- 
fore, be able to draw upon his store of recorded experience. He is still 
able to record his new experience of things heard and seen, and to 
compare the new experience with the whole of his past similar ex- 
periences. Thus his capacity to perceive through other channels than 
the sound and form of words is preserved.' 14 

Particularly impressive is the evidence from temporary aphasia in- 
duced by electrical stimulation of the cortical speech areas of the con- 
scious and consenting patient. Penfield's usual method was to show the 
patient an object printed on a card and ask him to name it, while the 
low-voltage electrode was applied to various points of the cortex: 
'The patient may remain silent, or he may use words to explain that 



602 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



he cannot name the object, or he may misname it. He may show 
perseveration.' 15 
A typical case is the following (italics in the original): 

When the electrode was applied to the supramarginal gyrus at point 
27, he said: 'I know what it is', and was silent. When the electrode 
was withdrawn, he said at once, 'tree*, which was correct. 

When the electrode was applied to the posterior temporal region 
at 28, he was completely silent. A little time after the electrode was 
withdrawn, he exclaimed suddenly: 'Now I can talk — butterfly 
[which was correct]. I couldn't get that word "butterfly" and then I 
tried to get the word "moth". . . .' The speech mechanism was 
separately paralysed, and yet the man could understand what he saw 
and could substitute the concept, moth, for the concept butterfly, 
in a reasoned attempt to regain control of the speech mechanism, by 
presenting to it a new idea, moth. He could also snap his fingers (as 
he did) in exasperation at his failure. 

The words of C. H. [the patient] bring us face to face with other 
brain mechanisms. The concept of a moth, as distinguished from a 
butterfly, must also depend on a brain mechanism — a mechanism 
capable of functioning when the speech mechanism is selectively 
paralysed — a mechanism that stores something derived from the 
past 16 

Dropping the terminology of physiology for the moment, I may 
say that the patient presented the concept of a 'butterfly' to his speech 
mechanism, expecting that the word for it would be forthcoming. 
When the mechanism failed him, he cast about and selected an 
analogous concept from his storehouse of concepts and presented 
that to the speech mechanism. But again he was disappointed, and he 
snapped his fingers in exasperation. He could still express himself 
emotionally with his fingers in that way, although he would 
probably not have been able to write the lost words.* 

Penfield concludes that there exists a 'conceptual mechanism' in the 
brain, and a 'speech mechanism' which is structurally separate, and 
functionally separable from the former. 

We have seen that a considerable portion of mental activities is of 
a non-verbal character — in the nature of experiences which 'cannot be 
put into words', which remain incommunicable and inarticulate, and 
nevertheless play an important, sometimes even a dominant, part in a 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



603 



person s life. We now see that even in articulate verbal thinking, a 
distinction must be drawn between the ideational process and its con- 
version into verbal currency. I have quoted some of the clinical 
evidence; there is also a vast body of experimental evidence reviewed, 
e.g. by Humphrey (195 1). 17 Among the most convincing results are 
those which emerged from factor analysis (Burt, 1949).* 

Everyday experience points in the same direction. In states of fatigue 
one may read every word of a printed paraghraph without under- 
standing 'a single word of it'. And vice versa: every experienced 
lecturer knows that one's thoughts may race ahead, or go astray, 
while one goes on talking — as if talking were an automatized and 
autonomous skill like •the typist's who copies behind'. More precisely, 
the lecturer converts into verbal currency cognitive sub-wholes on 
lower levels of the hierarchy, which have already been portioned out 
or 'pre-chewed' by the ideational process proceeding on the higher 
level. 

"We may safely conclude, then, with Humphrey: 'Clinical expert" 
mental and factorial results agree that language cannot be equated with 
thinking. Language is ordinarily of great assistance in thinking. It may 
also be a hindrance.' 

NOTES 

Top. 504. Excerpt from the textbook Psychology t ed. A. D. Calvin (Boston, 
1961), Section Four: 'Learning, Retention and Motivation* by F.J. McGuigan: 

The experimental data that we have presented . . . have been limited, to 
rather simple responses such as salivation and bar-pressing. In our everyday 
life we seldom spend much time in thinking about such isolated responses, 
usually thinking of more gross activities, such as learning a poem, carrying on a 
conversation, solving a mechanical puzzle, learning our way around a new city, 
to name only a few. While the psychologist could study these more complicated 
activities, as is done to some extent, the general approach of psychology is to 
bring simpler responses into the laboratory for study. Once the psychologist dis- 
covers the principles of learning for simpler phenomena under the more ideal 
conditions of the laboratory [sic], it is likely that he can apply these principles 
to the more complex activities as they occur in everyday life. The more complex 
phenomena are, after all, nothing but a series of simpler responses. Speaking to a 
friend is a good example of this. Suppose we have a conversation such as the 
following: 

He: "What time is it?* 

She: 'Twelve o'clock.' 

He: 'Thank you.* 

She: 'Don't mention it.* 

He: 'How about lunch?* 

She: 'Fine.' 

Now this conversation can be analysed into separate S.-R. units. 'He' makes 
the first response, which is emitted probably to the stimulus of the sight of 'She*. 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



When 'He* emits the operant, 'What time is it?*, the muscular activity, of course, 
produces a sound, which also serves as a stimulus for 'She*. On the receipt of this 
stimulus, she emits an operant herself: 'Twelve o'clock', which in turn produces 
a stimulus to 'He'. And so on. . . . 

In such a complex activity, then, we can see that what we really have is a 
series of S.-R. connections. The phenomenon of connecting a series of such S.-R. 
units is known as chaining, a process that should be apparent in any complex 
activity. We might note that there are a number of sources of reinforcement 
throughout the chaining process, in this example the most obvious being the 
reinforcement of 'She' by receiving an invitation for lunch and of 'He' by having 
the invitation accepted. In addition, as Keller and Schoenfeld point out, there 
are such sources of reinforcement as the hearer 'encouraging' the speaker to 
continue, the use that the conversationalists make of the information received 
(he finds out what time it is), etc. 

This example of the analysis of a complex activity is but one of numerous 
possibilities that we could discuss. You should continue to think of others your- 
self and try to diagram the chaining process for them ... (p. 375). 

To p. 595. It is interesting to note that Hebb, an enlightened behaviourist 
yet a behaviourist, considers as the chief advantages of language that words can be 
used in varying combinations: 'In man ... we also have a kind of behaviour, 
which, as far as we know, does not occur in any other species. This is language. 
It includes sign language as well as spoken and written words; and the chief 
problem does not concern the ability to make the sounds of human speech, 
since lower animals are not capable of sign language either. What puts language 
on a higher level than the purposive communication of dog or chimpanzee is the 
varied combination of the same signs (words, pictures, gestures) for different pur- 
poses. . . . The criteria of language are then: (1) that it is usually purposive com- 
munication (though a number of non- purposive uses is common also, as in 
talking to oneself), and (2) that two or more items of the behaviour are com- 
bined in one way for one purpose and recombined for other purposes' (Hebb, 
1958, p. 209; his italics). Is that all? Or may we at least add, with Hilgard, that 
'without language it would be well-nigh impossible to think of such abstract 
notions as justice or reciprocal tariffs* (Hilgard, 1957, p. 315). 

Top. 601. In Head's gesture-imitation experiments, on the other hand, some 
kind of implicit verbal symbolization seems to be indispensable, because reliance 
on visual or kinesthetic clues leads only to the familiar mirror-confusion — as 
any normal person will discover by repeating the experiment. 

To p. 602. One might further speculate that the patient's inability to name 
the object shown on the printed card, while he is perfectly capable of using words 
to explain that he cannot name it, may be due to the fact that single object-names 
like tree, moth, etc., have a more arbitrary character qua phonetic labels learnt by 
rote, and have more 'brittle' traces, than verbs and propositions which form 
syntactic sub-wholes. A 'tree', after all, is originally a nonsense syllable. One of 
Penfield's patients, shown a card picturing a foot, said, 'Oh, I know what it is. 
That is what you put in your shoes'. After withdrawal of the electrode, he said 
correctly 'foot'. Now why should 'foot* be more difficult to name than 'shoe'? 
Perhaps because the word 'shoe' occurred in a meaningful context — Burt's 
Factor II of Verbal Ability — whereas 'foot* occurred in a naming context (Factor 
I) which was blocked (see next note). In other words, the naming-code was out 
of action, while the semantic code continued to function. 



LEARNING TO SPEAK 



605 



To p. 603. Burt divided Verbal Ability into a word factor dealing with words 
in isolation and a language factor dealing with words in their context. The former 
he sub-divided into a receptive factor of recognizing and understanding words 
and into an executive factor for finding and selecting the right word. The 
language factor is similarly sub-divided into a receptive factor for understanding 
statements and an executive factor for literary expression and verbal fluency. 
Burt's divisions followed in broad outline Head's classifications of aphasia and 
substantiated the validity of the letter, (The British Journal of Educational Psy- 
chology, Vol. XIX, June and November, 1949). 



XV 

LEARNING TO THINK 



tet me return to the early development of verbal matrices. 
From about the eighteenth month onward, the child acquires 
-/ new words at a faster rate; about the same time it begins to 
correlate single words into word-sequences, and later on into sentences. 
The earliest word-sequences are again produced by spontaneous, un- 
directed vocal activity, in which meaningful words alternate with 
strings of nonsense syllables and with words imitated but not yet 
understood. Some children have the uncanny gift of imitating the 
phonetic patterns of adult speech so well that from the next room their 
babbling sounds like a meaningful monologue. If we are to believe 
Bertrand Russell, his daughter at the age of eighteen months, 'when 
supposed to be sleeping, was overheard saying to herself: "Last year 
I used to dive off the diving-board, I did." Of course, "last year" was 
merely a phrase repeated without understanding. . . .' x This philoso- 
phical comment seems to imply, oddly enough, that the remainder of 
the sentence was pronounced with understanding. 

Frequently the first meaningful string of words refers to a sequence 
of events. Fenton's unusually precocious son, also at the age of eighteen 
months, 'uttered soon after seeing his father climb into an automobile 
with another man and drive away, the words, "Daddy, school, man, 
auto".* 2 This sounds exactly like the 'picture-strip language' of the 
primitive (as Kretschmer called it 3 ) — the unrolling of a visual sequence, 
where each single word symbolizes a complete event. 'The speech 
units of the child belong to no single class of words because they are 
(i.e. stand for) not single words but sentences/* Even the first verbal 
labels have a not merely denotative, but an operative character; they 
do not refer to objects in vacuo, but to 'action-objects', 5 that is to say, 
to the functional relevance of the object to the child. 'Chamberlain, 
Tracy, Dewey, Binet and others have shown that the child's symbols 

606 



LEARNING TO THINK 



607 



are action-words, i.e., their content is action. There is also practically 
universal agreement on the fact that the first symbols of the child are 
in reality word-sentences designating action and object or subject, 
or all three at once.' 6 

This, of course, is again a far cry from any S.-R. theory of language 
learning. The command right turn is a simple and definite verbal 
stimulus, which, one would think, should be easy to associate with a 
definite motor response; but many children and some normal adults 
have considerable difficulty in distmguishing between right and left. 
This fact is used by Hebb as an elegant proof that the concept (of right- 
left-sidedness) precedes the word for it: 'The child can very readily learn 
at the age of three that "right" and "left" each refers to a side of the 
body — but ah me, which one? . . . What is set up first is a conceptual 
organization. By the age of six the word "right" clearly and im- 
mediately means sidedness to the child. A considerable conceptual 
elaboration has already occurred, and the stimulus effectively arouses 
that structure; but it arouses no prompt, specific response. . . . With 
such facts, it becomes nonsense to explain man's conceptual 
development as exclusively consisting of verbal associations.* 7 

The point becomes clearer when we realize that between the ages of 
two and four many children are equally confused about 'up-down', 
'back-front', etc.; but they only confuse opposites with each other, 
never 'left' with 'up' or 'front' with 'down'. 8 This shows that the child 
forms at an early stage sensory-motor matrices of 'up-downness*, 
left-rightness', etc.; and that the verbal labels acquired later on may 
become attached to the matrix as a whole, before directions within the 
matrix are verbally cUscriminated. This does not mean, of course, that 
abstraction preceded ^crimination, since both are aspects of the same 
process; it only means that there is often delay and confusion in the 
verbal labelling of pre-verbal concepts. 

This brings us to the central problems of the evolution of symbolic 
thought: abstraction and concept-formation. 

Abstraction, Discrimination, and Transfer 

In common usage abstract' thought is regarded as a specifically 
human faculty, and more particularly as a prerogative of the scientific 
mind. The Concise Oxford defines abstraction as 'the process of strip- 
ping an idea of its concrete accompaniments'. There are, however, 



6o8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



obvious analogies between the abstraction of ideas — the formation of 
concepts — and perceptual generalization — the extraction of invariant 
features, stripped of their accidental accompaniments, from varied 
situations. It is therefore frequently asserted or implied that abstract 
thought is merely the extension, along a continuous scale, of selective 
processes which operate already in the rat and even lower down. I shall 
first briefly recapitulate those aspects of the abstractive process which 
are indeed continuous with animal learning — until we arrive at the 
point where the line again breaks. I shall again use the term generaliza- 
tion' in the sense indicated above — and not in the sense of 'spreading of 
responses* (seep. 537 ff.). 

The continuum of abstractive processes can be extended down into 
the inorganic domain. The green-grocer's balance abstracts from a 
pound of peaches and a pound of potatoes the one feature which it has 
been programmed to recognize as relevant, their weight. A barometer, 
programmed to compensate for variations of temperature, can be 
regarded as a model for perceptual size-constancy — the apparatus 
programmed to compensate for distance. The same barometer used 
as an altimeter may serve to illustrate the reversible figure-ground 
relation. Each of these programmes is represented by a code which 
determines which type of stimulus should be regarded as relevant and 
abstracted from experience, and which not. 

Built-in perceptual analysers for the recognition of species-specific 
sign-releasers may be described as the result of the phylogenetic ab- 
straction of biologically relevant stimulus-patterns. We may regard 
this abstractive power, with Lashley, as 'one of the primitive basic 
functions of organized nervous tissue'. 9 

Turning to acquired behaviour, we must distinguish between learn- 
ing under natural and artificial conditions. In both cases the animal 
must learn to abstract relevant patterns from its environment as a 
conditio sine qua non of properly reacting to them. With animals in their 
natural habitat this happens either during maturation, or, in adult 
animals, after a few repetitions of a certain kind of experience. Since 
the animal attends only to stimuli which are biologically relevant to it 
— to which its perceptual organization is 'attuned' — the learning pro- 
cess consists essentially in the sharpening and modification of its built- 
in perceptual analysers. In the laboratory situation, however, the 
animal must in the first place readjust to an artificial universe, in which 
stimuli which it would normally treat as irrelevant, become all- 
important. When this revaluation is well under way, the cat in the box 



LEARNING TO THINK 



will begin to abstract from its bewildering environment die significant 
patterns of loops and bolts in general, regardless of variations in their 
position and shape. But this will be a slow, repetitive process because 
abstraction is a function of relevance, and relevance in this case must 
be inferred by induction; the cat is caught in a vicious circle. Even so, 
its powers of abstraction are considerable — see the perfunctory lick 
reduced to a symbolic performance (p. 570). The rat in the maze is in 
a more favourable position: it likes exploring highways and byways; 
and the cognitive map which it abstracts from a number of concrete 
tries provides it with a matrix of remarkable plasticity — see Lashley's 
extirpation experiments, pp. 458 f. 

The child's pre-verbal concepts are derived from abstractive pro- 
cesses which form a continuous series with animal learning — from the 
early development of its perceptual constancies and its 'sensory-motor 
intelligence' to the crystallization of 'object concepts'. The child learns 
to recognize its mother before it learns the word 'ma'. Unlike the 
gosling whose nervous system is ready, a few hours after its birth, to 
receive the imprint of the mother-goose all in one piece, the helpless 
infant must slowly, and perhaps painfully, abstract the concept of 
its mother as a stable, unvarying entity from a series of her very varied 
appearances, all different in shape, and disconnected in time. The breast 
first, more tactile than visual, monopolizing the whole perceptual 
field; a fully-clad figure with concealed breasts, standing or bending 
over; a series of faces appearing at intervals, never looking quite the 
same — such must have been the fragmentary, concrete experiences 
out of which the unitary mother concept was extracted in the first 
three weeks of our existence — if only we could remember. 

However, owing to the nursing mother's exceptional importance 
to, and sustained bodily contact with, the child the formation of the 
mother-concept must also be regarded as an exceptional process in 
which several successive stages are telescoped into one. Other object 
and action concepts emerge more slowly and hesitantly, even if the 
object is a person. The adult's awareness of other people's personal 
identity is based on empathy-^which is a projective phenomenon, in 
some respects comparable to the stroboscopic effect. But in the babe 
the experience of its own identity is still hazy, and so is its awareness 
of the personal identity of others. When a feature F, which is im- 
portant to the child, is common to several individuals whose other 
attributes are less important to it, then the child will abstract, con- 
ceptualize, and name that shared feature in preference to the collection 



6io 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



of features which constitutes each individual's personal identity. This 
can happen even if one of the persons concerned is the father — at the 
stage before the father becomes functionally important to the baby. A 
baby is often taught the word 'da-da' before it has learned to recognize 
its father — except for some vague features such as largeness or bulki- 
ness, which are equally found in other appearances. As a result, it 
applies the label 'da-da' 'widely and often embarrassingly to large 
individuals of all shapes, sizes, ages, and colours'. 10 Abstraction and 
discrimination are guided by relevance; and the relevant experience 
in this case is some feature of dada-ness shared by lots of visitors who 
— their colour, age, etc., being as yet irrelevant — are not discriminated 
as individuals. It is the same with the gosling, which in the first stage 
of imprinting follows all human shapes, and only later on confines its 
attention to the keeper. During the first stage individual differences in 
appearance are seen, but not 'taken in' and retained, because they are 
not yet relevant to the gosling; during the second stage the distinguish- 
ing marks become relevant because the gosling has learned that keepers 
produce food, while other humans do not. Thus the sharpenings and 
modifications of discriminatory codes are the result of changes in the 
scales of relevance. In the first stage of development, all 'dada-ish' 
visitors to the baby — and all human beings to the gosling — are regarded 
as 'for all intents and purposes the same thing' ; in the second stage they 
no longer are, because the intents and purposes have changed. 

I have laboured this point at the risk of repetitiveness because once 
accepted, it allows us to dispense with terms like transfer, spreading, 
'generalization' (in sense b, cf. p. 537), and 'association by similarity' — 
and to close the lid of the semantic Pandora box. Take, for instance, 
"Watson's famous experiment intended to establish a 'conditioned fear 
reflex' in an infant eleven months of age, by striking an iron bar 
with a hammer each time the child touched its pet animal, a white rat. 
After this was repeated several times within the span of a week, little 
Albert responded with fear, crying, etc., whenever the rat was shown 
to him. But he also showed fright-reactions in varying degrees to 
rabbits, fur coats, cotton wool, and human hair—none of which had 
frightened him before. Watson concluded, and a number of textbooks 
with him, that the conditioned reflex had 'spread' or been 'transferred' 
to all furry things — words which have the connotation of motion in 
space, conveying the image that the child had somehow lifted its fear- 
reaction from the rat and put it down on the piece of cotton wool. In 
fact the idea of the 'spreading' of the conditioned response was origin- 



LEARNING TO THINK <5ll 

ally derived from Pavlov's notion of the irradiation of excitatory- 
processes spreading across the cortical tissues. This physiological theory 
of Pavlov's has long been abandoned, 11 but its unconscious echoes still 
haunt the laboratories. On a metaphorical level there is of course no 
objection to saying that the child's dread had spread from rats to cotton 
wool, but on the technical level the concept of 'spreading' has no 
explanatory value, and has been the source of endless confusion. (The 
same applies to 'transfer', and to 'generalization' used as a synonym 
for spreading.) Instead of pretending that the child has shifted its 
response, along a so-called generalization gradient, from rat to cotton 
wool, we should say that it has abstracted the tactile quality of furriness, 
and recognized it in the cotton wool. And its reaction to it was per- 
fecdy logical, because Watson had taught it that furriness always 
signalled the dreaded bang. It would of course be nonsensical to pretend 
that this child of eleven months was incapable of seeing the difference 
between rabbit, cotton wool, and human hair. But at that time the 
tactile quality alone was relevant, and with regard to that, rabbit, rat, 
and fur coat were all 'the same thing' (cf. pp. 537 ff.). 

We can observe the operation of the same principles on the verbal 
level at a more advanced age. Stern's daughter, Hilda, 12 at the age of 
nineteen months, had been in the habit of pulling at her parents' 
noses; when she discovered that the tips of their shoes (before having 
learned the name 'shoe') offered the same satisfactory opportunities, 
she prompdy named them 'noses'. Again, instead of speaking of 
'transfer', etc., we shall say that the child recognized an abstracted 
quality that could be found in various objects. Koffka mentions a 
boy of twenty-six months 'to whom "la-la" first meant song or music; 
later when he heard a military band, it meant soldier, and finally all 
kinds of noises, including sounds like claps and thuds. . . . Another 
little boy uttered the word "atta" at the end of his eleventh month 
whenever anything disappeared — when a person left the room or 
when a light was turned out.* 13 

The first object- and relation-concepts to be abstracted and named 
are those which have the greatest functional relevance to the child. 
At that stage no verbal distinctions are made between objects and 
attributes, between qualities and things in which these qualities are 
vested, between nouns, adjectives, and verbs. Lala refers to music; it 
functions as a collective name for bells, soldiers, instruments; and if we 
feel that Lala is a silly name for a soldier, but regard 'redcoat' or 
'poilu as reasonable, then only because wearing a red coat or being 



6*12 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



unshaven appear to us more relevant martial qualities than making 
music. "When the child learns to use words, the functionally most 
important aspect of an as yet unnamed object or event will provide 
its name; the less important aspects of secondary qualities are then 
relegated to the role of 'going together with it' — its 'attributes' or 
'parts' or 'functions'. But the criteria of relevance change with age; 
when Stern's little girl learned to walk, shoes acquired a more im- 
portant function than that which they shared with noses; and with it a 
new name. 

Of course the visual experience of Watson's baby is different when 
it touches a rat and when it touches a fur coat; but it is the touch that 
matters, the visual aspect is irrelevant, and accordingly, in its overt 
reactions, the baby does not discriminate between the two. Similarly, 
the baby mentioned by Koffka saw the difference between the shapes 
of its Teddy bear and of its stuffed rabbit; but this difference is irrele- 
vant at the early age when all that matters is. manipulating a soft toy; 
hence the name 'dolly* was sufficient to symbolize the whole class, 
and no motivational need arose for explicit verbal cUscrimination. 
Adults behave much the same way. The Eskimoes have several words 
for various kinds of snow where we have only one; but Malinovski's 
savages had only one word, manna wala, for all insects and birds — 
except those that could be eaten. Building workers, who shift from 
job to job, cannot be bothered to learn one another's names; all elec- 
tricians are 'Sparks' and all carpenters 'Chippies'. Elderly ladies addic- 
ted to romantic novels from the lending library feel that the names of 
authors are irrelevant; all that matters is that it should be a 'nice book'. 

Thus all along the line we abstract and discriminate only qualities 
which are relevant to us; and new cUscriminations arise as a result of 
changes in our criteria of relevance — where 'us' refers to animal and 
man. In the normal development of the individual these changes are 
due to maturation and guided learning. In the experimental laboratory, 
as in reformatory schools and other brainwashing establishments, 
rewards and punishments effect the transformation of the subject's, or 
victim's, scale of values. In classical conditioning all tuning forks are 
'the same thing' to the dog until the difference in pitch is made sig- 
nificant by the giving or withholding of food. In guided learning, all 
pages in his algebra book look the same to the schoolboy unci he 
learns to distinguish linear from quadratic equations at a glance. 

Distinctions which are irrelevant to the subject will either go entirely 
tmnotked; or they may be perceived but not retained; or they may be 



LEARNING TO THINK 



613 



retained but not verbally discriminated. Thus if we fail to observe 
differences, it is either because we lack the equipment for doing so 
('lack of discrimination in the colloquial sense), or because the 
differences are 'indifferent' to us, or not important enough to give 
them verbal labels (e.g. knowing stars by sight but not by name). 

I have dwelt at some length on the subject of abstraction and dis- 
crimination because although most of what I have said would seem 
self-evident to the layman, this would not be the case with students 
of experimental psychology — or of philosophy, if it comes to that. 
Already in the twelfth century a.d. John of Salisbury remarked that 
the world had grown old discussing the problem, and that it had spent 
more time on it than the Caesars took to conquer the world. But 
Pavlov, Watson, and those direcdy or indirecdy influenced by them 
have certainly made confusion worse confounded.* 

From the genetic point of view, abstraction and discrimination 
appear (cf. pp. 608 f.) as the latest extensions of the basic principles which 
we saw at work on all levels of the hierarchy, starting with the inte- 
gration of functions and differentiation of structures in morphogenesis. 
Abstraction, by creating pattern and order out of the chaotic stream 
of experience, corresponds to the former; discrimination in perception 
and the consequent differentiation of response correspond, as language 
indicates, to the latter. If we wish to indulge in analogies, we might say 
that the categories of Aristotle acted as embryonic inductors on the 
self-differentiating morphogenetic fields of conceptual thought. 

The Magic of Names 

We have so far distinguished several stages in the child's progress: 

(a) the abstraction of pre-verbal object concepts (and action concepts); 

(b) attaching a verbal symbol, which soon acquires central importance, 
to the concept; (c) the discovery, signalled by the appearance of the 
naming question, that all things have names, that the words previously 
learned are only particular instances of a general relation between 
words and things. The next step consists in the concretization of this 
relation itself in the concept name'. The child has realized that not 
only have all things verbal handles and labels attached to them, but 
that these labels and handles are called names. 

A characteristic feature of this development is that at each step a 
relation has been abstracted and turned into a relatum. At the first step 



6i4 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the relation between the varied particular appearances of the mother 
was turned into a single relatum 'mama', which now enters as a unit 
into other relations; at the last step the relation between words and 
things was abstracted and turned into the conceptual entity 'name'. 
'Name is the verbal symbol attached to the relation of verbal sym- 
bolism; by being made explicit and conscious the relation is now 
experienced as a concrete relatum. 

In fact, an over-concrete relatum. To quote Piaget: 'Names are, 
to begin with, situated in objects. They form part of things in the 
same way as do colour and form. Things have always had their names. 
It has always been sufficient to look at things to know their names. . . . 
To deform the name is to deform the thing/ 14 When a child of four 
and a half was asked how one knows that the sun's name is *sun\ it 
answered: 'Just because one sees it*. And when a child of nine was 
asked whether one could have given another name to the sun, he 
answered: 'No — because the sun is just the sun*. Another child of six 
and a half, when pressed, admitted that God could have given the sun 
another name, but in this case 'God would have done something 
wrong'. 16 

When Herschel discovered Uranus, the German naturalist Sachs 
remarked sceptically: 'What guarantee have we that the planet found 
by him really is Uranus?' Equally inspired was this philosophic re- 
flection of an Englishman: 'English is the most logical language; a 
knife, for instance, is called by the French couteau, by the Germans 
Messer, and so on, whereas the English call it "a knife" which is after 
all what a knife really is.' 

In the mentality of primitives, the person and his name are magically 
related. In Eastern religions, evocation of the names of deities — the 
recital of mantras — fulfils a magic function; in Tibetan Buddhism 
the work is left to the prayer mill. This attitude lingers on in medieval 
philosophy (Realists versus Nominalists); in all forms of magic, and, 
more covertly in modern science — in the unconscious belief that 
words like gravity, entelechy, or electro-magnetic 'field', etc., some- 
how have an explanatory value an sich (cf. Book One, VII). Such 
is the power of verbal symbols to focus attention that it confers on 
hazy concepts in statu nascendi the appearance of hard, tangible 
concreteness, and 'gives to airy nothing /a local habitation and a 
name'. The name is then experienced as a self-evident explanation, a 
saturation of free valencies as it were. 



The Rise of Causality 



During its first years the child does not discriminate between nominal, 
attributive, and causal predications — as earlier it did not differentiate 
words according to grammatical categories. 

When children between five and six are asked: 'Why does the sun 
not fall down?', they will answer: 'Because it is hot', 'Because the sun 
stops there*, 'Because it is yellow'. 15 And the moon does not fall down 
'Because it is very high up', 'Because the sun is not there', etc. The sig- 
nificant aspects of an experience are connected as 'going together* 
in an undifferentiated 'feeling of relation'. 16 Goethe's 'Connect, always 
connect' seems to be the motto of the child as, out of the fluid raw 
material of its experiences, it selects and shapes patterns and relations 
— relations which will be re-classed and re-grouped later on according 
to shifts in motivation and interest leading to the emergence of new 
criteria of relevance — until the final, more rigid but not always more 
perfect adult relation-categories emerge. The urge to connect, to 
aggregate matrices of experience into more comprehensive ones; the 
fumbling for hypotheses about the way things are held together, the 
tentative formulation of rules of the game — in all these fertile activities 
we see the participatory tendencies at work: intimations of the funda- 
mental unity of all things. Later on they will crystallize in magic 
causality, with its correlates: animism and 'mystic participation* (to 
use an expression coined by Levy-Bruhl for the mentality of primi- 
tives, and applied by Piaget to the mentality of the child). Needless 
to say, the self-asserting tendencies too play their obvious part both 
in the child's overt behaviour and its fantasy world. 

It seems that the first relational patterns which arc discriminated are 
relatively static forms of attribution (of names and other properties), 
and of dynamic changes-in-time. The latter give rise to a vague 'feeling 
of causal relations' 20 derived from the cumulative experience that 
'things make other things do things'. At this stage, word-classes begin 
to emerge which roughly correspond to substantive-nouns, adjective- 
attributes, and action-words or verbs. But these classes, and the types 
of relations implied in them, remain for a long time fluid. The child's 
progress towards grammatically more correct forms of speech is 
mainly due to imitation and conventional training— which mask the 
fact that behind the increasingly adult forms of expression, magic 
ways of thought survive. They survive, of course, even in the adult, 
and never vanish completely. Thus the stabilization of the codes of 

615 



6i<5 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



grammar and syntax in no way corresponds to the dynamic evolution 
of thought, and inferences drawn from the former to the latter have 
for a long time misled child psychologists. 21 

"With the momentous realization that 'one thing leads to another', 
intimations of causality emerge from the fluid pool of perceived 
'togetherness* and ^elatedness*. The homo novus has now set out on a 
long and tortuous road, which has in fact no end, except where, of his 
own choice, he will come to rest — theological causality, mechanical 
causality, statistical probability — gods playing billiards or throwing 
dice. But children are philosophical optimists, and the same process of 
empirical induction which earlier on led to the discovery that all 
things have names, now leads to the discovery that all things have 
'becauses'. The sequel is a familiar one: the naming question is re- 
placed by the 'why* question which is many a parent's despair; just 
as a thing was incomplete without a name, so now an event has a free 
valency which must be filled by a 'because'. The actual content of the 
proffered explanation, the when, and how, and how much, is as yet 
of secondary importance; 'the sun does not fall down because it is 
yellow' is accepted as quite as satisfactory an answer as 'the dolly is 
called dolly because that's her name'. Just as, at the earlier stage, when 
a name was not immediately offered, it was invented to fill the vacancy, 
so now, when no 'because' is proffered at once, an explanation is 
provided ad hoc by the child itself. And just as the invention of names 
is guided by onomatopoeia or private associations, so the causal ex- 
planations of children are derived from their private matrices of 
thought. 

The questioning mania is reinforced by the desire to attract atten- 
tion and to be in the centre of events; it is a typical mixture of par- 
ticipatory and self-assertive motivations. Lorimer made a record of all 
the why's asked by a child of four years, eleven months, in the course 
of four days, 17 which is both charming and instructive. (One asterisk 
signifies that no answer was given; two asterisks: no answer given, 
question not repeated): 

1. "Why do you have this box for your feet? 

2. Why did they bring the bed down from the attic? 

3. Take your dollies in now, Joyce! Why? 

4. Fix the rug! You caught your feet under the edge of it! Why? Why 
did I? 

5. Why did you take two cookies? 



LEARNING TO THINK 



617 



6. Why does the watering-pot have two handles? 

7. "Why did he put the solder in so many places? 

8. The song-sparrow isn't pretty to look at — Why isn't he pretty? 

9. The bobolink has a brown coat in winter. Why?* Why? 

10. It was careless of you to lose your shovel. Why?* Why? 

11. This is your orange juice. Why?** 

12. You are to sit here, in Daddy s place. Why?* — Please, Mother, tell 
me why. 

13. Do we have bangs at the back of our heads? No! Why?* Why, 
Mother? 

14. And then he made a mast for his little boat. Why? Please tell me why 
he made a mast. 

15. Why do you wash the hair off (the razor)? 

16. (Putting on bathrobe without putting her arms in the sleeves) 
Is this good? No. Why?* — (impatiently) Why? Speak out! (but then 
without waiting for an answer) Because it wouldn't stay on. There, 
you thought it out for yourself, didn't you? 

17. Why did you stub your toe? Because I wasn't watching out. Why? 
18. 1 will tell you a story about this willow plate — Why?** 

19. Please hurry, Joyce! Why?* — Because you want me to wash?* 
Why didn't you wash first? Because you knew I wanted to go with 
Daddy? 

20. See the little tea things! Why did we buy them? Why do you 
think? Because we might use the others all up. 

21. Why did you use both a fork and a spoon in making that cake? 

22. Why did you sit in that chair, Mother? 

23. Please don't climb in that chair! Why?** 

24. Why are you putting up that screen?** 

25. Why are you opening that window?** 

26. Why does the little chicken grow in the shell? 

27. You can't win by jumping up and down! Why? 

28. Jeremiah, Jeremiah. He got into a pit, didn't he? Why did they 
put him into a pit? 

29. Please be careful not to break the bean-plants. Why? 

30. 1 saw your blue apron through a crack in the door. I thought it 
was a spider. A spider isn't blue, dear! Why?* — Please, Mother, tell me 
why a spider isn't blue. 

31. You shouldn't talk about a visitor's beard, Joyce, until he has gone! 
Why?* Please tell me why. 

32. Why don't you have a beard, Mother? 



6i8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



33.I want to cut my eyebrows in half! Oh! You wouldn't want to do 
that! Why? Because I would look funny? 

34. Why do we have eyebrows? 

35. Why must I hurry? 

36. Why should I wait for candy until after supper? 

37. Why did you speak to that man? 

38. Please dont bang the car-door! Why?* 

39. Why did the chickens walk in front of the car? 

40. It is time to go home for dinner now! Why?* 

A certain number of these questions are obviously motivated by the 
desire to attract attention or intended as a protest; others are quasi- 
automatic exercises of the questioning habit — they remind one of 
Leerlauf activities in vacuo. But others, such as Nos. 2, 9, 26, 32, are 
expressions of genuine curiosity; Lorimer put thirteen out of forty 
questions into this category, judging them by content and the child's 
expression. It is curiosity of a new type, no longer directed at the 
practical or playful uses of things only, but at the mystery of their 
'becauses'. 

The word 'because* now plays a similar part to that which the 
word name* did before: an abstracted relation has become a relatum, 
concretized in a verbal symbol. The child's concept of 'becauseness', 
i.e. causality, will undergo a series of changes, but not the verbal 
symbol which refers to it. Later on, the causal relation will enter as a 
relatum into the higher matrix of logical categories'; and even later 
this class, in its turn, will become a member of the matrices of epis- 
tomology, psychology, and so on. 

Explaining and Understanding 

This leads us to the question of the nature of explanation. 

Earlier on I quoted Craik's suggestion that the nervous system's 
main function is 'to model or parallel external events', and that 'this 
process of paralleling is the basic feature of thought and explanation. 18 
In terms of the present theory the 'model* consists of hierarchies of 
flexible matrices with fixed codes, abstracted by the organism accor- 
ding to its lights. Insight and understanding then become relative 
terms, the degree of understanding depending on how many different 
aspects of reality have been abstracted, how sharply they are dis- 



LEARNING TO THINK 



6l9 



criminated, to what extent the abstract codes lend themselves to 
explicit formulations, and the degree of precision and error which the 
model reveals when subjected to the test of empirical verification. 

We have seen that it is necessary to distinguish between progress 
in understanding — the acquisition of new insights, and the exercise of 
understanding at any given stage of development. Progress in under- 
standing is achieved by the formulation of new codes through the 
modification and integration of existing codes by methods already 
discussed: empirical induction, abstraction and discrimination, bi- 
sociation. The exercise or application of understanding — the explanation 
of particular events — then becomes an act of subsuming the particular 
event under the codes formed by past experience. To say that we have 
understood a phenomenon means that we have recognized one or 
more of its relevant relational features as particular instances of more 
general or familiar relations, which have been previously abstracted 
and encoded. 

The conventional test of understanding is verbal explanation — the 
subject is invited to name the general rule of which the event to be 
explained is a particular instance. But the availablility of such neat and 
ready explanations is the exception rather than the rule — unless the 
explanation was learned by rote — because, in the first place, the 
codes which govern perception and cognition function below the 
level of focal awareness; in the second place because a great number of 
codes which govern thinking are unverbalized — including the codes 
of verbal thinking, grammar, and syntax; thirdly because there are 
emergent, 'nascent* codes which are still unstable and cannot be 'pinned 
down', but are sometimes nevertheless of decisive help to understand- 
ing. We thus arrive at a whole series of gradations in understanding 
and explanation — such as: 

(a) Unconscious understanding mediated by the dream — a form of 
internal discourse in which specific experiences are subsumed under 
very old, emotion-charged matrices with pre-verbal codes. The 
transformations and disguises which people and events undergo in the 
dream may be described as acts of recognition of different appearances 
as the 'same thing* on the scales of symbolic relevance peculiar to the 
dream. Myth, folklore, fairy-tale, the fantasy world and magic 
causality of the child are rnainly inspired by this type of understand- 
ing; and the explanations offered by primitives and children for 
their beliefs are true explanations in the sense defined, 

(b) Tentative explanations, which indicate that the matrix into which 



620 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the event is to be incorporated is still in the process of construction 
by trial-and-error learning and hypothesis-formation. 

(c) Half-understood explanations referring to matrices in statu nascendi 
which, unlike (b), are being formed mainly by unconscious guidance, 
by unverbalized analogies, etc. 

(d) Explanation by explicit analogy — its validity depending on 
whether it is arrived at by selective or Procrustean methods. 

(e) Implicit understanding, when the phenomenon is recognized as 
an instance of a relation which has been abstracted but cannot be made 
verbally explicit. 

(f) The same as (e) plus a verbal label. The abstracted pattern can 
now be named but not otherwise verbally described, ('sweet', 'pungent', 
'beautiful' — visceral, kinesthetic, aesthetic experiences). 

(g) Explicit verbal explanations and definitions which sound precise 
and convincing, but where the codes to which they refer contain 
some hidden axiom, idee recue, unwarranted assumption. 

(h) Over-explicit, rigid definitions which explain away problems as 
meaningless by taking the verbal components of the symbolic model 
to pieces — forgetting that the 'exact' sciences have always operated 
with fuzzy concepts, that good cooks work in dirty kitchens, and that 
the sterilization of verbal concepts leads to sterility. 

Other headings could be interpolated into this list. Compared with 
the relatively few levels of understanding in the rat and even the chim- 
panzee, man's explanatory hierarchies represent a veritable tower of 
Babel; not merely because they reach higher, but because there are 
more finely graded levels between the unconscious processes at the base, 
and the abstract symbolism at the top. 

Thus instead of talking of insight and understanding as all-or- 
nothing processes, and making verbal explanation a test for passing 
school exams, we should proceed by more cautious statements, such 
as: Johnnie has now understood that a phenomenon P is a particular 
instance of a general relation R which he can name; he has also under- 
stood that R is a particular instance of S, which he can also name. He 
may further have grasped that S is a particular instance of T which he 
has abstracted but which he cannot verbalize; or it may dawn on him 
that experiences of the type S have something in common, and are 
perhaps particular instances of some general relation T, which, how- 
ever, he has not yet abstracted. 

It follows that the degree of clarity and penetration of Johnnie's 
understanding must not be judged by the 'absolute height' he has 



LEARNING TO THINK 



621 



reached in any 'vertical* abstractive hierarchy, but by the mastery he 
has attained on his own particular level. This depends on the factors 
already discussed, where the multi-dimensionality of experience (the 
intersection of several abstractive hierarchies in it) was taken for 
granted. Thus a garage mechanic may have a more complete under- 
standing of the structure and function of motor cars than a theoretical 
physicist, in spite of the latter's more extended abstractive hierarchies; 
and an experienced Nanny may know more about children than an 
experimental psychologist. 'Vertical' progress in abstraction is of 
primary importance in the theoretical sciences only, but not in other 
domains of experience which are of greater significance to the majority. 
This may be the reason why the abstractive hierarchies were built up 
so very slowly in the learning process of the human species — although 
the native equipment for it was given millennia ago — and are acquired 
at an equally hesitant rate by the child. 

Theoretically the building of the tower of Babel, of hierarchies of 
abstractions, can go on indefinitely, or until the most general patterns 
of events are subsumed as particular instances under one all-embracing 
law — a lapis philosophorum, or the unified field equations which 
Einstein hoped to find. But in fact individuals and cultures have their 
own ceilings of abstraction, where their quest for ultimates reaches 
saturation point — in theism, pantheism, vitalism, mechanism, or 
Hegelian dialectics. In less exalted domains the ceiling can be sur- 
prisingly low. Some primitive languages have words for particular 
colours but no word for 'colour* as a class. The abstraction of Space 
and Time as categories independent from the objects which occupy 
them (i.e. from duration and extension) is only some three hundred 
years old; so are the concepts of mass, force, etc. The slow, fumbling 
emergence of abstract concepts which in retrospect appear so self- 
evident, is best illustrated by the beginning of mathematics — a domain 
where pure abstraction seems to reign supreme. 



The Dawn of Mathematics 

To quote Russell's famous dictum once more, 'it must have required 
many ages to discover that a brace of pheasants and a couple of days 
were both instances of the number two'. In fact, evidence indicates 
that the discovery was not made in one fell swoop, but in several hesi- 
tant steps; and when it was achieved, some cultures were quite content 



622 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



to stop there and rest on their glories: Australian aborigines have only- 
three number-words in their vocabulary: one, two, and many. 1 * 
Most European languages show the traces of this stage of development: 
the Latin ter means both 'three times' and 'many* (cf. 'thrice blest'). 

At the earliest stage the number concept is not yet abstracted from 
the objects which are numbered: 'two-ness' is a feature situated in 
particular twosome objects, not a general relation. Language bears 
witness to this 'embeddedness': a 'brace* of pheasants is not a 'pride* 
of lions; a 'pair', when married, is a 'couple', when engaged in singing, 
a 'duo'. In some primitive languages not only the number two but all 
numerals adhere to the type of object counted; in the Timshian tongue 
of New Guinea there are seven different classes of number-words 
referring, respectively, to flat objects, round objects, long objects, 
people, canoes, and measures; the seventh, used for counting in general, 
was the latest to develop. 20 

Children go through a similar stage; Koffka mentions several three- 
year-olds who understood and used the words 'two apples', but did 
not understand 'two eyes', 'two ears'. One child, over four, when 
asked by hisf grandfather, 'How many fingers have I?', replied, 'I 
don't know; I can only count my own fingers.' There is an old joke 
about the new arithmetic teacher who, when he asked the class, 'How 
many oranges would Johnnie have if . . . etc.', received the indignant 
reply, 'Please, sir, we have only learned to count in apples'. The num- 
ber-matrix, once adherent to the object-matrix, has gained such 
lofty independence, that their re-union is experienced as a bisociation 
of incompatibles. 

The next step is the abstraction of individual numbers, which are not 
yet regarded as parts of a continuous series. The first 'personalized' 
number-concept abstracted by primitive and child alike is almost in- 
variably the number two. Next follow the concepts one' and 'many'. 
Some cultures, as mentioned, stop there; others retain traces of this 
stage in their languages; Hebrew and Greek have retained separate 
grammatical forms for the singular, the dual, and the plural. Koffka 
mentions a child who played with combinations of 'two and one', 
'two and two', etc., until early into its fifth year; only then did the 
number-word 'three* become firmly established. 

These first individual number-concepts are only semi-abstract; 
they emerge as it were reluctantly from the womb, and retain for a 
long time the umbilical cord which attaches them to concrete objects 
or favourite symbols. In some primitive languages the word for five 



LEARNING TO THINK 



623 



is 'hand', for ten 'two hands'. Each number primarily refers to some 
such 'model collection' of practical or mystical significance: the four 
cardinal points, the Holy Trinity, the magic Pentagram. Each number 
has its preferential connotation, its personality and individual profile; 
it is as yet unrelated to other numbers and does not form a continuous 
series with them. The number sense of Otto Koehler's birds who 
can identify at a glance object-collections up to seven, and the same 
faculty of human subjects (to whom heterogeneous objects are shown 
on a screen for a time too short for counting) give us some idea of the 
character of our own earliest number-concepts. They could be des- 
cribed as qualities rather than as quantities in a graded series; the identi- 
fication of numbers in experiments where counting is excluded, con- 
sists apparently in recognizing the quasi-Gestalt quality of 'fiveness' 
(I say 'quasi' because the objects are distributed at random and do not 
provide coherent figural unity). In other words, each of the first 
individual numbers up to perhaps seven or eight, is represented by 
a separate matrix — its associative connotations — and a perceptual 
analyser-code which enables us to recognize 'fiveness' directly, at a 
glance. The analyser probably works by scanning, as in the perception 
of triangles and squares; but this process is automatic and unconscious, 
as opposed to conscious counting. 

Thus the first 'personalized' number-concepts 'do not constitute a 
homogeneous series, and are quite unsuited to the simplest logical or 
mathematical operation'. 21 Those first operations are, apparently, 
carried out not by counting, but by matching the collection of objects 
to be counted against 'model collections' of pebbles, notches cut into 
a stick, knots made in a string, and above all the fingers and toes. The 
'model collections' are usually those to which the individual number- 
concept originally referred. The earliest model collections seem to have 
been pebbles; 'to calculate' is derived from calculus, meaning pebble; 
to tally, from talea, cutting. Relics of other model-collections abound 
in our weights and measures: feet, yards, furlongs, chains, bushels, 
rods. The Ayepones in Australia hunt wild horses; when they return 
from an excursion nobody asks them how many horses they have 
caught but 'How much space will they occupy?'. Even Xerxes counted 
his army by this method — at least, if we are to believe Herodotus: 

All the fleet, being now arrived at Doriscus, was brought by its 
captains at Xerxes* command to the beach near Doriscus . . . and 
hauled up for rest. In the meanwhile, Xerxes numbered his army at 



024 THE ACT OF CREATION 

Doriscus. What the number of each part of it was I cannot with exact- 
ness say, for there is no one who tells us that; but the count of the 
whole land army showed it to be a million and seven hundred 
thousand. The numbering was done as follows: a myriad [10,000] 
men were collected in one place, and when they were packed 
together as closely as might be, a line was drawn round them; this 
being drawn, the myriad was sent away, and a wall of stone built on 
the line reaching up to a man's navel; which done, others were 
brought into the walled space, till in this way all were counted. 22 

It seems that as a general rule matching precedes counting in the 
most varied cultures. 

The next great advance was the integration of individual numbers 
into a homogeneous series — the transition from cardinal to ordinal 
numbers, from 'fiveness* to 'the fifth'. The activity of counting seems 
to originate in the spontaneous, rhythmic motor activities of the small 
child: kicking, stamping, tapping, with his hands and feet; and the 
repetitive imitation of patterned series of nonsense syllables: 'Eeny 
meeny miny mo' — a kind of pseudo-counting. Even more important 
is perhaps the spontaneous, rhythmical stretching of fingers and tapping 
with the fingers. Here was the ideal 'model collection out of which, 
in the course of something like a hundred thousand years, the skill of 
finger-counting must have emerged. Danzig 23 calls attention to a 
subde distinction: 

'In his fingers man possesses a device which permits him to pass 
imperceptibly from cardinal to ordinal number. Should he want to 
indicate that a certain collection contains four objects he will raise or 
turn down four fingers simultaneously; should he want to count the 
same collection he will raise or turn down these fingers in succession. 
In the £ist case he is using his fingers as a cardinal model, in the second 
as an ordinal system. Unmistakable traces of this origin of counting are 
found in practically every primitive language.' A fascinating account 
of counting methods in primitive societies can be found in Levy- 
Bruhl, How Natives Think (1926, Chapter V). 

I have tried to re-trace the first two steps at the base of the mathe- 
matical hierarchy. The first was the slow and hesitant abstraction of 
individual number concepts from the concrete objects to which they 
relate; the second was the abstraction of the sequential relation between 
numbers, which establishes the basic rule of the mathematical game: 
counting. A posteriori it would seem that the road now lay open to the 



LEARNING TO THINK 



62$ 



logical deduction of the whole body of the theory of numbers; in fact 
each advance required the exercise of creative imagination, jumping 
over hurdles, following up crazy hunches, and overcoming mental 
blocks. Centuries of stagnation alternated with periods of explosive 
progress; discoveries were forgotten and re-discovered; within the 
same individual, brilliant insights could be followed by protracted 
snowblindness. It took several hundred years until the Hindu inven- 
tion of zero was accepted in Christian Europe; Kepler detested and 
never accepted the 'coss' — i.e. algebraic notation; his teacher Maestlin 
showed the same hostility towards Napier's logarithms. Progress in 
the apparently most rational of human pursuits was achieved in a 
highly irrational manner, epitomized by Gauss' 'I have had my solu- 
tions for a long time, but I do not yet know how I am to arrive at 
them'. The mind, owing to its hierarchic organization, functions on 
several levels at once, and often one level does not know what the 
other is doing; the essence of the creative act is bringing them together. 



The Dawn of Logic 

Let us turn to the genesis of logical codes — and take as an example the 
so-called law of contradiction in its post-Kantian formulation: A is 
not not-A. To disregard this law used to be considered as a mortal 
sin against rationality; chief among the sinners were primitives and 
children, with their notorious imperviousness to contradiction — plus 
all of us who dream at night being A and not-A in a single breath. 

Now in order to tell A from not-A, I must discriminate between 
them. Once I have discriminated between them 'A is not not-A' be- 
comes tautologous, and you cannot sin against a tautology. But dis- 
crimination, as we saw, is a function of relevance. Functionally irrele- 
vant differences between experiences may go either entirely unnoticed, 
or may be noticed but not retained, or they may be implicidy retained 
without arousing the need for explicit discriminatory responses, verbal 
or otherwise. 

Once upon a time I had a sheep farm in North Wales, and my 
Continental friends kept addressing their letters to: Bwylch Ocyn, 
Blaenau Ffestiniog, near Penrhyndeudraeth, England. The postman, 
a Gaelic patriot, was much aggrieved. Had he consulted Lord Russell 
(who was my neighbour and lived in Llan Ffestiniog), he would no 
doubt have learned that since Wales is not-England and Ffestiniog 



626 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



is Wales, it followed that foreigners had a pre-logical mentality and 
were unable to understand the law of contradiction. Thus, if the criteria 
of relevance of X, determined by X's patterns of motivation, values, 
and knowledge, are significantly different from Y's, then Y's behaviour 
must necessarily appear to X as irrational and 'indifferent to contra- 
diction. Hence the mass of misinterpretations which missionaries have 
put on the mentality of primitives, and grownups on the mental world 
of the child. 

To the primitive mind the most significant relations between per- 
sons, objects, and events are of magical character; in totemistic societies 
the existence of a magic link is assumed between members of the 
group and the totem. The Bororo tribe in northern Brazil, whose 
totem animal is the red arara, a kind of parakeet, affirm that they are 
red araras. Naturally, the Bororo can see the difference between a 
red bird and his fellow tribesman; but when referring to his conviction 
that both participate in a mystic unity, the difference between them is 
treated as irrelevant— just as the child who calls all pointed things 'nose', 
chooses to ignore the difference between noses and shoes as irrele- 
vant for its purpose. The difference between primitive and modern 
mentality is not that the former is indifferent to contradiction, but that 
statements which appear as contradictory to one, do not appear so to 
the other, because each mentality abstracts and discriminates along 
different dimensions of experience or 'gradients of relevance', deter- 
mined by different motivations. This applies not only to so-called 
^^1^' cultures (which, of course, are often far from primitive). 
European thought in the Middle Ages, and Aristotelian physics in 
particular, appear to us full of glaringly evident self-contradictions. 
The same applies to the philosophical systems of Buddhism and 
Hinduism, which do not discriminate between object and subject, 
perceiver and perceived, and in which the value of the discriminatory 
act itself is discredited by the dogma of the unity of opposites. 24 Vice 
versa, if we tried to see ourselves through the eyes of a Buddhist or 
medieval Christian, our notion that random events exert a decisive 
influence on an ordered and lawful universe would appear as self- 
contradictory. To them — as to the pre-Socratians — apparent coin- 
cidences were the vital gaps in the trivial web of physical causation 
through which the deus ex machine manifested its will; these gaps caused 
a kind of porousness in the texture of reality through which destiny 
could infiltrate. In the modern European s universe, our critics would 
say, the figure-background relation in the porous texture is reversed. 



LEARNING TO THINK 



627 



In the magic world of the child, physical causation and abstract 
categories play an equally subordinate and uncertain part, and cannot 
be regarded as a test for contradiction. When a child makes contradic- 
tory statements, for instance, 'the sun is alive because it gives light' 
and 'the sun is not alive because it has no blood', this is simply due to 
the fact that the word 'alive' was learned before the concept of aliveness 
was formed; it is a case, as so often found at that age, of a symbol in 
search of a referent. Piaget, from whose experiments with a child of nine 
I have been quoting, emphasized that children are apt to forget their 
previous judgements and then give a contradictory one. Yet obviously 
the word 'alive' is used on each of the two occasions with a different 
meaning, based on different criteria: in the first case on the discrimina- 
tion between hot and cold bodies (A and not- A), in the second between 
bodies with and without blood (B and not-B). Thus there is no contra- 
diction between the two statements, only confusion regarding the mean- 
ing of the word 'alive'; what the child intended to say was: 'the sun is 
alive in so far as it is hot, but not alive in so far as it has no blood*. Implicit 
discrimination between contrasting alternatives is often blurred in the 
explicit statements of the child owing to its linguistic inexperience. 

The child's attitude to its experiences is discriminatory within its 
framework of relevant relations, and its apparent contradictions are 
due partly to the fact that its scales of relevant values are different from 
the adult's, partly to the inadequacy of its symbolic equipment. But 
although the child experiences certain facts and relations as mutually 
exclusive and reacts accordingly, the relational concept of 'contradic- 
tion itself is only abstracted at a much later stage of development; 
just as the child uses names before the name-thing relation as such is 
abstracted. 

There seem to be three stages in the emergence of the 'law of con-» 
tradiction. The first is training the child to respond to the commands 
'Yes' and 'No' and their equivalents; the second is the child's use of 
these symbols as levers to control the actions of others; the third is the 
use of 'Yes' and 'No' with reference to verbal activities. Stern's daughter 
used the word *Nein at eighteen months in answer to the question, 
'Shall we take Hilde away?'. But when she was asked 'Is this a doggie?* 
while the wrong animal was shown her, she remained silent, then 
echoed 'doggie*. Four months later, however, she began to contradict 
a wrong name by substituting the right one; and another two months 
later — at two years—she firmly said 'No' in denial of blatantly false 
verbal statements. 



628 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Thus we see that the principle of contradiction is applied to sym- 
bolic activities precisely at the stage where symbolic relations as such 
become relevant to the child and call out discriminatory reactions. 
Once this stage has been reached the child uses 'No' not only to prevent 
undesirable action, but to reject incorrect symbolic propositions. This 
new verbal device is for the child a source of satisfaction comparable 
to the discovery of the naming game. It is expressed by the frequent 
use of antithetic statements which are characteristic for this age; three- 
year-olds delight in phrases which sound as if they had been borrowed 
from the Proverbs of Solomon: 'I am fast runner, not slow runner', 
*I not old boy, new boy', etc. The use of such paired antithetic state- 
ments marks the beginning of the process of abstracting the relation of 
mutual exclusion as such, foEowed by the other, now familiar, stages: 
the gradual downing of the generalized relation; the implicit grasp of 
the principle; and finally its explicit naming — though this last stage 
may never be reached. But regardless of whether or not the subject is 
able to give a verbal definition of it, the principle of the mutual ex- 
clusion of opposites. previously discriminated as such, will enter as an 
important rule of the game into all matrices of rational thought. 

Thus the so-called 'laws of thought' in traditional logic are, from 
the point of view of developmental psychology, merely the explicit 
formulations of implicit relations, abstracted by the usual procedures 
characteristic for all forms of learning. We may say that the principle 
of contradiction exists a priori in the organization of the nervous 
system, because the power to discriminate is built into that organiza- 
tion, and contradiction is merely an epi-phenomenon of discrimina- 
tion. But we may also say that our judgements of what is a contradic- 
tion and what is not are empirically derived, because the gradients of 
relevance along which abstraction and discrimination proceed, are 
subjective and differ according to individual and culture. 

But this subjectivity does not detract from the great power which 
the principle of contradiction exercises over the mind. And not only 
over the human mind; the experimental neuroses which Pavlov in- 
duced in his dogs testifies to it. The dog is trained to discriminate 
circles, or nearly circular ellipses, from flat ellipses, the former sig- 
nalling food, the latter 'no food'. So long as the two types of signals 
are comfortably distinguishable from each other, the dog shows no 
sign of strain. But when intermediary forms are shown which could 
be interpreted as belonging to one class or its opposite, experimental 
neurosis sets in: the dog goes wild, then becomes apathetic, and 



LEARNING TO THINK 



629 



seems to lose altogether its power of discrimination; it goes emotionally 
and intellectually to pieces. One might say that the dog has lost con- 
fidence in a world in which the law of the excluded middle has ceased 
to operate, and A is no longer not not-A. 

It appears that dogs are not only emotionally more stable and loyal, 
but also more orthodox logicians than their masters. For the powers of 
discriminatory judgement are more diluted on the level of symbolic 
thought than in perception; and when thought is dominated by emo- 
tion and faith, the Red and White Queens always score agamst reason- 
able Alice, who asserts that 'One cant believe impossible things'; 
whereas the White Queen, after a little practice, managed to believe 'as 
many as six impossible things before breakfast'. 

Which is, all things considered, quite a modest estimate. 

NOTE 

To p. 613. Once upon a time Lashlcy and Wade (1946) tried to make a 
distinction 'between the "so-called generalization" which means only a failure to 
observe differences and the generalization which involves perception of both 
similarities and differences. The amorphous figure, lacking in identity, is genera- 
lized in the first sense only/ The quotation is from Hebb (1949, p. 27), who 
seemed to share Lashley's view, although Lashley himself later dropped the 
distinction. The 'amorphous figure' in the quotation refers to 'an irregular mass 
of colour or a pattern of intersecting lines drawn at random*. Being amorphous 
it does jper definitionem lack identity, i.e., the prerequisites for the formation of an 
object-concept; but it is nevertheless seen as some kind of figure on a background 
that is discriminated. In fact, abstraction without discrimination is a contradiction 
in terms. The abstracted quality — whether 'nose*, 'dolly', or 'sound of the tuning 
fork' is always differentiated from non-nose and non-dolly and no-sound. (If 
the sound of the tuning fork is very weak, it will approach the limen of no-sound; 
about the effect of simple gradients of intensity, see Hebb (1958), p. 189; about 
pitch and octave gradients, see Osgood, op. cit., p. 361. Since perception of in- 
tensity, pitch, etc. is part of the animal's perceptual organization, they must 
influence the functioning of the analyser-codes.) 



XVI 



SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 

Multi-Dimensionality 




n the preceding chapter we have discussed the processes by which 
the rules of the game of symbolic thought are acquired; let us 
. now turn to adult thinking and problem-solving. 



Thinking is a multi-dimensional affair. The Sterns recorded all the 
questions asked by their little daughter in the course of four days; 
but the record gives us only the scantiest pointers to what went on in 
the child's head. Perhaps one day a super-EEG will be constructed, 
which will record all the thoughts — or at least all verbalized thoughts 
— which the stream of consciousness carries through the subject's 
wired skull; yet even such a record, far more complete than anything 
James Joyce could dream of, would be but a poor pointer to the multi- 
dimensional patterns underlying the linear stream. The oscillating 
curve on the gramophone record needs a human auditory system to 
yield all the information it contains. The super-EEG would record 
larger units of information — entire words; but it would still need a 
psychoanalyst or a Joyce-interpreter to divine the meaning behind the 
meaning: the connotations of individual words, their unconscious 
echoes, the motivation behind it all, the rules of the patient's game, 
hidden to himself, and the memories which crop up as landmarks in 
his internal, mental environment. 

We must nevertheless try to sort out some of the dimensional 
variables in this immensely complex, multi-dimensional activity; 
these variables will then yield gradients of different kinds; for instance: 

(1) Degrees of consciousness; 

(2) Degrees of verbalization; 

(3) Degrees of abstraction; 

(4) Degrees of flexibility; 

630 



SOME ASPECTS OP THINKING 



6 3 I 



(5) Type and intensity of motivation; 

(6) Realistic versus autistic thought; 

(7) Dominance of outer or inner environment; 

(8) Learning and performing; 

(9) Routine and originality. 

Each of these headings has been repeatedly discussed in various 
contexts in various chapters. Most of them cut across the conventional 
classifications of thought such as 'associative' versus 'directional'. All 
variables are inter-dependent. 

Now if variables depend on each other, there must be a function 
which defines their iriter-dependence — a rule of the game. The question: 
'If y = £(x) and at is 7, how much is y? is meaningless unless I define £ 
Similarly, if in the experimental laboratory the subject is given the 
stimulus word: S = 'big' and is asked for the 'response', the question 
is meaningless unless f is defined as 'synonyms' or 'opposites' or 
'rhymes', or whatever game is to be played. 

One of the main contentions of this book is that organic life, in 
all its manifestations, from morphogenesis to symbolic thought, is 
governed by 'rules of the game' which lend it coherence, order, and 
unity-in-variety; and that these rules (or functions in the mathe- 
matical sense), whether innate or acquired, are represented in coded 
form on various levels, from the chromosomes to the structures in 
the nervous system responsible for symbolic thought. The codes are 
assumed to function on the trigger-release principle, so that a relatively 
simple signal-pattern releases complex, pre-set action-patterns, as the 
referee's whistle initiates or stops the activities of the football players. 
The rules are fixed, but there are endless variations to each game, their 
variability increasing in ascending order; this lends elasticity to habit, 
and gives rise to the subjective experience of freedom of choice between 
alternate possibilities of action. There is also an overall-rule of the 
game, which says that no rule is absolutely final; that under certain 
circumstances they may be altered and combined into a more sophisti- 
cated game, which provides a higher form of unity and yet increased 
variety; this is called the subject's creative. potential. 

Faced with the imaginary EEG record of the patient's stream of 
thoughts, the only way of interpreting it would be to find out what 
game the patient is playing at any moment, and why. This actually 
is the procedure of the free-association method in psychotherapy: the 
patient's words provide the record, and his dreams, it is hoped, will 



632 THE ACT OF CREATION 

provide the interpretation of the underlying patterns of his individual 
matrices of thought. We follow, as we saw earlier on, similar methods 
in perceptual analysis: the sequence of pressure-variations reaching the 
ear-drum must be dismantled, analysed, and reassembled if we want 
to get at the underlying patterns of timbre, melody, and speech. The 
stream of sounds, like the stream of thoughts, yields its meaning only 
if the percipient knows the rules of the game. 

The Experience of Free Choice 

Let us consider some of the dimensions of thinking listed on pp. 630-1. 
Regarding consciousness I proposed to make a distinction between the 
'linear scale* of awareness on the one hand, and hierarchic levels of 
consciousness on the other (Book One, VII, VIII). The former was to 
be regarded as a continuous gradient extending from completely self- 
regulatory physiological processes, through more or less automatized 
skills, to peripheral, and lastly, focal, awareness of events; the latter to 
be represented by quasi-parallel layers of mental organization — 
comparable to geological strata — which are discontinuous and governed 
by codes formed at different stages of phylogenetic and ontogenetic 
development. All this has been discussed at length in the previous 
volume, and need not be recapitulated; but I must append two 
additional points. 

The first concerns 'linear* awareness. I have described, somewhat 
perversely, awareness as that dimension of experience which diminishes 
and shrinks away with the progressive automatization of a skill. For 
'awareness* is an irreducible term, a black box like that other which 
contains the power of organic life to extract energy and information 
from its environment — and, in fact, continuous with the latter. On 
the other hand, the progressive automatization of motor skills, per- 
ceptual skills, verbal and mathematical skills, is an observable and to 
some extent even measurable factor of behaviour — epitomized on its 
lowest level by sensory habituation. Thus by expressing awareness by 
the inverse ratio of the automatization of the ongoing process, a certain 
strategic advantage is gained. Other things being equal (i.e. under 
stablized environmental conditions), automatization manifests itself 
in predictable, stereotyped performance, where the matrix has no 
degrees of freedom left for strategic decisions, because these are made 
by pre-set feedback controls, and do not require the attention of 



SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 



higher centres. Conversely, the less automatized the skill, the greater 
the freedom of choice between alternatives, to be decided on higher 
levels according to more complex feedbacks — 'loops within loops' — 
from the outer and inner environment. Thus the logic of the argument 
led first to a negative criterion of awareness as the reciprocal of habit- 
formation, and now to the positive criterion of awareness as being 
directly proportional to the degrees of freedom of the centre control- 
ling the activity to make alternative choices, based on its estimate of 
the lie of the land. We must assume that the higher in the hierarchy 
the centre is placed, the more vivid will be the subject's experience of 
his 'freedom of choice'. Freedom of the will is a metaphysical question 
outside the scope of this book; but considered as a subjective datum 
of experience, Tree will' is the awareness of alternative choices. 



Degrees of Self-Awareness 

The above was related to degrees of awareness on the continuous, 
'linear' gradient. The second addendum relates to the hierarchic levels 
of consciousness. At any moment of our existence, we carry on activi- 
ties on various levels, simultaneously and more or less independently 
from each: we breathe, metabolize, drive the car, and talk to the passen- 
gers all at the same time, 'in parallel' as it were. 

But there are moments when a person perceives what he is doing 
from a bird's eye view as it were; from a parallel' level of conscious- 
ness which is not at all involved in the activity in hand. Take a simple 
example: you are absorbed in a game of chess; you concentrate on a 
stratagem to defeat your opponent. You look up for a moment to 
light a cigarette, and at that moment your awareness jumps to another 
plane, as it were; you say to yourself 'what fun I am having playing 
chess with old Henry on a Sunday afternoon'. Then you go back to 
your game. It was a brief break-through from the activity in hand to 
the contemplation of that activity from an upstairs balcony — a vertical 
shift of awareness which enabled you to look down at the top of your 
own head. To put it in a different way, attention has been displaced 
from the object of the ongoing activity to the subject engaged in 
carrying it out — that elusive entity, the self. 

It is a paradox as old as Achilles and the Tortoise, that the subject 
who is aware can never become the object of his awareness; at best he 
can, if so inclined, achieve successive approximations which form a 



634 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



convergent series. One may call this the paradox of the dog at dinner. 
The dog is eating his dinner; the wagging of his tail indicates that he is 
enjoying himself; but does he know that he is enjoying himself? . . . 
A little boy is watching a Western on the TV screen. He is enjoying 
himself. He knows perhaps that he is enjoying himself. Does he know 
that he knows? . . . The philosopher is thinking of a problem. He is 
aware that he is thinking of this problem. Is he aware that he is aware, 

etc ? The known is always one step ahead of the knower, and they 

chase each other up a spiral staircase, as it were. In Craik's terminology 
one might say that the model can never make a complete model of 
itself.* Regarding verbal models in particular, we have seen (pp. 592 £F.) 
that verbal statements are initiated by unverbalized intentions on higher 
levels, so that we again arrive at a receding series. This seems to indi- 
cate that the mind-body problem is not amenable to any solution in 
explicit, verbal terms. 

On the other hand, the fact that the subject who is aware can never- 
theless become, to some extent, the object of his own awareness, is of 
course of outstanding importance in mental life. Animals, apparently 
from planaria onwards, display attention and expectancy which indicate 
varying degrees of 'linear* awareness; primates, as well as domestic 
pets, may also have some rudiments of self-awareness. But the many- 
layered hierarchies of man, and particularly his symbolic hierarchies, 
place him on a lonely peak, and impose on him the impossible com- 
mand to 'know thyself'. Awareness of awareness is a tantalizing gift; 
and 'I think therefore I exist' is a hopeful beginning. But the end, the 
identification of the knower and the known, which alone would 
constitute complete consciousness of existence, though always in 
sight, is never achieved. The successive forms of self-identification, 
starting from the child's fluid world of experience which knows as yet 
no firm boundary between self and not-self, can be likened to a mathe- 
matical series converging towards unity, or to a spiral curve converg- 
ing towards a centre which it will only reach after an infinite number 
of involutions. 

The aim of certain mystic practices — such as Hatha Yoga — is to 
permeate the self with awareness of itself by gaining voluntary control 
over visceral processes and isolated muscles. It would seem that this 
focussing of consciousness on the self, the inward core of the contrac- 
ting spiral, is the direct opposite of the self-transcending aspirations of 
other schools of mysticism — the expansion of consciousness in an un- 
folding spiral, and its final dissolution in the 'oceanic feeling'. In fact, 



SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 



635 



however, the Yogi's effort to gain conscious mastery of the body is 
considered as merely a detour towards attaining 'pure consciousness* 
— that is, 'consciousness without object or content other than conscious- 
ness itself '.Thus turned upon itself, pure consciousness is supposed to 
penetrate the Real Self— which, unlike the transient self, is part and 
parcel of the Atman, the universal spirit. 1 Both methods, therefore, 
each with a long historical ancestry, share the same ultimate aim — 
situated at the point where opposites meet; after all, as the bright little 
boy said, 'the infinite is where tilings happen which don't*. 

'Self-awareness', in the sense of the preceding paragraphs, has of 
course nothing to do with 'self-consciousness' in the sense of gauchery, 
stage-fright. The latter is our old friend, the paradox of the centipede 
— the disorganization of behaviour which results when higher centres 
interfere with the autonomous functioning of parts on lower levels. 
'Self-consciousness', used in this sense, is a typically English coinage; 
it provides an amusing and rather revealing contrast to the equally 
malapropos German coinage ' Selbstbewusstsein — meaning self-con- 
fident, conscious of one's own value. As for the French, faithful to 
the Cartesian spirit, they use conscience to designate both conscious- 
ness and moral conscience. 



Master-Switches and Releasers 

Motivation has been discussed in Chapter VIII. It determines what 
kind of game the subject will engage in, and activates the proper codes. 
If he feels the need to build castles in Spain, day-dreaming will replace 
the routines of planning ahead. The rules of day-dreaming impose a 
minimum of restraints and leave a vast choice of strategies to reach 
the desired goal, wish-fulfilment. Thus even day-dreaming is 'goal- 
directed', but the direction of thought is determined by emotional 
gradients, not by a concrete target. 

At the opposite end of the motivational spectrum are activities like 
problem-solving, governed by complex and precise rules. The goal 
to be reached is sharply defined, but has in itself no emotional sig- 
nificance; the reward is not contained in the target but in the act of 
reaching it. Some textbooks make a distinction between 'associative* 
and 'directive' thinking; but directiveness in the sense described is 
present even in the daydream, and controlled association enters into 
problem-solving; the difference is one of degree. Similar considerations 



636 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



apply to other classifications: abstract — concrete, realistic — autistic, 
etc. 

Most ordinary thinking is of a mixed kind; it may pursue a set 
directional course for a while, according to strict rules, then go off at a 
tangent and drift along, until some higher centre enters into action, 
and discipline is restored. We have discussed these general aspects of 
ideation before; it remains to consider briefly some specific patterns 
of verbal thought. 

At the base of all hierarchies which enter into our universes of dis- 
course operate the implicit sub-codes of grammar and syntax; 'im- 
plicit' because they are automatized and we are not aware of their 
functioning. Lashley's dictum on perception is equally applicable to 
speaking and listening: 'We are aware of an organized structure; the 
organizing is never experienced.' The rules which determine how 
thoughts are put into words cannot themselves be put into words 
— except by the patient labours of logicians and semanticists to 'break 
the code*. 

Next come the rules of common sense or common-or-garden logic, 
which are also empirically acquired, abstracted relations — codified 
modus operandi which the majority of people are no more able to define 
than they can define how they ride a bicycle. But as we move upward, 
towards more specific universes of discourse, the codes, too, become 
more explicit. 

The simplest examples of explicit codes are the verbal commands in 
word-association tests, e.g.: name opposites!'. The experimenter 
then says 'dark', and the answer 'light' pops out promptly, as if pro- 
duced by a slot-machine — although in a free-association test the sub- 
ject would probably associate 'dark' with 'night' rather than with 
'light', and 'hot' with 'Italy' rather than with 'cold'. Thus the verbal 
command 'opposites* has acted as a master-switch, as it were, which 
changed the entire pattern of verbal organization. Even more striking 
is what happens to my verbal matrices si je continue de developer ma 
pensie en francais—i£ I continue to develop my argument, but use 
French words and French grammar to express it. My line of thinking 
has remained the same (or almost entirely so) but that single command- 
word 'French' has triggered off an instant reorganization affecting 
millions of neurons and their mode of inter-action. Not only has the 
vocabulary been changed, but also the method of converting ideas into 
syntactic language-units according to the sub-codes of French grammar. 

I do not want to go into neuro-physiology, but let us note that the 



SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 



<537 



model of the telephone-switchboard plugging into another localized 
'language-area* simply will not do. Let us return for a moment to word- 
association tests. 'Light-dark', 'hot-cold' are primitive examples of 
matrices governed by codes with a single parameter in semantic space. 
Even so, are we to assign, by analogy with the 'language-areas', 
different cortical territories to operations controlled by the commands 
'opposites', 'synonyms', 'super-ordinate class', etc.; not to mention 
'inter-polation', 'extra-polation', and the mighty hierarchies of 
symbolic logic or of mathematical operations? Moreover, if the 
command is again 'opposites', and the stimulus-word 'Napoleon; or if 
the command is 'supraordinate class' in the species-genus game, and the 
stimulus-word nail' or 'birth' — what is the 'correct' response? Seman- 
tic space is multi-dimensional and cannot be represented by purely 
spatial connections activated by all-or-nothing signals in the three- 
dimensional rind of the brain; a model must include at least specific 
signals (e.g. frequency modulation pulses) and chemical (RNA) 
changes in the neurons to account for selectivity of response. 2 

In all controlled associations and symbolic operations we again find 
a principle confirmed which we found operating on all levels — namely, 
that a relatively simple 'releaser' signal from higher quarters fopposites' 
'speak French', 'find the square root of. . .') triggers off the operation 
of a complex code — a whole universe of discourse in fact, with a 
hierarchy of implicit sub-codes, and a flexible strategy. (Even to find 
an 'opposite' to the word hairpin requires complex operations governed 
by individual 'strategies', perhaps involving visual images — a process 
continuous with problem-solving). The trigger-releaser may be a 
verbal or visual, or even chemical command — a tumblerful of gin or 
an amphetamin tablet: yet look what remarkably new rules of the 
game are triggered off by them.* 



Explicit Rules and Implicit Codes 

The implicit codes of grammar and syntax were, as we saw, acquired 
empirically 'as the gypsy learns to fiddle'. But the rules which govern 
more advanced symbolic skills — mathematics or chemistry, or Law — 
are learned in explicit verbal form. They may be acquired by rote- 
learning, or by guided learning, but at some stage they must be stated 
in explicit form. Take an example from elementary algebra: the 
average student learning the rule for solving quadratic equations: 



638 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



x lt 2= — p/2± sj p 2 /4.—q. For the next few days or weeks, every 
time he has to use the formula, he must look it up in his textbook (or, 
if he is very brilliant, derive it afresh). At this stage of the learning pro- 
cess the formula is not yet an automatically functioning rule of the 
game; it is not yet a 'code' impressed on his nervous system. But after 
some practice, a single glance at an expression of the form x 2 -\-px-\- 
q =o will tell him that it is a member of the matrix of quadratic equa- 
tions and trigger off the rule — by now an automatized code — for 
solving it. 

Thus rules which at first have to be looked up, or reconstructed by 
a conscious effort, become codified and automatized by routine. It is 
irrelevant in this particular context whether the student has by now 
forgotten the derivation of the formula and merely uses it as a mechani- 
cal gimmick; or whether he is aware of its binomial ancestry. This 
makes a vast difference in terms of understanding, but need not affect 
the process of automatization. 

I have emphasized before that the term 'code* is used in this book 
not in the metaphorical way in which Freud, for instance, used the 
word 'censor', but to refer to concrete processes or patterns of organi- 
zation in the central nervous system. However, it sounds somehow 
more plausible to attribute physiological reality to codes on lower 
levels of the organic hierarchy—the genetic code, the codes of instinct- 
behaviour and sensory-motor skills — than to claim that the rules of 
such esoteric games as non-Euclidian geometry or quantum mechanics 
are physiologically represented, by appropriate coding methods, in the 
nervous system, and can be triggered off by simple releasers (such as 
the command 'let's talk shop'). I must therefore underline once more 
that the term code' is meant to apply only to those rules of behaviour 
which govern established routines and function automatically with- 
out conscious effort. In the initial stages of learning a complex symbolic 
skill, the rules of the game (laws, theorems, mathematical or chemical 
formulae) must be constantly memorized, looked up, or consciously 
recalled; so long as this is the case they are not yet incorporated into 
the physico-mental organization and are not to be called 'codes'. 
Codes are only those fixed stable rules which, once switched on, 
automatically govern the thinking routine. The problem in problem- 
solving consists firstly in discovering which routine is appropriate to 
the problem— what type of game is to be played; and secondly, how to 
play it— Le. which strategy to follow, which members of the flexible 
matrix are to be brought into play according to the lie of the land. 



SOME ASPECTS OP THINKING 



<*39 



We learn, or discover, with strenuous effort, a new method of 
thinking; after a while, with practice, the novelty changes into semi- 
automatized routine, based on an invariant code with an adaptable 
matrix, and is incorporated into our repertory of habits. It is astonish- 
ing how soon, once a new railroad is built across desert and mountains, 
the passenger-trains start running on schedule. 

But the process of habit-formation does not stop^there: not only the 
rules of the newly learnt game become soon automatized to such an 
extent that it becomes increasingly difficult to go against them, but 
strategy, too, tends to become stereotyped and incorporated into the 
code. Take progress in chess, an example I have mentioned before. The 
beginner is uncertain about the rules; then the rules become automatic 
codes and it becomes almost impossible for him to move his men in 
impermissible ways; after protracted practice certain tactical prin- 
ciples, which are no longer 'rules' in the formal sense, also begin to 
operate automatically in his mind — e.g. to avoid pins, to seek open 
rook-files. But this reification of tactical pseudo-rules into auto- 
matized sub-codes contains a mortal danger, because considerations 
of strategy on a higher level demand that each of these tactical rules 
should be broken if the occasion warrants it. Sacrifices in material, 
and moves which look cockeyed (that is: positionally unsound), are 
signs of combinative power, i.e. originality; the mediocre player 
always remains a slave of habit and cautious orthodoxy. 

At this point the argument merges into that of Book One (IX-XI), 
concerning the pitfalls of orthodoxy, over-specialization, and one- 
sided development in the history of science and philosophy. In biology 
or theoretical physics there are no clean-cut distinctions between 
canonical rules of the game and heuristic rules of strategy and tactics. 
We are inclined to believe, as popular books on science tell us, that the 
'permissible moves' are laid down for ever by the laws of formal 
logic and the criteria forjudging evidence; and that strategy is deter- 
mined only by the lie of the land, that is, the data of observation. In 
fact, however, the rules turn out to be infiltrated with implicit assump- 
tions and 'self-evident axioms' which as often as not are specious contra- 
band; and the empirical strategies are often weighted by a stubborn 
adherence to methods of interpretation and biassed techniques, pro- 
moted to canonical status. Habit is heir to originality; without the 
hierarchies of organized habits life would be chaos; creativity means 
breaking up habits and joining the fragments into a new synthesis. 



Matrix Categories 



I have tried to outline the hierarchic organization of levels of under- 
standing, levels of consciousness, and levels of habit and flexibility — 
the last ranging from implicitly acquired codes, through the master- 
switches of controlled association, to the explicitly learned rules and 
pseudo-rules in the universes of discourse of science and philosophy. 
To avoid giving undue dominance to the abstractive hierarchies in the 
mental landscape, I must briefly mention some different types of 
language matrices — without aspiring at anything like a complete 
catalogue. 

Phonetic matrices (of rhythm, meter, alliteration, assonance, rhyme, 
and euphony) do not properly belong to symbolic thought, though 
they interact with it not only in poetry and word-games but also 
in ordinary discourse, often more persistently than we are aware of. 

Chronological matrices, naively regarded, seem to be linear chains of 
events, but are of course nothing of the sort. They are multi-dimen- 
sional structures in semantic space, governed by a diversity of selective 
codes, whose criteria of relevance are often quite indifferent to tem- 
poral order. This applies to personal memories, which always unfold 
within specific frames of reference, but also to written History: 
historians organize their material according to highly idiosyncratic 
rules for sifting and interpreting evidence, and for constructing causa- 
tive theories. 

Classijicatory codes in taxinomy, indexing systems and in certain 
branches of mathematical logic are hierarchic par excellence but rigid; 
they resemble stone pyramids in the mental landscape. 

Dogmatic matrices could be described as closed systems with dis- 
torted feedback and impaired sub-skills of reasoning. They are ruled by 
a fixed code derived from an act of faith, a circular argument, or 
supposedly self-evident axioms. In other respects, however, they are 
remarkably adaptable, and their dialectical strategies are of great 
subdety. Related to these are frames of value which determine ethical 
or aesthetic judgements or attitudes, and emotion-dominated matrices 
which need not be discussed as a separate category, since emotion 
enters in various guises and intensities into all form of thought. 

Lastly, 'style codes' represent a person's idiosyncrasies, mannerisms, 
etc., which, in their ensemble, constitute his individuality. Gait, 
gesture, v6ice, hand-writing are all governed by stable automatic 
codes. If a person, deprived by accident of the use of his right hand, 

640 



SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 

learns to write with the left, his signature, before long, recovers its 
true character, 'Even the suspicious bank clerk will cash his cheque 
because the old form of signature returns/ wrote Penfielcl, 3 who had 
several such patients. 'The pattern of the signature and of the writing 
is in the brain, not in the hand.' 

This applies, to a considerable extent, even to the style of writing. 
Hemingway or Proust can be identified — and parodied — after reading 
a few lines— as you identify the timbre of a drum or violin after a few 
transients. Even the language of common mortals whose style is 
undistinguished and seemingly indistinguishable, appears to have fixed 
characteristic ratios — .e.g. between the number of adjectives to verbs. 

The total matrix, which comprises all these frames of behaviour, con- 
stitutes the personality structure. But even here, the code can apparently 
be triggered on and off by some super-master-switch — as the spec- 
tacular cases of multiple personalities indicate. Once more the hier- 
archy fades into a receding series. 

NOTES 

To p. 634. Cyberneticists have discussed at length models which are supposed 
to be capable of this feat. But they have no bearing on the question of awareness. 

To p. 637. A summary of earlier work on controlled association tests, and 
the controversies around it (e.g. complex theory versus constellation theory) can 
be found e.g. in Woodworth (1939), pp. 790-800. 



XVII 



ASSOCIATION 

'Multiple Attunements 

A ssociationism is dead, but association remains one of the funda- 
A-\ mental facts of mental life. So far I have considered mental 
JL Jl organization chiefly in its 'vertical' aspect — hierarchic struc- 
tures formed by abstractive processes in ascending series. But each 
verbal concept, apart from being a member of a 'vertical' hierarchy, 
is also a member of several connotative matrices, each of which could 
be represented by an inclined plane. The concept's place in the vertical, 
abstractive hierarchy provides the dictionary definition — as far as 
that goes — of its meaning. But the concept as a psychological reality, 
its aura of connotations, and its individual significance to the person 
•who actually uses it, is determined by the multitude of matrices which 
intersect in it. Each of them provides an associative context governed 
by a, selective code; and the more there are of these inclined planes in 
semantic space the richer and more multi-dimensional the concept. 

If concepts are to be regarded as atoms of thought, they are certainly 
not the hard lumps of classical physics. In the first place, they are un- 
stable and subject to change — to change both in definition and in 
connotation. My concept of a 'gene* or a 'seductress', or of 'President 
Eisenhower' is certainly not the same as it was ten years ago, though 
the verbal label attached to each of these concepts has remained the 
same. It is strange to reflect that a major part of our scientific and 
philosophical vocabulary consists of old Greek bottles filled and re- 
filled with new wine; that electron once meant a piece of amber, and 
Homer's cosmos a flat disc covered by a vault. It is even stranger that 
the same Sanskrit root matr split, by mitosis, as it were, into maya — 
the Oriental's web of illusions, and metron, metre, the Occidental's 
yardstick to measure the world. 

A concept has as many dimensions in semantic space as there are matrices 
642 



ASSOCIATION 



<?43 



of which it is a member. Let me return for a moment to the example of 
the parlour game mentioned before, 'towns starting with M\ In 
playing that game, I write down on my list 'Madrid* — which proves 
that the concept Madrid is a member of the phonetic matrix governed 
by the code 'initial M\ Since I am bored with the game, I permit my 
thoughts to wander, and at once an image arises: the crowd at the 
Puerta del Sol stampeding in the panic of an air bombardment — and 
off we go along the emotion-charged matrix of my memories of the 
Spanish Civil War. At this moment Brenda's little girl — who was 
watching the game, equally bored — asks, 'What is Madrid?'; and I 
oblige with the information: 'Madrid is the capital of Spain and of the 
Province of Madrid, situated on the left bank of the river Manzanares, 
which falls into the river Jarama' — whereby I have produced a de- 
finition of sorts of the concept 'Madrid*. A moment later I remember 
the Prado, with its Goyas, Velasquezes, and El Grecos — which are items 
in a mental catalogue indexed under the code 'Painters', sub-code 
'Painters, Spanish' (but also under 'Spain', sub-code 'Spain, painters 
of). These connotations presented themselves more or less auto- 
matically, but now my repertory of associations is nearly exhausted, 
and my mind a momentary blank. Add to the repertory the printed 
and auditory-vocal images of the word, plus the location of the town 
on a mental map, and you get about half a dozen matrices which will 
be activated by, and which will activate, the concept 'Madrid' without 
effort. The associative contexts of a concept that are firmly estab- 
lished in a person's repertory of thought-habits, are less numerous 
than we are inclined to believe — as free association tests demonstrate. 

If, on the other hand, somebody asks me to talk about the geological 
foundations of Madrid, I shall make an embarrassed effort, and recall 
that the town stands on an undulating plateau and, by some inarticulate 
analogy, perhaps arrive at the conclusion that the soil consists chiefly 
of sand and clay. But that was an inference arrived at by the usual method 
of problem-solving, and not of a spontaneous association. My matrix 
of geological knowledge is scant; its code consists of the vague rule 
'all that is relevant to the structure of the earth's crust'. This indi- 
cates the direction in semantic space of the search for an answer; but 
since the data of knowledge are lacking, there is little firm ground 
on which to move about. 'Madrid' was not a member of my geo- 
logical matrix; after this embarrassing experience, it has been recruited 
to membership, but its ties to the matrix remain weak and tentative. 

We have seen that the concept Madrid can be activated by any of 



644 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the matrices to which it belongs (for instance 'Civil War); and vice 
versa, that any of these matrices can be activated by it. If we assign to 
each matrix, metaphorically speaking, a specific wave-length* then 
the concept may be represented as an aggregate of several oscillation- 
circuits, each of which will receive and emit on the specific 'wave- 
length' of its matrix. We may call this the 'multiple attunement' of the 
concept to the various matrices of which it is a member.* 

Now the aggregate of circuits, which is the concept, may receive 
on one wave-length and emit on another, 'Madrid* was evoked by the 
phonetic matrix 'initial M', and in its turn activated a different matrix, 
'Civil War', which functions on a different wave-length. If the matrix 
of the incoming signal is of a complex or abstract character, the 
aggregate may tend to switch over to a circuit functioning on the wave- 
length of an emotionally more appealing matrix. Thus a concept is a 
member of several clubs, but it likes some clubs more than others. 
Its 'multiple attunements' may be represented as a line-spectrum of 
frequencies with a relatively stable energy-distribution. The fre- 
quencies of maximum energy — like the dominant partials in a sound- 
spectrum — would represent the concept's 'most-preferred' associative 
contexts. As the years go by, new lines would be added to the spectrum, 
while others would fade away, and the energy-distribution of associa- 
tive preferences would change — getting mellower perhaps, like an 
old Stradivarius, or croaking, like an un-tuned piano. The effort to 
'concentrate' on an abstract problem is probably proportionate to the 
energy required to inhibit preferential associative contexts of high 
energy-potential — i.e. 'habit strength*. 

The preceding paragraphs may have given an exaggerated impres- 
sion of the subjectivity of concepts— rather on the lines of Humpty 
Dumpty's 'a word means what I intend it to mean'. The connotations of 
concepts referring to individuals or places are of course largely per- 
sonal; but on the other hand, there is experimental evidence to show 
that the associative priorities and the connotative 'aura' of concepts 
of a general character are surprisingly stable and standardized in indi- 
viduals of the same culture. 'Marbe's Law' demonstrated the existence 
of a logarithmic relation between an individual's reaction-time in giv- 
ing a certain response to a stimulus-word in an association test, and 
the frequency of the same response occurring in a group of people.** 
Osgood has invented an ingenious method of measuring 'semantic 
differentials'. The subjects were asked to assess the ratings of a concept 
— e.g. poute— on ten different graded scales: e.g. 'angular-rounded', 



ASSOCIATION 



<545 



'cold-hot', 'good-bad', 'wet-dry*. Two groups of twenty subjects 
were used, and the mean ratings of each group were then plotted and 
compared. Surprisingly enough, the two graphs were almost identical; 
even more surprising, the greatest amount of disagreement (c. fifteen 
per cent) was found in the ratings of politeness as 'good* or 'bad': one 
group thought that to be polite deserved a goodness' rating of six 
points, the other of six and a half points, on a seven-point scale. 1 

To recapitulate: a concept may be regarded as a relatively stable 
a gg re g ate or 'cluster* of receiving-transmitting circuits, with a kind 
of nuclear core: the verbal label ('madrid'). Additional circuits may 
be recruited, others may fade with disuse, and the relative energy 
potentials of the circuits may be altered by long-term processes or the 
person's momentary mood; but the auditory-vocal (and visual) trace 
of the word Madrid remains unaltered, and thus preserves the 
identity of the concept through all these changes in time. We may 
further assume that any mcoming signal, regardless through which 
circuit it is received, will activate the nuclear circuit— the auditory- 
vocal trace. If all goes well the response output will be emitted on the 
same wave-length on which the input was received, and I shall happily 
go on playing the 'towns with M' game. But since the cluster 'hangs 
together' it is likely that some amount of excitation has nevertheless 
spread to other circuits not concerned with the game — and thus caused 
the fleeting, fringe-conscious stirrings of my memories of the Civil 
War. This is a minor, permissible kind of distraction; and perhaps even 
a necessary one — without such ripples the stream of thought would be 
linear, colourless, all-too single-ininded. But if one of the circuits with 
a high energy-potential gets excited, the control centres on higher 
levels of the hierarchy must prevent it from taking over if chaos is 
not to result; i.e., the code of the 'distracting' matrix must be blocked. 
During strenuous efforts to concentrate, one seems literally to 'feel' 
inside one's head the expenditure of energy needed to suppress diver- 
sional thoughts which keep popping up like jacks-in-the-box. 'A 
great part of our fatigue', Maxwell once remarked, 'often arises, not 
from those mental efforts by which we obtain the mastery of the 
subject, but from those which are spent in recalling our wandering 
thoughts' — particularly, one may add, during a long and boring lecture; 
while the reverse phenomenon is produced by the (Hsinhibiting action 
of alcohol and drugs. All this seems to indicate that our preferential 
matrices of ideation are most of the time blocked by centres on higher 



646 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



levels — which agrees well with the predominantly restraining func- 
tion of the hierarchic controls in perceptual and motor organization. 

Types of Association 

I have used the word Association loosely, as it is nowadays mostly 
used. In Drever's Dictionary of Psychology, for instance, we find: 

'Association: used generally of the principle in accordance with 
which ideas, feelings, and movements are connected in such a way as 
to determine their succession in the mind or in the actions of an indi- 
vidual, or of the process of establishing such connections/ 

Or take Humphrey (1951): 

'The term "association", or mental association, is a general name 
often used in psychology to express the conditions under which 
mental events, whether of experience or behaviour, arise.' 2 

Hebb (1958) speaks at length about the association areas of the 
cortex, but does not define association. Other authors, and textbooks, 
differ widely in their definitions of the word, or prefer, wisely, not 
to define it at all. 

Hobbes was probably the first to draw a distinction between what 
came later to be called 'free association' and 'controlled' association: 

The train of thoughts, or mental discourse, is of two sorts. The first 
is unguided, without design, and inconstant ... in which case the 

thoughts are safe to wander, as in a dream The second is more 

constant, as being regulated by some desire and design. 8 

However, free association is never entirely free: there are motiva- 
tions, conscious or sub-conscious, which give it direction. On the 
other hand, association controlled by some rule of the game, such as 
'towns with M\ is Tree* to the extent that the rule allows alternative 
choices between permissible moves. The degrees of freedom of a 
matrix vary from rigid automatism to the great adaptability of com- 
plex mental skills; and the flow of associative thought will accordingly 
vary in character: it may move along fixed canals, or follow, like a 
rivulet, the accidents of the terrain and make detours round obstacles 
with an air of earnest goal-directedness. 

Since the attempts of the classic associationist school to reduce 
thinking to association by contiguity and sirnilarity (plus the *secon- 



ASSOCIATION 



647 



dary laws' of facilitation) had to be abandoned, the principles sup- 
posedly underlying association have been classified and re-classified 
over and again. Thus Wells 4 once made a catalogue of eighteen types 
of association adapted from Jung, such as: 'egocentric predicate* 
(example: lonesome— never); 'evaluation* (rose— beautiful); matter 
of fact predicate* (spinach— green); 'subject-verb* (dog—bite), and 

so forth, through 'object-verb*, 'cause-effect*, 'co-ordination*, "Sub^ 

ordination', 'supraordination*, 'contrast', 'coexistence', 'assonance', 
etc. Woodworth (1939) suggested four classes: definition including 
synonyms and supraordinates; completion and predication; co- 
ordinates and contrasts; valuations and personal associations. He also 
suggested an independent classification cutting across the one just 
mentioned, according to a scale from 'meaningfulness' to 'super- 
ficiality'. 5 Most of the experimental work refers to association tests 
where the stimulus is a single word and the response is restricted to 
one other word — a condition not exacdy typical of ordinary verbal 
discourse outside the laboratory. 

The lesson which emerges from these elaborate and painstaking 
attempts at classification is that the principles underlying associative 
thinking are determined by the matrix in which the thinking takes 
place; and that there are as many types of association as there are 
codes which control verbal behaviour. In bilingual countries like 
Switzerland, the response to a German stimulus-word will often be 
its French equivalent; some people are addicted to metaphor, others 
to punning; the chess player and the draughts player's associations 
follow the rules of their respective games. 

To sum up: associative thinking is the exercise of a habit. It may be 
rigid or flexible, with a wide range of adaptability; yet it remains a 
habit in so far as it observes certain invariant rules of the game. Associa- 
tion, qua exercise of a skill, is thus distinguished from learning, which 
is the acquisition of a new skill, and from bisociation, which is the 
combination, re-shuffling and re-structuring of skills. But these 
categories overlap — as discussed in the next chapter. 

NOTES 

To p. 644. *Wave-length* is of course used metaphorically for much more 
complex processes, including both structural and functional characteristics of 
nervous tissue. 'Excitation-clang* or 'frequency-modulation signals* or Hebb*s 
*phase-sequences in cell assemblies* would be closer approximations. 



648 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



To p. 644. For a summary see Woodworth (1939) pp. 3<5o seq., Osgood 
(i960) pp. 722 et seq. Osgood (p. 722), discussing the relative frequencies and 
reaction times of verbal responses in association tests, speaks of a *hierarchical 
structure of associations ; but he uses the word 'hierarchy' to refer to a linear 
scale of gradations. 



XVIII 

HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



Problem-solving is bridging a gap between the initial situation 
and the target. 'Target' must be understood in the widest sense 
— it may be an apple hanging high up on a tree, or a formula for 
squaring the circle, or inventing a honey-spoon which does not drip, 
or fitting a fact into a theory, or making the theory fit the facts. 

Strictly speaking, of course, problems are created by ourselves; 
when I am not hungry, the apple ceases to be a target and there is no 
gap. Vice versa, the insatiable curiosity of Kepler made him see a 
problem where nobody saw one before — why the planets move as 
they do. But the motivational aspect of problem-solving, and the 
exploratory drive in general, have already been discussed. 

There is also a different way of creating problems— for others to 
solve. Economy in art consists in implying its message in the gaps 
between the words, as it were. Words, we saw, are mere stepping- 
stones for thoughts; the meaning must be interpolated; by making 
the gaps just wide enough, the artist compels his audience to exert its 
imagination, and to re-create, to some extent, the experience behind 
the message. But this aspect has also been discussed already, and no 
longer concerns us. 

Bridging the Gap 

The process of bridging the gap between the perceived problem and 
its solution is described in an oft-quoted passage by Karl Mach: 

The subject who wishes for a tree to be laid across a stream to 
enable him to cross it, imagines in fact the problem as already solved. 
649 



650 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



In reflecting that the tree must have previously been transported to 
the river, and previously to that it must have been felled, etc., he 
proceeds from the target-situation to the given situation, along a 
road which he will re-trace in the reverse direction, through a 
reversed sequence of operations, when it comes to actually construct- 
ing the bridge. 1 

This quotation has a long ancestry. It goes back — as Polya (1938) 
has shown in a remarkable paper — to Pappus* classic distinction between 
the analytical method, which treats the unknown solution of a geo- 
metrical problem as if it were already known, then inquires from what 
antecedent it has been derived, and so on backward from antecedent 
to antecedent, until one arrives at a fact or principle already known; 
and the synthetic method which, starting from the point reached last 
in the analysis, reverses the process. 

However, the traditional distinction between analytical and syn- 
thetical method is full of pitfalls, and, though 'thinking backwards' 
from the unknown to the given plays an important role in mathematical 
reasoning, this is by no means always the case in problem-solving; 
moreover 'forward' and 'backward' are often quite arbitrarily used by 
taking topological metaphors too literally. If I aim my rifle at the 
target and then pull the trigger, it would be ridiculous to say that I was 
'thinking backward' from target to trigger; I was merely demonstra- 
ting the trivial fact that in all goal-directed activities one always has 
to 'keep one's eyes on the target' — which can be taken either literally 
or metaphorically. The chess player's aim is to capture the opponent's 
king, either by directly attacking his defences, or by gaming such an 
advantage in material that the king will be at his mercy. But the 
player rarely reasons backward from an anticipated mate position — 
this happens only at dramatic combinative stages; as a rule he looks 
around the board to see 'what's in the position', explores the possi- 
bilities, and then considers what strategical or tactical advantages he 
can derive from it. 

If I wanted to find out whether I am a descendant of Spinoza (as a 
crackpot uncle of mine once asserted), I could follow one of two 
methods, or a combination of both. I could trace Spinoza's descen- 
dants as they branch out downwards, or I could trace my own ances- 
tors branching out and up; or start at both ends and see whether the 
branches meet. The example is a paraphrase from the Logique de Port 
Royal, whose authors seem to equate the upward process with analysis, 



HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



the downward one with synthesis. Spinoza, incidentally, had no 
descendants. 

Returning to Mach's example, the following would perhaps be a 
more realistic way of approaching the problem. To get to my target 
I must cross this stream. This conclusion is arrived at by keeping my 
eyes both on the target and on my own position — by glancing in 
alternation forward and back as it were. Since I must cross the stream, 
let's look for a bridge. There is no bridge. Is there perhaps a boat 
somewhere? No, there is not. Can I wade across? Yes — no, it's too 
cold. I have found three analogies with past methods of solving a 
problem, in my repertory of simple routines. If I wish to be pedantic I 
can say that the rules of the river-crossing skill allowed me three 
choices, three different stratagems, each of which I tried out implicidy, 
as a hypothesis. But surveying the lie of the land I find all three ob- 
structed. What can be done? I must search for some other routine which 
fits the situation. Mach's suggestion to fell a tree is not a very practical 
one — I saw only once a bridge across a swollen gully built that way, 
by natives in Uzbekistan — but I have no axe and we are not in Uzbeki- 
stan. So, roll up your trousers, and let's hope the water is not too icy. 

This is the hum-drum routine of planning and problem-solving in 
every-day life. It means, firstly, searching for a matrix, a skill which 
will * bridge the gap'. The matrix is found by way of analogy (or 
'association by similarity'), that is to say, by recognizing that the 
situation is, for my present intents and purposes, the same as some past 
situations. I then try to apply the same skill which helped in those past 
situations, to the present lie of the land hi the above example I have 
tried three successive stratagems — I have made three hypotheses — and 
after two have failed completely, I reverted to the third, which offered 
the only solution, though a far from perfect one. In other words, I 
have settled for an approximation. Most problems in practical life 
and in the history of science admit of no better solution. 

A point to be noted is that even in this trivial example, the solution 
does not proceed in a single line from target to starting point, or vice 
versa, but by a branching out of hypotheses — of possible strategies — 
from one end, or both ends, until one or several branches meet, as in 
the Spinoza example. Furthermore, in a real geneaological search, the 
expert would eliminate unlikely branches and concentrate on those 
which for geographical or other reasons seem more promising. We 
have here, on a miniature scale as it were, that groping in a vaguely 
sensed direction, towards the good combination', the 'hooking of 



6$2 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the proper atoms' (Poincare), which I have discussed in Book One, 
Vin. However, in these trivial examples the groping and searching 
is done on the conscious or fringe-conscious level, and what we are 
looking for to bridge the gap is merely some routine trick in our 
repertory; a practical skill which will fit the particular lie of the land. 
In other words, the fanning out of hypotheses, the trial-and-check 
procedures in simple thinking routines, reflect the flexibility of the 
skill, which can operate through several sub-skills or equipotential 
lines of action, according to feedback from the environment. 

These sub-skills of symbolic thought have been discussed in various 
contexts. They range from the implicit codes of grammar, syntax, 
and commonsense logic, through the operational rules of extrapola- 
tion, interpolation, transposition, schematization (exaggeration and 
simplification), and so forth, to the special rules of such special games as 
vector-analysis or bio-chemistry. But even these very special and com- 
plex skills can be practised by sheer routine; and vice versa some of 
the most original discoveries arose out of relatively simple problems. 
Complexity of thought is no measure of originality. 

Searching for a Code 

Polya defines a routine problem as one 'which can be solved either 
by substituting special data into a formerly solved general problem, 
or by following step by step, without any trace of originality, some 
well-worn, conspicuous example'. 2 He contrasts these routines with 
the 'rules of discovery': 'The first rule of discovery is to have brains 
and good luck. The second rule of discovery is to sit tight and wait 
till you get a bright idea.' 3 And he defines a 'bright idea' as 'a sudden 
leap of the imagination, a flash of genius'. 4 

However, most practical and theoretical problems are solved at 
some level between these two extremes. Polya's definition of routine 
is too narrow and rigid; it does not take into account the great flexi- 
bility, for instance, of sensory-motor skills such as rock-climbing, or 
glass-blowing, or playing an instrument in an uninspired but tech- 
nically accomplished manner. In symbolic thinking we find equally 
flexible skills which are nevertheless routine: solicitors dictating a 
document or brief; interpreters at public congresses dictating ad hoc 
into the multi-lingual earphone-circuits; politicians on whistle-stop 
tours reeling off variations on well-worn themes. These are routine 



HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



<553 



performances in Polya's sense- of 'substituting special data into general 
equations'; but the equation, the code, leaves in these cases many 
more degrees of freedom than does a mathematical formula, and the 
act of 'substituting special data* has varying degrees of trickiness. 
Even to a skilled and expert translator, for instance, it often happens 
that he has no ready-made idiom or turn of phrase in his repertory to 
substitute for the original. He must improvise some approximation, 
perhaps a metaphor, to cover the meaning — which is a much higher 
skill, involving a degree of originality. 

Turning to more difficult problems, of the type which Duncker and 
Maier put to their subjects, we find routine solutions combined with 
intimations of originality, and we shall recognize an increasing number 
of those factors > in embryonic shape as it were, which we saw at 
work in the creative process. 

The degree of originality which a subject will display depends, 
ceteris paribus, on the nature of the challenge — that is, the novelty and 
unexpectedness of the situation. Familiar situations are dealt with by 
habitual methods; they can be recognized, at a glance, as analogous 
in some essential respect to past experiences which provide a ready- 
made rule to cope with them. The more new features a task contains, 
the more difficult it will be to find the relevant analogy, and thereby 
the appropriate code to apply to it. We have seen (Book One, VIII, 
XVII) that one of the basic mechanisms of the Eureka process is the 
discovery of a hidden analogy; but 'hiddenness* is again a matter of 
degrees. How hidden is a hidden analogy, and where is it hidden? And 
what does the word 'search* mean in this context? In the terms of the 
present theory it means a process of scanning, of bringing successive, 
perceptual or conceptual analyser-codes to bear on the problem; to 
try out whether the problem will match this type of filter or that, as 
the occulist tries out a series of lenses in the frame before the client's 
eyes. Yet the word 'search', so often used in the context of problem- 
solving, is apt to create confusion because it implies that I know 
beforehand what I am searching for, whereas in fact I do not. If I 
search for a lost collar-stud, I put a kind of filter into my 'optical 
frame* which lets only collar-studs and similar shapes pass, and re- 
jects everything else — and then go looking through my drawers. But 
most tasks in problem-solving necessitate applying the reverse pro- 
cedure: the subject looks for a clue, the nature of which he does not 
know, except that it should be a 'clue* (Ansatzpunkt, point d*appui), 
a link to a type of problem familiar to him. Instead of looking through 



654 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



a given filter-frame for an object which matches the filter, he must 
try out one frame after another to look at the object before his nose, 
until he finds the frame into which it fits, i.e. until the problem presents 
some familiar aspect — which is then perceived as an analogy with 
past experience and allows him to come to grips with it. 

This search for the appropriate matrix, or rule of the game to tackle 
the process, is never quite random; the various types of guidance at 
the fumbling, groping, trying stages have been discussed before. Among 
the criteria which distinguish originality from routine are the level 
of consciousness on which the search is conducted, the type of guidance 
on which the subject relies, and the nature of the obstacle which he has to 
overcome. 

Degrees of Originality 

In one of Maier's ingenious experiments the problem set to the subject 
was to catch hold at the same time of two thin strings hung from the 
ceiling so wide apart that he could only get hold of one at a time. 
The only available tool was a pair of pliers. The solution is to tie the 
pliers to one string and set it into pendular motion. The crucial point 
of the experiment, however, is described as follows: 5 

'If the subject had not spontaneously solved the problem within 
ten minutes, Maier supplied him with a hint; he would "accidentally" 
brush against one of the strings, causing it to swing gently. Of those 
who solved the problem after this hint, the average interval between 
hint and solution was only forty-two seconds. . . . Most of those 
subjects who solved the problem immediately after the hint did so 
without any realization that they had been given one. The "idea" of 
making a pendulum with pliers seemed to arise spontaneously/ (My 
italics.) 

Here we have a beautifully ambiguous example of what looks like 
'unconscious' guidance. Obviously there is a world of difference 
between this kind of thing, and the nature of the sub-conscious pro- 
cesses which produce Kekule's serpent dream or Poincare's discovery 
of the Fuchsian functions. Maier's subjects seem to have 'cottoned on* 
to the solution on the pre-conscious or fringe-conscious level of 
awareness. Poincare's inspiration was derived from the creative 
powers of the 'underground*. 

Nevertheless, we notice that while trivial tasks, in so far as they re- 
quire any reflection at all, are solved in full daylight as it were, with the 



HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



65$ 



focus of awareness on the target, even problems of moderate difficulty, 
such as Maier's, require a type of guidance on a different level. Fre- 
quently the difficulty arises not from the objective novelty of the 
problem, but from its 'embeddedness' in the subject's mind. In Book 
One (p. 189) I have described an experiment of Duncker's in which an 
object was so embedded in its visible role as a 'pendulum weight* that 
the student was unable to conceive of it in the role of a 'hammer*. 
'Embeddedness' is a trivial version of the occasional 'snowblindness' 
of genius. In both cases the difficulty lies in going against routine — in 
discarding the most obvious or hkely matrix that offers itself and thus 
gets into the way of the more unlikely one which will do the job. But 
again there is more than a mere difference in degrees between over- 
coming the perceptual attachment of the weight to the string, and over- 
coming the millennial attachment of the human mind to the all-too- 
plausible axioms of Aristotelian physics. 

'Thinking aside' also occurs on all intermediate levels of difficulty. 
It may take the form of switching to visual imagery — as in the prob- 
lem of the Buddhist monk (Book One, p. 183); or of re-stating the 
problem in different terms; or letting one's attention wander, guided 
by some nascent, cloudy analogy. A good example is the Duncker- 
puzzle about the two trains and the bird. Two goods-trains, a hundred 
miles apart, start moving towards each other, each at a speed of twenty 
miles per hour. A silly bird, frightened by the starting hiss of one 
of the trains, flies away at thirty miles per hour in a straight line along 
the railway track until it meets the other train; it reverses its direction 
until it meets the first train, then turns again, and so forth. What 
distance will the bird cover in its flight to and fro until the two trains 
meet? 

To compute the sum of the series of flight-stretches is a rather 
complicated task. But if we think aside, forget about the distances 
covered by the bird, and compute the time until the two trains will 
meet — two and a half hours — we see at once that the bird has also 
flown for two and a half hours and hence covered a total of seventy- 
five miles. The puzzle reflects in miniature Galileo's epocal discovery 
of the laws of free fall — by switching his attention from the spatial to 
the temporal aspects of the process. 

Another famous Duncker problem is how to bring up exactly six 
pints of water from a river, when you have only two containers, one 
measuring nine, the other four pints. You fiddle around, decant in 
your imagination the big container twice into the smaller one, throwing 



656 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the water each time back into the river. This leaves you with one pint 
which you can keep in the bigger or put into the smaller container — but 
that does not help because now you cannot isolate the five pints to 
which the single pint must be added. The solution is simply to switch 
from addition to subtraction: you keep your pint in the smaller con- 
tainer, and fill it up from the larger one — it will now only take 4—1=3 
pints, leaving 9—3=6 pints in the large jug. Different people solve 
this problem by different methods. Polya gives an analytical ex- 
planation; personally I found that with most people the click occurs 
through the reversal of the direction of thought from addition to sub- 
traction — from figure to background — a phenomenon we frequently 
met in discovery. 

At a certain level of problem-solving even a healthy kind of illo- 
gicality, of disregarding apparent contradictions, makes its appearance 
— as in the image of the monk meeting his alter-ego. But enough has 
been said to show that as the challenge becomes more provoking, the 
nature of the guidance which directs the search for the right type of 
matrix to bear on the problem, becomes more intuitive, more re- 
mote from the normal routine of thinking, and that extra-conscious 
processes play an increasingly important part. And thus, having started 
from the base of the hierarchy, we arrive at last at the roof, which we 
have surveyed in the first volume but had left hanging in the air: the 
act of discovery. 

The term 'bisociation* is meant to point to the independent, auto- 
nomous character of the matrices which are brought into contact in 
the creative act, whereas associative thought operates among members 
of a single pre-existing matrix. But we have seen that this is a relative, 
not an absolute criterion, because the members of a matrix are sub- 
skills, i.e. matrices in their own right on a subordinate level of the 
hierarchy, and the degree of their integration, i,e. the coherence of 
the matrix, varies according to case. In matrices which have become 
fully automatized, the code alone determines which member shall 
act in which order — the pedant always takes the same route to his 
office, his strategy is fixed once and for all, and has become in- 
corporated into the code. But the more flexible a skill, the greater 
the part played by strategy. Thus in the problem about the trains and 
the bird, the subject must compute the distance D flown by the bird, 
and he knows that distances are computed by the rule of the game 
D= v.t. The velocity v of the bird is given, and he could get the t in 



HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



a jiffy by substituting for it the time taken by the trains until they 
crash (t= 100/40= 2j). Both the formula, and the process of sub- 
stitution, are familiar sub-skills in the subject's repertory of habits, 
and should function as members of the matrix. However, owing to 
the unusual He of the land — i.e. the way the data are presented — his 
strategy breaks down, the matrix goes to pieces, and its members 
function as independent entities. Once this has occurred it would 
require a certain originality to combine them again. We might even 
be generous and say, that to re-combine them would be a minor bi- 
sociative act. 

Thus the degree of independence of the matrices or submatrices 
which combine in the solution of a problem, can only be judged with 
reference to the subject's mental organization. Any boy of the sixth 
form can derive the Pythagorean theorem, which he has previously 
learned, as a matter of routine; but to discover it for himself would 
require a high degree of originality. 

I hope I have laid sufficient emphasis on the fact that originality 
must be measured on subjective scales and that any self-taught novelty 
is a minor bisociative act. This taken for granted, let me recapitulate 
the criteria which distinguish bisociative originality from associative 
routine. 

Associatioti and Bisociation 

The first criterion was the previous independence of the mental 
skills or universes of discourse which are transformed and integrated 
into the novel synthesis of the creative act. The student solving the 
train-bird problem is entitled to shout Eureka because his mathematical 
skills are so poorly integrated (or so easily dislocated) that the act of 
'hooking them together appears to him a novel discovery. The more 
unlikely or Tar-fetched* the mediating matrix M 2 — i.e. the more 
independent from M x — the more unexpected and impressive the 
achievement. The creative act could be described as the highest form 
of learning because of the high improbability (or anti-chance proba- 
bility) of the solution. 

If we now turn from subjective originality to discoveries which are 
new in actual fact, we again find the previous independence of the 
components that went into the 'good combination to be a measure 
of achievement. Historically speaking, the frames of reference of 
magnetism and electricity, of physics and chemistry, of corpuscles and 



6$$ THE ACT OF CREATION 

waves, developed separately and independently, both in the individual 
and the collective mind, until the frontiers broke down. And this 
breakdown was not caused by establishing gradual, tentative connec- 
tions between individual members of the separate matrices, but by the 
amalgamation of two realms as wholes, and the integration of the 
laws of both realms into a unified code of greater universality. Multiple 
discoveries and priority disputes do not diminish the objective, his- 
torical novelty produced by these major bisociative events — they 
merely prove that the time was ripe for that particular synthesis. 

Minor, subjective bisociative processes do occur on all levels, and 
are the main vehicle of untutored learning. But objective novelty 
comes into being only when subjective originality operates on the 
highest level of the hierarchies of existing knowledge. 

The discoveries of yesterday are the truisms of tomorrow, because 
we can add to our knowledge but cannot subtract from it. When two 
frames of reference have become integrated into one it becomes 
difficult to imagine that previously they existed separately. The 
synthesis looks deceptively self-evident, and does not betray the 
imaginative effort it needed to put its component parts together. In 
this respect the artist gets a better deal than the scientist. The changes 
of style in the representative arts, the discoveries which altered our 
frames of perception, stand out as great landmarks for all to see. The 
true creativity of the innovator in the arts is more dramatically evident 
and more easily distinguished from the routine of the mere practi- 
tioner than in the sciences, because art (and humour) operate primarily 
through the transitory juxtaposition of matrices, whereas science 
achieves their permanent integration into a cumulative and hierarchic 
order. Laurence Olivier in Hamlet is perceived as Olivier and as 
Hamlet at the same time; but when the curtain goes down, the two 
personae separate again, and do not become amalgamated into a higher 
unit which is later combined with others into still higher units. 

A further criterion of the creative act was that it involves several 
levels of consciousness. In problem-solving pre- and extra-conscious 
guidance makes itself increasingly felt as the difficulty increases; but 
in the truly creative act both in science and art, underground levels 
of the hierarchy which are normally inhibited in the waking state 
play a decisive part. It is perhaps significant that the German word 
for the Creator is Schopfe^ and for creating schogfen — 'to scoop' in 
the sense of drawing water in buckets from a well. The Creator is 
thus visualized as creating the world out of His own depth, and the 



HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 



6$9 



creative mind with a small c is supposed to apply a similar procedure. 
But whatever the inner sources on which the Lord of Genesis drew 
while his spirit hovered over the dark waters, in the case of humble 
mortals the sources are in the phylogenetically and ontogenetically 
older, underground layers of his mind. He can only reach them 
through a temporary regression to earlier, more primitive, less specia- 
lized levels of mentation, through a reader pour mieux sauter. In this 
respect the creative act parallels the process of biological regeneration 
— the liberation of genetic potentials normally under restraint, through 
the de-dirFerentiation of damaged tissues. Thus the creative process 
involves levels of the mind separated by a much wider span than in 
any other mental activity — except in pathological states, which rep- 
resent a reader sans sauter. The emotional manifestations of the Eureka 
act — sudden illumination followed by abreaction and catharsis — also 
testify to its subconscious origins; they are to some extent comparable 
to the cathartic effects of the analyst's method of bringing 'repressed 
complexes' into the patient's consciousness. 

The re-structuring of mental organization effected by the new 
discovery implies that the creative act has a revolutionary or destrudive 
side. The path of history is strewn with its victims: the discarded isms 
of art, the epicycles and phlogistons of science. 

Associative skills, on the other hand, even of the sophisticated kind 
which require a high degree of concentration, do not display the above 
features. Their biological equivalents are the activities of the organism 
while in a state of dynamic equilibrium with the environment — as 
distinct from the more spectacular manifestations of its regenerative 
potentials. The skills of reasoning rely on habit, governed by well- 
established rules of the game; the 'reasonable person' — used as a 
standard norm in English common law — is level-headed instead of 
multi-level-headed; adaptive and not destructive; an enlightened 
conservative, not a revolutionary; willing to learn under proper 
guidance, but unable to be guided by his dreams. 

The main distinguishing features of associative and bisociative 
thought may now be summed up, somewhat brutally, as follows: 

Habit Originality 
Association within the confines Bisocktion of independent 
of a given matrix matrices 



Guidance by pre-conscious or Guidance by sub-conscious 

extra-conscious processes processes normally under restraint 



660 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Habit 
Dynamic equilibrium 

Rigid to flexible variations on a 
theme 

Repetitiveness 
Conservative 



Originality 
Activation of regenerative 
potentials 

Super-flexibility (recukr pour 
mieux sauter) 

Novelty 

Destructive-Constructive 



And thus we are back where we left off in the first book; the circle 
is closed. 



APPENDIX I: ON LOADSTONES 
AND AMBER 



I have compared (Book One, X) the constructive periods in the 
evolution of science to river-estuaries in which previously separate 
branches of knowledge merge in a series of bisociative acts. The 
present appendix is meant to illustrate the process by a few salient 
episodes from the history of magnetism and electricity — two fields of 
study which, until the beginning of the nineteenth century, had 
developed on independent lines, and seemed to be in no way related. 
Their merging was due to the discovery of unitary laws of a previously 
unsuspected kind underlying the variety of phenomena, and took 
physics a decisive step forward towards a universal synthesis. 

The Greeks, fortunately perhaps, had not paid much attention to 
the antics of loadstones and amber; they had shrugged them off as 
freak phenomena. Aristode had hardly anything to say about them — 
had he laid down the law on magnetism and electricity, as he did in 
other domains of physics, the story might have been different. As it 
happened, both sciences started from scratch in the seventeenth century, 
just at a time when scholasticism had to yield to the empirical ap- 
proach. This smoothed their path of progress — but even so, progress 
was neither smooth nor continuous. 

Apart from some casual references in earlier sources, the first land- 
mark in the history of magnetism in Europe is a manuscript, dated 
1269, by a French crusader, Petrus Peregrinus from Picardy. It gives a 
detailed description of two types of mariner's compass (which ap- 
parently had been in use for at least a century): a magnetized needle 
either floating on a stick in a bowl of water, or turning on a vertical 
axle. Peregrine further described his experiments with a spherical 
loadstone which he had fashioned, defining its poles and the attractive 
and repellent properties of its surface; yet he shared the contemporary 

661 



662 



THE ACT OB CREATION 



belief that the source of the Virtue' which attracted the compass needle 
was located in the sky—in the Polar Star or the Great Bear. 

During the next three hundred years no further progress seems to 
have been made — except for some improvements of the compass and 
attempts to measure magnetic declination, caused by the puzzling dis- 
covery that the direction of the needle deviated at different places to 
different degrees from the direction of the Polar Star. 

The next landmark is Dr. William Gilbert of Colchester, court 
physician to Queen Elizabeth, the first great English experimentalist. 
Gilbert put both magnetism and electricity on the map — or rather, on 
two separate maps; his influence on his younger contemporaries, 
Kepler and Galileo, was enormous. Gilbert's fundamental discovery — 
in fact the only important discovery made in the whole history of 
magnetism as an independent science — is again one of those which, in 
retrospect, appear deceptively simple. He found that the power which 
attracted the magnetic needle was not in the skies but in the earth: that 
the earth itself was a huge spherical loadstone. He arrived at this con- 
clusion by making, as Peregrine had done, a spherical magnet, and 
exploring the behaviour of a minute compass-needle on its surface. 
As he moved the needle over his globe, he saw that it behaved exacdy 
as the needle of the mariner's compass behaved on a sea journey — both 
with regard to its north-south alignment and to its 'dip', which in- 
creased the closer the needle approached either of the poles. He con- 
cluded that his spherical loadstone was a model of the earth which 
therefore must be a magnet.* 

So the secret of the compass-needle was solved by ascribing magnetic 
properties to the earth— there remained only the secret of the nature of 
magnetism itself. Gilbert's book, De Magnete, was published a.d. 
1600 — the same year in which Kepler joined forces with Tycho de 
Brahe to lay the foundations of the new astronomy; the symbolic 
year which, like a watershed, divides medieval from modern philo- 
sophy. Gilbert, born in 1544, stood, like Kepler, astride the water- 
shed: with one foot in the brave new world of experimental science, 
the other stuck in Aristotelian animism. His descriptions of how 
magnetism works are modern; his explanations of its causes are 
medieval: he regards the magnetic force as a living emanation from 
the spirit or soul of the loadstone. The earth, being a giant loadstone, 
also has a soul— its magnetic virtue — and so have the heavenly bodies. 

'Magnetic force is animate, or imitates the soul; and in many things 
surpasses the human soul while this is bound up in the organic body/ 1 



APPENDIX I 



663 



The actions of the magnetic virtue are 'without error . . . quick, 
definite, constant, directive, motive, imperant, harmonious ... it 
reaches out like an arm clasping round the attracted body and drawing 
it to itself. ... It must needs be light and spiritual so as to enter the 
iron — but it must also be a material, subtle vapour, an ether or 
effluvium. Even the earth's rotation is somehow connected with 
magnetism: 'In order that the Earth may not perish in various ways, 
and be brought from confusion, she turns herself about by magnetic 
and primary virtue/ 2 

Thus Gilbert's book, which enjoyed uncontested authority for the 
next two hundred years, postulated on the one hand action at a dis- 
tance, but asserted on the other the existence of an effluvium or ether 
which passes 'like a breath' between the attracting bodies. It was also 
a major factor in creating semantic confusion: the word 'magnetism', 
which originally referred to the properties of a type of ore mined in 
Magnesia, a province of Thessaly, came soon to be applied to any kind 
of attraction or affinity, physical, psychological, or metaphorical 
('animal magnetism', 'Mesmerism', etc.). But as long as the study of 
the behaviour of magnets remained an isolated field of research, no 
further progress could be made. In 1621 van Helmont, and in 1641 
Athanasius Kircher, published books on the subject which added 
nothing new to it, but dwelt at length on the alleged wound-healing 
properties of magnets; Kircher's book carried a whole section on the 
'magnetism' of love, and ended with the dictum that the Lord is the 
magnet of the universe. Newton took no interest in magnetism except 
for some remarks in the third book of the Princtpia* to the effect that 
the magnetic force seemed to vary approximately with the inverse 
cube of the distance; while Descartes extended his theory of cosmic 
vortices to cover both magnetic and electric phenomena. The main 
subjects of interest were the variations in the positions of the earth's 
magnetic poles which, to the navigators' distress, were found to wander 
around like floating kidneys. This led to the kind of controversy 
characteristic of most periods of stagnation in the history of science; 
thus one $enry Bond of London town, a 'Teacher of Navigation', 
published in 1676 a book, The Longitude Found, based on the theory 
that the magnetic poles lagged behind the earth's daily rotation. This 
thesis was torn to pieces in another book, The Longitude Not Found, by 
Peter Blackborough. 

Even the great Halley went haywire where magnetism was con- 
cerned: he proposed that the earth was a kind of solar system in 



664 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



miniature, with an inner core and an outer shell, both of them mag- 
netized, and a luminous fluid between them to provide light for the 
people living on the surface of the inner core; this luminous effluvium 
escaping through the earth's pores gave rise to the aurora borealis. 
Halley was the greatest astronomer and one of the leading scientific 
minds of the age, who had published the first modern magnetic chart 
in Mercator's projection, based on his own patient observations; but 
his wild speculations indicate that the element of the fantastic was 
firmly embedded in the concept of magnetism — as it still is in our day. 
Children are still fascinated by compasses and magnets, governed by a 
force more mysterious than gravity — because the latter is taken for 
granted from earliest experience whereas magnetism cannot be sensed, 
and not only attracts but also repels. No wonder that this unique 
phenomenon, while considered in isolation, had led those who studied 
it round in circles in a blocked matrix. 

But although, for nearly two centuries, the study of magnetism made 
no progress, Gilbert's work had a fertile influence on other branches of 
science. The loadstone became the archetype of action-at-a-distance, 
and paved the way for the recognition of universal gravity. Without 
the demonstrable phenomena of magnetic attraction, people would 
have been even more reluctant to exchange the traditional view that 
heavy bodies tended towards the centre of the universe, for the im- 
plausible suggestion that all heavenly and earthly bodies were tugging 
at each other 'with ghostly fingers* across empty space. Even the magic 
properties attributed to magnetism, and the very ambiguity of its 
concept, proved to be unexpectedly stimulating to the tortuous line 
of advance which led via Mesmerism and hypnosis to contemporary 
forms of psychiatry. 

The next turning point is Coulomb's discovery, in 1785, that the 
inverse square law applied to magnetism too, as it applied to gravity. 
It must have looked at the time as if these two kinds of action-at-a- 
distance would soon turn out to be based on the same principle — as 
Kepler and Descartes thought they were; as if a great merger of sciences 
were in the offing. But that synthesis is still a matter of the future; 
instead of merging with gravity, magnetism entered into a much less 
obvious union with electricity. 

The first mention of electricity on record occurs in the fragments of 
the History of Physics by Theophrastus, the successor of Aristotle at the 
head of the Athenean Lyceum. He innocently remarks that when amber 



APPENDIX I 



665 



is rubbed it acquires the curious virtue of attracting flimsy objects. The 
Greek word for amber is elektron. Although the Greeks were not 
interested in the elektron s virtues, Forever Amber would be an appro- 
priate motto for modern science. 

For two thousand years little more is heard of electricity, until we 
again come to Dr. Gilbert, who demonstrated that the peculiar 
properties of amber were shared by glass, sulphur, crystals, resin, and 
a number of other substances, which he accordingly called 'electrics'. 
To account for electric attraction he created the concept of an electric 
effluvium, as distinct from the magnetic effluvium— but with an 
equally lasting influence on further developments. 

During the next century, advance again was slow. Members of the 
Italian Academia del Cimento (a short-lived forerunner of the Royal 
Society) continued Gilbert's experiments, and added a few observations 
to them. The main events of the century were the discovery of elec- 
tric repulsion and the construction, by Guericke, of the first machine 
for the continuous production of electricity. The machine consisted 
of a sulphur ball, the size of a child's head, which was rotated on 
an axle while the experimenter's hand was pressed against its surface, 
thus generating a frictional charge. Guericke also discovered, and 
described, the phenomena of electrical conduction and induction— but 
nobody paid any attention to them, and they had to be rediscovered 
in the next century. This illustration of discontinuity in progress was 
followed, almost immediately, by yet another one. In the first years 
of the eighteenth century an Englishman, Hawkesbee, invented a new 
machine to produce electricity by replacing Guericke's sulphur sphere 
with one of glass — which was a vast improvement, but again passed 
unnoticed. The glass-friction machine was re-invented and improved 
in the 1740s; the sphere was replaced by a cylinder, pads were used 
instead of. the hand, and the machine was equipped with insulated 
wire conductors — the conductivity of metal having been meanwhile 
discovered by Gray and Du Fay, who also made the basic distinction 
between conductors and insulators. 

The fact that the electric virtue produced by this machine could be 
carried by wires over distances of hundreds of feet led to the concept 
of a flow or current— the electric effluvium was now regarded as a 
kind of liquid, or liquid fire, flowing through the wire. But the 
phenomena of electric repulsion led Du Fay to assume two kinds of 
electric fluid — like kinds repelling, unlike kinds attracting each other, 
on the analogy of magnetic poles. Benjamin Franklin did not like the 



<5<56 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



idea of two fluids; he believed that the polarity could be explained by 
a surplus or a deficiency of a single fluid, designated by a plus and a 
minus sign — a rather unhappy suggestion which, to this day, is apt 
to confuse the minds of hopeful students. A further complication 
arose from the fact that while the electric fluid was demonstrably 
unable to flow across insulating substances such as glass or air, it 
nevertheless induced electric charges on the other side of the in- 
sulator; so one now had to assume that there were two kinds of 
electricity: the first a fluid running through a wire, the second an 
etheric effluvium acting at a distance. 

Thus by the middle of the eighteenth century the whole science was 
in a state of confused and creative anarchy — as cosmology and mecha- 
nics had been a hundred years earlier, before Newton. 'We cannot 
follow the twists of theory in the rninds of these men', Pledge wrote 
about Franklin and his contemoraries; 4 yet they went happily ahead, 
theorizing in dirty kitchens and experimenting with kites, Hghtning 
rods, luminous discharges in vacuum tubes, detonating inflammable 
spirits, electrocuting birds, mice, and occasionally themselves. I have 
mentioned before (p. 204) the sensation created by the discovery of 
the condenser in the shape of the Leyden Jar — due to accidental shock; 
a few years later, the expression 'an electrifying effect' had already 
gone into metaphorical use. According to the Oxford Dictionary, 
armies were the first to be 'electrified' — by courage (Burke); theatre 
audiences came next (Emerson). Typical of the happy confusion 
was Gray's theory, which he confined to the secretary of the Royal 
Society on the day before his death, that the planets were moved round 
the sun by a simple electric force. To demonstrate this, a small pen- 
dulum weight was held on a string over an electrically charged globe, 
and lo! the weight began to describe circles and ellipses round the 
globe, always in the correct direction from west to east — due, of course, 
as was later proved, to small unconscious jerks which the experi- 
menter imparted to the string. 

The first indirect intimation of the shape of things to come was the 
demonstration (around 1780) by Cavendish and Coulomb that the 
action-at-a-distance type of electricity (i.e. the electrostatic field) was 
governed by the same inverse square law as magnetism and gravity. 
Thus mathematics entered into the study of electricity and magnetism, 
although their physical nature was anybody's guess. The mathematical 
tools were ready, in the shape of differential equations which French 
mathematicians of the eighteenth century — Lagrange, Laplace, 



APPENDIX 1 



667 



Legendre — had worked out for gravity and mechanics; then Poisson 
lifted the basic equations of the gravitational potential out of their 
original frame of reference, and applied them first to the electrostatic, 
then to the magnetic field. He was able to import these rules of the 
game from a foreign playing-field by the bold move of substituting 
electric charge' and 'magnetic pole strength* for gravitational mass' 
in the equation — and it worked. Newton's inverse square law, Lag- 
range's and Poisson's equations, were among the first striking in- 
stances revealing the unity of mathematical laws underlying the 
diversity of phenomena. 

In the meantime, Luigi Galvani, Professor of Anatomy at the 
University of Bologna, had spent some fifteen years working on a 
theory of 'animal electricity'. On September 20th, 1786, he recorded 
one of his experiments, which was to make history. He attached a 
nerve-muscle preparation of a dissected frog to a copper hook and 
hung the hook on an iron railing. Whenever one of the frog's legs 
touched the iron, it jerked away and contracted violently. Now it 
was already known that electric discharges from Ley den Jars or light- 
ning rods caused muscles to contract; but since the iron railing could 
not be a source of electricity, Galvani drew the logical conclusion that 
the electricity which caused the contraction was generated in the 
muscle itself under the stimulus of the metallic contact. Like so many 
neat and logical deductions it happened to be wrong; but it was an 
error which proved to be as immensely fruitful as Columbus* or 
Kepler's errors. The muscle convulsion had indeed been an electrical 
phenomenon; however, as Volta was soon to prove, the current had 
been generated not inside the muscle but by tie contact of the two 
different metals, copper and iron— the prototype of the Voltaic battery 
(the frog's leg touching the railing closed the circuit). Galvani's 
theory had been a wrong move in the right direction, for the experi- 
ment did demonstrate the sensitivity of certain living tissues to minute 
electric currents; after a few decades of the usual detours, Sonimering 
compared nerves to electrical telegraph wires; and from the middle 
of the nineteenth century onwards electric phenomena played an in- 
creasing part in physiology, until finally the electro-chernisty of 
living tissues became a single, integrated matrix. 

In the domain of inanimate matter, the Voltaic battery, inspired by 
Galvani's frogs, led to a parallel synthesis of electricity and chemistry. 
The battery gave the experimenters for the first time ample supplies 
of electric current— which neither the friction machines nor the 



668 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Leyden Jar had been able to do. It taught them not only that the 
chemical interaction of metals produced electricity; but also that an 
electric current sent through certain chemicals led to their decom- 
position. In 1806 Davy tentatively suggested that chemical affinity 
had an electrical basis. But nearly a century had to pass until, in 1897, 
Thompson discovered that a certain type of electrical discharge — the 
so-called cathode rays — consisted of particles smaller than atoms; 
and that in these particles 'matter derived from different sources such 
as hydrogen, oxygen, etc. — is one and the same kind, this matter being 
the substance from which the chemical elements are built up*. 5 
Thompson's 'elementary corpuscles' were later named 'electrons'. 

But let me return for a moment to the Voltaic battery. The abun- 
dant flow of current which it produced was so startling that it was at 
first doubted whether this 'electric fluid' was the same kind of thing 
which came in sparks out of the older contraptions. Comparison of 
their effects led to the realization that the discharges of static electricity 
from a Leyden Jar had a higher potential or tension, whereas the flow 
from the battery had a low potential but carried a greater quantity of 
current. Thus the distinction was made between the potential (vol- 
tage), roughly comparable to the gradient of a river-bed, and the 
quantity of liquid (amperage) that passed through it. But only fifty 
years later did Faraday realize that the spark from a Leyden Jar could 
be regarded as a short-lived current; then came Maxwell, who treated 
currents as moving charges, thus finally raiifying the two kinds of 
electricity: 'frictional' and 'Voltaic*. 

In the meantime, however, that other grand synthesis got underway: 
the unification of electricity and magnetism. There were several steps. 
The first link was established in 1820 by the observation of Hans 
Christian Oersted in Copenhagen that if an electric current flowed 
through a wire in the vicinity of a magnetic compass, the needle was 
deflected and turned into a position at right angles to the wire. The 
news created an immediate sensation in Paris, where Ampere's ex- 
citable brain gave off a spark bigger than any Leyden Jar: he realized 
in a single flash that if an electric current produced a magnetic field, 
as the reaction of the needle indicated, then all magnetic fields may be 
due to electric currents— that magnetism was a by-product of elec- 
tricity. He let a current run through a spiral coil inside of which he 
placed a steel needle: it became magnetized, and the first electro- 
magnet was born.* 

But how, then, was the 'natural magnetism' of loadstones to be 



APPENDIX I 



669 



explained, which had no currents running around them? Ampere's 
answer was that minute currents were circulating in coils inside the 
atoms of the loadstone. These sub-atomic currents produced magnetic 
fields, which tended to align themselves with the magnetic field of 
the biggest loadstone, the earth. The theory at the same time dis- 
pensed with the necessity of explaining magnetism by the physical 
action of poles; it was perhaps the boldest and most surprising idea in 
this whole development. Unfortunately, Ampere's contemporaries 
were not 'ripe' for it. To quote D. L. Webster: 

Scientists should have reacted to this surprise better than they 
did — but scientists are human. The philosophical principle of parsi- 
mony in hypotheses should have been their guide. Instead their guide 
seems to have been habit. Parsimony would have dictated as follows: 

1. Whatever we believe about magnets, we must recognize 
currents in wires as currents. 

2. The pole theory of magnets requires us to believe in two types 
of field producers, poles and currents, whereas Ampere's theory 
requires only currents. 

3. The pole theory requires two very different sets of laws for 
magnetic fields, one for fields due to poles and the other for fields 
due to currents, whereas Ampere's theory requires only one set of 
laws. 

4. Therefore, we shall follow Ampere. 

But poles were treated as real for nearly another century. 6 

Yet Ampere's idea was never entirely forgotten. Maxwell compared 
Ampere's sub-atomic coils to miniature spinning-tops which always 
tend to preserve the direction of their axes; he tried to magnetize a 
piece of iron by rotating it fast. In 191 3, when Niels Bohr invented his 
model of the atom as a miniature solar system, it was thought that the 
orbital motions of the electrons round the nucleus provided the 
Amperean circuits. This turned out to be part of the truth; but the 
principal source of magnetism was found to be, even more surprisingly, 
a spinning motion of the electrons round their own axes. An electron, 
of course, can hardly be said to have an axis since it is now regarded 
as something in the nature of a blur; but mathematically the model 
worked, and that is all one can ask for in the present state of physics. 



670 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



A century after Oersted, magnetism and electricity were finally re- 
duced to a common source. 

But I have been anticipating the happy end. The next stage, after 
Ampere had shown that an electric current will produce a magnetic 
field, was the discovery by Faraday (in 183 1) that magnetism could be 
'directly converted into electricity' by moving magnet and conduct- 
ing coil relative to each other.* This led to the invention of the dynamo, 
and later of the electric motor; but we are concerned with theory, not 
with the ubiquitous applications of electric energy. 

Faraday, as we know, was a visualizer, who saw the universe pat- 
terned by lines of force— like the familiar diagrams of iron filings 
grouped round a magnet. James Clark Maxwell, who inaugurated the 
post-Newtonian age in physics, was a super-visualizer. He took 
Faraday's imaginary lines of force and put them into imaginary tubes 
carrying a fluid; then he abolished the spaces between the tubes so 
that they became 'mere surfaces, directing the motion of a fluid filling 
up all space' — the ether. Next, he applied to this model the rules of a 
game which bore no relation at all to electro-magnetism — hydro- 
dynamics, with its vortices and eddies and changing pressures.** One 
conclusion which emerged from this imaginary operation was that all 
changes in electric and magnetic force (for instance, those caused by 
an oscillating circuit) sent waves spreading through space; and that 
these waves had the same transverse character, and the same speed, 
as light. "We can scarcely avoid the inference', he wrote in a monu- 
mental sentence, 'that light consists in the transverse undulations of the 
same medium which is the cause of electric and magnetic phenomena.' 

Thus after electricity and magnetism had been united, both were 
now united to light. Electro-magnetic radiations came to be regarded 
as rapid alternations of electrical and magnetic stresses in space, where 
each change in the electric stress gives rise to a magnetic stress, which 
again gives rise to an electric stress and so on. Soon the range of these 
radiations was shown to comprise not only the visible spectrum 
between the ultra-violet and the infra-red of radiant heat, but to extend 
to the ultra-short gamma rays of radioactivity, and to the kilometre- 
long waves used in radio-communication. 

Perhaps the most fascinating aspect of Maxwell's genius is that as 
soon as he had worked out the mathematical formulation of his 
theory, he discarded the model by means of which he had reached it. 
It was as if a man, after climbing a ladder to get a free view over his 
surroundings, had kicked out the ladder from under him, and remained 



APPENDIX I 



67I 



freely suspended in the air. Gone were the tubes, the vortices, the 
ether; all that remained were 'fields' of an abstract, non-substantial 
nature, and the mathematical formalism which described the propa- 
gation of real waves in an apparently non-existent medium. It was the 
great turning point in physical science, when the aspiration to arrive 
at intelligible, mechanical models was abandoned. This renuncia- 
tion, born of necessity, soon hardened into dogma — a secular version 
of the Commandment 'Thou shalt not make unto thee any graven 
image' — of gods or atoms.* 

The transition from model-making to mathematical abstraction is 
strikingly illustrated by the fact that Maxwell himself left it to others 
(to Heinrich Rudolph Herz, as it came to pass) to give empirical proof 
of his electro-magnetic waves. As Crowther wrote: 

The General Equations of the Electro-magnetic Field were more 
real to him than material phenomena he could know in the labora- 
tory. Physicists have often wondered why Maxwell made no attempt 
to prove experimentally the existence of electro-magnetic waves. 
He probably felt he was better acquainted with the waves through 
the medium of the General Equations, and would not have known 
them any better, perhaps not so well/ if he had met them in the 
laboratory. 7 

Yet even Maxwell had his blind spots. The electron as a basic, 
quasi-atomic unit of electricity was clearly implied in his model of 
ether-vortices, and in his theory of electrolysis. Yet he rejected the 
concept of 'particles* of electricity as Faraday before had rejected it. 
Thus, as already mentioned, it was left, to J. J. Thompson to take the 
next decisive step: the identification of the electron as an elementary 
unit of electricity, and at the same time an elementary particle of 
matter. Some fifteen years later Rutherford discovered that the atom 
had a positively charged nucleus; Moseley discovered that the number 
of electrons in an atom determined its place in the periodic system; 
and Bohr made his famous model of electrons circling round the 
nucleus like planets round the sun. Matter and electricity had merged 
into a single matrix. 

We have followed, though only in the scantest outline, the suc- 
cessive confluences into a vast river-delta, of electricity, magnetism, 
light, heat, and other electro-magnetic radiations; of chemistry, bio- 
chemistry, and atomic physics. This development was, as we have seen 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



(p. 228), accompanied by the realization that the various powers of 
nature* were merely different forms of energy. In earlier days, and 
well into the nineteenth century, each of these 'powers' were thought 
to be contained in a material substance, a subtle fluid or vapour or 
effluvium: heat in the phlogiston; organic energy in the vital fluid'; 
gravity in the ether; electricity and magnetism in their separate effluvia. 
The word 'energy* from the Greek en-ergos (work) was for the first 
time used by Thomas Young in 1807 to designate kinetic energy only. 
But by that time Rumford had already shown by an ingenious experi- 
ment that mechanical energy could be converted into heat: he made a 
blunt boring machine, driven by horses, work against a metal cylinder 
underwater, and demonstrated that the heat thus produced actually 
brought the water to the boil. By the middle of the century it became 
evident that the powers of nature were convertible: mechanical 
motion into heat, heat into motion, motion into electricity, elec- 
tricity into magnetism, and so forth. Thus one by one the various 
'subtle fluids' dropped out of the game, and were replaced by equa- 
tions determining the exchange rates, as it were, for the conversion 
of one kind of energy-currency into another. Lastly, Einstein and his 
successors taught us that mass and energy, particle and wave, are 
merely two aspects of one and the same basic process. Only in one 
respect have they failed so far: in their attempts to link the gravita- 
tional field and the electro-magnetic field in a single system of equa- 
tions, a unified field theory. 



NOTES 

To p. 662. The 'dip', or magnetic inclination seems to have been dis- 
covered independently by Georg Hartmann, a German clergyman, in 1544, and 
by Robert Norman, a compass-maker from Wapping. Norman and Mercator 
also anticipated Gilbert by placing the source of magnetic attraction in the earth. 

To p. 668. The experiment was actually suggested to Ampere by Arago. 

To p. 670, Faraday's original formulation was indeed entirely relativistic. 
According to Newtonian mechanics, however, it did make a difference whether 
the wire was moved or the magnet. This paradoxical asymmetry was one of the 
pincipal considerations which led Einstein to the theory of special relativity 
(cf. Polanyi, 1957, pp. 10-11). 

To 670. Vortices had already appeared in Kepler's and Descartes' ex- 
planations; and Helmholz, too, had compared the dynamics of fluids with 
electric currents and magnetic fields; but Maxwell's electro-hydro-dynamics 
were of an incomparably more refined order. 



APPENDIX I 



673 



To p. 671. Maxwell himself was less dogmatic about it. Tor the sake of 
persons of different types of mind, scientific truth should be presented in different 
forms and should be regarded as equally scientific whether it appears in the 
robust form and vivid colouring of a physical illustration or in the tenuity and 
paleness of a symbolical expression.* 



APPENDIX II: SOME FEATURES OF 
GENIUS 



1. THE SENSE OF WONDER 



In one of his essays — The Cutting of an Agate — William Butler 
Yeats voiced one of the silliest popular fallacies of our times: 

Those learned men who are a terror to children and an ignomi- 
nious sight in lovers' eyes, all those butts of a traditional humour 
where there is something of the wisdom of peasants, are mathe- 
maticians, theologians, lawyers, men of science of various kinds. 

The fallacy consists in the identification of 'men of science of 
various kinds* with the lowest kind: the figure of the uninspired 
pedant in the waxworks of popular imagination* (p. 256). One might 
as well identify 'the artist* with the factory-girls who put in the colour 
on 'hand-painted' souvenirs. 

It is a fallacy of relatively recent origin. Tillyard 1 and Marjorie 
Nicolson 2 have shown how profoundly the Pythagorean revival 
had influenced Shakespeare and transformed the Elizabethan world- 
picture. Perhaps the greatest experience of Milton's youth was peering 
for the first time through a Galilean telescope: 

Before [his] eyes in sudden view appear 
The secrets of the hoary Deep — a dark 
Illimitable ocean, without bound, 
Without dimension 



And we remember John Donne's excitement caused by Kepler's 
discoveries: 

674 



APPENDIX II 



675 



Man hath weavd out a net, and this net throwne 
Upon the Heavens, and now they are his owne . . . 

The sense of wonder was shared by mystic, poet, and scientist 
alike; their falling apart dates only from the end of the nineteenth 
century. In Book One, XI, I have discussed the scientist's motivational 
drive, and the emotions to which it gives rise: the present appendix is 
meant to illustrate these general considerations by concrete examples 
from the lives of a few outstanding men. 

Aristotle on Motivation 

The mental image that one tries to form of a white-clad, sandalled 
member of the Pythagorean Brotherhood, living around 530 B.C. in 
Croton, southern Italy, is necessarily hazy. But at least we know that 
the Brotherhood was both a scientific academy and a monastic order; 
that its members led an ascetic communal life where all property was 
shared, thus anticipating the Essenes and the primitive Christian com- 
munities. We know that much of their time was spent in contempla- 
tion, and that initiation into the higher mysteries of mathematics, 
astronomy, and medicine depended upon the purification of spirit and 
body, which the aspirant had to achieve by abstinences and examina- 
tions of conscience. Pythagoras himself, like St. Francis, is said to have 
preached to animals; the whole surviving tradition indicates that his 
disciples, while engaged in number-lore and astronomical calculations, 
firmly believed that a true scientist must be a saint, and that the wish 
to become one was the motivation of his labours. 

The Hippocratics followed a materialist philosophy; yet that won- 
derfully precise ethical commandment, the Hippocratic Oath, pre- 
scribed not only that the physician should do everything in his powers 
to help the sick, but also that he should refrain, in the patient's house, 
'from any act of seduction, of male or female, bond or free' — a truly 
heroic act of self-denial. The motivation of Greek science in general 
was summed up in a passage by Aristotle, from which I have briefly 
quoted before (my italics): 

Men were first led to study [natural] philosophy, as indeed they 
are today, by wonder. At first they felt wonder about the more super- 
ficial problems; afterwards they advanced gradually by perplexing 



676 THE ACT OF CREATION 

themselves over greater difficulties; e.g., the behaviour of the moon, 
the phenomena of the sun, and the origination of the universe. Now 
he who is perplexed and wonders believes himself to be ignorant. 
Hence even the lover of myths is, in a sense, a philosopher, for a 
myth is a tissue of wonders. Thus if they took to philosophy to 
escape ignorance, it is patent that they were pursuing science for the 
sake of knowledge itself, and not for utilitarian applications. This is 
confirmed by the course of historical development itself. For nearly all 
the requisites both of comfort and social refinement had been secured before 
the quest for this form of enlightenment began. So it is clear that we do 
not seek it for the sake of any ulterior application. Just as we call a 
man free who exists for his own ends and not for those of another, 
so it is with this which is the only free man's science: it alone of the 
sciences exists for its own sake. 3 

It is amusing to note Aristotle's belief that applied science and 
technology had completed their task long before his time— as the 
italicized lines and other passages in his writings clearly indicate. His 
statement is somehow biassed, because it does not take into account 
the utilitarian element in the origin of geometry: land-surveying, and 
of astronomy: calendar-making. Nevertheless, his surnming up of the 
motives which drove the Greek men of science seems to be by and 
large true. Thus Archimedes, the greatest of them, was compelled by 
necessity to invent a whole series of spectacular mechanical devices — 
including the water screw, and some engines of war which brought 
him all the fame and glory an inventor can dream of. Yet such was his 
contempt for these practical inventions that he refused to leave a 
written record of them. His passions were mathematics and pure 
science; his famous words, 'give me but a firm spot on which to stand 
and I will move the earth' reflect a metaphysical fantasy, not an 
engineer's ambitions. When Syracuse fell in 212 B.C. to the Roman 
general Marcellus, the sage, in the midst of the turmoil and massacre, 
was calmly drawing geometrical figures in the sand; according to 
tradition, his last words were — after being run through the body by a 
Roman soldier: 'Pray, do not disturb my circles*. Apocryphal or not, 
that tradition symbolizes the Greek attitude to science as a quest 
transcending the mortal self. 



The Leaders of the Revolution 



After the long dark interlude which came to an end with the Pytha- 
gorean Renaissance in Italy around a.d. 1500, four men stand high- 
lighted on the stage of history: Copernicus, Tycho, Galileo, Kepler. 
They were the pioneers of the Scientific Revolution, the men on whose 
shoulders Newton stood: what do we know about their personal 
motives — which ultimately changed the face of this planet? 

We know least about Copernicus (1473-1543); as a person, he 
seems to have been a pale, insignificant figure, a timid Canon in the 
God-forsaken Prussian province of Varmia; his main ambition, as far 
as one can tell, was* to be left alone and not to incur derision or dis- 
favour. As a student in Italy, he had become acquainted with the 
Pythagorean idea of a sun-centred universe, and for the next thirty 
or forty years he elaborated his system in secret. Only in the last year 
before his death, at the age of seventy, did he agree, under pressure of 
his friends and superiors, to publish it; the first printed copy of his 
book On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres reached him on the 
day of his death. It is one of the dreariest and most unreadable books 
that made history, and remained practically unnoticed for the next 
fifty years, until Kepler took the idea up (the Church turned against 
it only eighty years after Copernicus's death). 

Copernicus was neither an original nor even a progressive thinker; 
he was, as Kepler later remarked, 'interpreting Ptolemy rather than 
nature'. He clung fanatically to the Aristotelian dogma that all planets 
must move in perfect circles at uniform speeds; the first impulse of his 
long labours originated in his discontent with the fact that in the 
Ptolemaic system they moved in perfect circles but not at uniform 
speed. It was the grievance of a perfectionist — in keeping with his 
crabbed, secretive, stingy character (which every Freudian would 
gleefully identify as the perfect 'anal' type). Once he had taken the 
Ptolemaic clockwork to pieces, he began to search for a useful hint 
how to put it together again; he found it in Aristarchus's heliocentric 
idea which at that time was much in the air.* It was not so much a 
new departure as a last attempt to patch up an outdated machinery 
by reversing the arrangement of its wheels. As a modern historian has 
said, the fact that the earth moves is 'almost an incidental matter in the 
system of Copernicus which, viewed geometrically, is just the old 
Ptolemaic pattern of the skies, with one or two wheels interchanged 
and one or two of them taken out.'* 

677 



678 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



For Tour times nine years', as he later confessed, Copernicus had 
worked in secret on his book, hugging it to his aching heart— it was 
the timid Canon s only refuge from a life of frustrations. It was his 
version of the harmony of the spheres. 

Tycho de Brahe (1546-1601) was an irascible, boastful Danish 
nobleman, trucculent and quixotic, born with a silver spoon in his 
mouth — to which a silver nose was added later, for his own had been 
sliced off in a duel with another noble Danish youth, who had the 
temerity to claim that he was the better mathematician of the two. 
Devotion to science could hardly assume more heroic proportions. 
Bufrwith Tycho everything was on a heroic scale: his figure (he kept, 
perhaps for the sake of contrast, a dwarf as a court jester); his eating 
and drinking, which led to his premature death from a burst bladder 
— because, with quixotic courtesy, he refused to leave the dinner 
table to pass water (even his pet animal, a temperamental elk, died of 
drinking too much beer); his quarrels with the kings he entertained, 
with the fellow astronomers whom he slandered, and with retainers 
whom he put in chains. On an even more gigantic scale were his 
observatories and the instruments — the likes of which the world had 
never seen — built on his island in the Sund. 

At fourteen Tycho had witnessed a partial eclipse of the sun, and 
'it struck him as something divine that men could know the motions 
of the stars so accurately that they were able a long rime beforehand to 
predict their places and relative positions'. 6 From then onward his 
course was set, and he became the 'Phoenix of Astronomy' — against 
the resistance of his family who thought such plumage unworthy of a 
nobleman. The decisive revelation for him was the predictability of 
astronomical events — in contrast to the unpredictability of a child's 
life among the headstrong Brahes (Tycho had been kidnapped from 
his cot and brought up by his Uncle Joerge, a squire and admiral). 
His passion for astronomy began much earlier than Copernicus' s and 
Kepler's, and took a direction almost opposite to theirs: it was not a 
passion for theory-making but for exact observation. Unlike those two, 
he was neither frustrated nor unhappy, merely irritated by the trivia- 
lity of a Danish nobleman's existence among 'horses, dogs, and luxury'. 

He took to astronomy not as an escape or metaphysical lifebelt but 
rather as a hobby—which then turned into the only thing held sacred 
by that Gargantuan heathen. 



APPENDIX II 



679 



'You cannot help it, Signor Sarsi, that it was granted to me alone to 
discover all the new phenomena in the sky and nothing to anybody 
else/ 6 The most conspicuous feature in the character of Galileo (1564- 
1642) and the cause of his tragic downfall was vanity—not the bois- 
terous and naive vanity of Tycho, but a hypersensitivity to criticism 
combined with sarcastic contempt for others: a fatal blend of genius 
plus arrogance minus humility. There seems to be not a trace here of 
mysticism, of 'oceanic feeling'; in contrast to Copernicus, Tycho, and 
Kepler, even to Newton and Descartes who came after him, Galileo 
is wholly and frighteningly modern in his consistently mechanistic 
philosophy. Hence his contemptuous dismissal in a single sentence of 
Kepler's explanation of the tides by the moons attraction: 'He 
[Kepler] has lent his ear and his assent to the moon's dominion over 
■the waters, to occult properties and such like fancuillezze.' 1 The occult 
little fancy he is deriding is Kepler's anticipation of Newtonian gravity. 

Where, then, in Galileo's personality is the sublime balance between 
self-asserting and self-transcending motives which I suggested as the 
true scientist's hallmark? I believe it to be easily demonstrable in his 
writings on those subjects on which his true greatness rests: the first 
discoveries with the telescope, the foundations of mechanics, and of a 
truly experimental science. Where that balance is absent — during the 
tragic years 1613-33, filled with poisonous polemics, spurious priority 
claims, and impassioned propaganda for a misleadingly oversimplified 
Copernican system— in that sad middle period of his life Galileo made 
no significant contribution either to astronomy or to mechanics. One 
might even say that he temporarily ceased to be a scientist— precisely 
because he was entirely dominated by self-asserting motives. The 
opposite kind of imbalance is noticeable in Kepler's periods of de- 
pression, when he entirely lost himself in mystic speculation, astrology, 
and number-lore. In both these diametrically opposed characters, un- 
sublimated residues of opposite kind temporarily dominated the 
field, upsetting the equihbrium and leading to scientific sterility. 

But in the balanced periods of Galileo, the eighteen happy years in 
Padua in which most of his epoch-making discoveries in the study of 
motion were made, and in the last years of resignation, when he com- 
pleted and revised the Dialogue Concerning Two New Sciences — in these 
creative periods we seem to be dealing with a different kind of per- 
son, patiently and painstakingly experimenting and meorking on the 
motions of the pendulum; on the free fall and descent along an in- 
clined plane of heavy bodies; on the flight of projectiles; the elasticity, 



68o 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



cohesion, and resistance of solid bodies, and the effects of percussion 
on them; on the buoyancy of 'things which float on the water', and 
a hundred related matters. Here we have a man absorbed in subjects 
much less spectacular and conducive to fame than the wonders of the 
Milky Way and the arguments about the earth's motion — yet delight- 
ing in his discoveries, of which only a select few friends and corres- 
pondents were informed; delighting in discovery for discovery's sake, 
in unravelling the laws of order hidden in the puzzling diversity of 
phenomena. 

That order was for Galileo, as it was for Kepler, a mathematical 
order: 'The book of nature is written in the mathematical language. 
Without its help it is impossible to comprehend a single word of it/ 8 
But unlike Kepler and the Pythagoreans, Galileo did not look at the 
'dance of numbers' through the eyes of a mystic. He was interested 
neither in number-lore nor in mathematics for its own sake — almost 
alone among the great scientists of his period, he made no mathematical 
discoveries. Quantitative measurements and formulations were for 
Galileo simply the most effective tools for laying bare the inherent 
rationality of nature. The belief in this rationality (and in the rationality 
of nature's creation, the human mind) was Galileo's religion and 
spiritual salvation — though he did not realize that it was a religion, 
based on an act of faith. 

His revolutionary methods of proving the rationality of the laws 
governing the universe was later called 'experimental philosophy' — 
and even later, by the much narrower terms 'experimental science' or 
'empirical science'. It was a fertile combination of experimenting and 
theorizing, which had been tentatively used by some of Galileo's 
precursors since the fourteenth century — but it was Galileo who 
elevated it to a modern technique and a philosophical programme. It 
was a monumental bisociation of the valid elements in Greek thought, 
transmitted by the Schoolmen (and particularly by the Occamists) 
on the one hand, and of the experimental knowledge of engineers, 
artisans, and instrument-makers on the other. The Dialogue Concerning 
Two New Sciences characteristically opens with a most unusual 
suggestion by Salviati (Galileo's mouthpiece): that, as a philosopher, 
he had much to learn from mechanics and craftsmen. 

Salviati: The constant activity which you Venetians display in your 
famous arsenal suggests to the studious mind a large field for investi- 
gation, especially that part of the work which involves mechanics; 



APPENDIX II 



for in this department all types of instruments and machines are con- 
stantly being constructed by many artisans, among whom there must 
be some who, partly by inherited experience and pardy by their own 
observations, have become highly expert and clever in explanation. 

Sagredo: You are quite right. Indeed, I myself, being curious by 
nature, frequendy visit this place for the mere pleasure of observing 
the work of those who, on account of their superiority over other 
artisans, we call 'first-rank men*. Conference with them has often 
helped me in the investigation of certain effects including not only 
those which are striking, but also those which are recondite and 
almost incredible. 9 

We are reminded of Pythagoras visiting the blacksmith's shop to 
discover the secret of vibrating chords—to learn from those dark, 
sweaty, and ignorant men about the harmony of the spheres. This is 
the point where hubris yields to humility; in his best and happiest 
moments, Galileo achieves not only this transition, but is also trans- 
formed from a scientist into a poet. In the midst of his formidable 
polemical onslaught on the Platonist dualism of despair — which con- 
trasted the perfect, immutable, crystalline heavens to the earthy 
corruption of generation and decay — his imagination and language 
suddenly grow wings: 

Sagredo: I cannot without great wonder, nay more, disbelief, hear 
it being attributed to natural bodies as a great honour and perfection 
that they are impassible, immutable, inalterable, etc.: as, conversely, I 
hear it esteemed a great imperfection to be alterable, generable, 
mutable, etc. It is my opinion that the Earth is very noble and 
admirable by reason of the many and different alterations, mutations, 
generations, etc., which incessantly occur in it. And if, without being 
subject to any alteration, it had been all one vast heap of sand, or a 
mass of jade, or ... an immense globe of crystal, wherein nothing 
had ever grown, altered, or changed, I should have esteemed it a 
wretched lump of no benefit to the Universe, a mass of idleness. . . . 
What greater folly can be imagined than to call gems, silver, and 
gold noble and earth and soil base? ... If there were as great a 
scarcity of earth as there is of jewels and precious metals, there would 
be no king who would not gladly give a heap of diamonds and rubies 
... to purchase only so much earth as would suffice to plant a 
jessarnine in a little pot or to set a tangerine in it, that he might see it 



682 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



sprout, grow up, and bring forth goodly leaves, fragrant flowers, 
and delicate fruit. . . . These men who so extol inconuptibility, 
inalterability, etc., speak thus, I believe, out of the great desire they 
have to live long and for fear of death, not considering that, if men 
had been immortal, they would not have had to come into the 
world. These people deserve to meet with a Medusa's head that 
would transform them into statues of diamond and jade that so 
they might become more perfect than they are. 10 

In another work, Galileo wrote a charming and profound allegory 
on 'the motives, methods, and limitations of the 'experimental philo- 
sophy' which he had created. The work is II Saggiatore, 'The Assayer' 
— which has only recendy been translated into English, presumably 
because most of it consists of a querulous, scientifically worthless 
polemics against the Jesuit scholar Grassi on the subject of comets 
(which Galileo insisted on treating as optical illusions — largely because 
Tycho and Grassi held the opposite views). Yet hidden in this nasty 
bunch of nettles are flowers of rare beauty: 

Once upon a time, in a very lonely place, there lived a man en- 
dowed by nature with extraordinary curiosity and a very pene- 
trating mind. For a pastime he raised birds, whose songs he much 
enjoyed; and he observed with great admiration the happy contri- 
vance by which they could transform at will the very air they 
breathed into a variety of sweet songs. 

One night this man chanced to hear a delicate song close to his 
house, and being unable to connect it with anything but some small 
bird he set out to capture it. "When he arrived at a road he found a. 
shephered boy who was blowing into a kind of hollow stick while 
moving his fingers about on the wood, thus drawing from it a 
variety of notes similar to those of a bird, though by a quite different 
method. Puzzled, but impelled by his natural curiosity, he gave the 
boy a calf in exchange for this flute and returned to solitude. But 
realizing that if he had not chanced to meet the boy he would never 
have learned of the existence of a new method of forming musical 
notes and the sweetest songs, he decided to travel to distant places 
in the hope of meeting with some new adventure. 

Subsequently, the man discovered that there are many other ways 
of producing musical notes — from strings and organs, to the swift 



APPENDIX II 



683 



vibrations on the wings of mosquitoes and the 'sweet and sonorous 
shrilling of crickets by snapping their wings together, though they 
cannot fly at all'. But there was an ultimate disappointment waiting 
for him: 

Well, after this man had come to believe that no more ways of 
forming tones could possibly exist . . . when, I say, this man believed 
he had seen everything, he suddenly found himself once more 
plunged deeper into ignorance and bafflement than ever. For having 
captured in his hands a cicada, he failed to diminish its strident noise 
either by closing its mouth or stopping its wings, yet he could not 
see it move the scales that covered its body, or any other thing. At 
last he lifted up the armour of its chest and there he saw some thin 
hard ligaments beneath; thinking the sound might come from their 
vibration, he decided to break them in order to silence it. But 
nothing happened until his needle drove too deep, and transfixing 
the creature he took away its life with its voice, so that he was still 
unable to determine whether the song had originated in those liga- 
ments. And by this experience his knowledge was reduced to 
diffidence, so that when asked how sounds were created he used to 
answer tolerantly that although he knew a few ways, he was sure 
that many more existed which were not only unknown but un- 
imaginable. 11 

Hubris is temporarily submerged by humility. Galileo was the first 
of a race of modern experimental scientists convinced of the infalli- 
bility of their 'exact empirical methods'; in fact he created the type. 
It comes as a surprise to hear him talk about things 'not only unknown 
but unimaginable'. But this dtimate modesty, derived from a sense 
of wonder close to mysticism, is found in all great scientists — even 
if hidden by an arrogant facade, and allowed to express itself only on 
rare occasions. 

About Kepler I have said enough, in this book and elsewhere, to 
show that mysticism was the mainspring of his fantastically laborious 
life — starting with the analogy between God the Father and the Sun, 
continued in his lifelong conviction that the universe was built around 
the frames of the five Pythagorean solids, and that the planetary motions 
were regulated by the laws of musical harmony. But his mystic con- 
victions, and the disarrningly child-like streak in his character, did not 



684 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



prevent him from casting horoscopes for money — however much he 
despised himself for it; from indulging in naive snobbery, and quarrel- 
ling like a fish-wife with the overbearing Tycho. His vanity had a 
perverse twist: he was very proud of himself when his astrological 
forecasts of a cold spell and an invasion by the Turks came true; but 
towards his real discoveries he was completely indifferent, and he was 
astonishingly devoid of professional jealousy. He naively expected the 
same of other astronomers; and when Tycho's heirs delayed publi- 
cation of his priceless collection of observational data, Kepler simply 
stole the material to put it to proper use — his ethics did not include 
respect for private property in Urania's domains. 

"When Kepler had completed the foundations of modern astronomy 
by his Third Law, he uttered a long Eureka cry: 

The heavenly motions are nothing but a continuous song for 
several voices (perceived by the intellect, not by the ear); a music 
which, through discordant tensions, through sincopes and cadenzas, 
as it were (as men employed them in imitation of those natural 
discords), progresses towards certain pre-designed, quasi six-voiced 
clausuras, and thereby sets landmarks in the immeasurable flow of 
time. It is, therefore, no longer surprising that man, in imitation of 
his creator, has at last discovered the art of figured song, which was 
unknown to the ancients. Man wanted to reproduce the continuity 
of cosmic time within a short hour, by an artful symphony for 
several voices, to obtain a sample test of the delight of the Divine 
Creator in His works, and to partake of his joy by making music 
in the imitation of God. 12 

Here we have the perfect union of the two drives: the vain-glorious 
ego purged by cosmic awareness — ekstasis followed by katharsis. 

Newton, Monster and Saint 

From the end of the seventeenth century onward the scene becomes 
too crowded for a systematic inquiry into individual motivations; 
however, I have said enough to suggest the basic pattern — and though 
the character of the times changed, that pattern rernained essentially 
the same. 

Look at Newton, for instance: he has been idolized and his character 



APPENDIX II 



685 



bowdlerized to such an extent (above all in the Victorian standard 
biography by Brewster) that the phenomenal mixture of monster and 
saint out of which it was compounded was all but lost from sight. On 
the one hand he was deeply religious and believed — with Kepler and 
Bishop Usher — that the world had been created in 404 B.C.; that the 
convenient design of the solar system — for instance, all planetary orbits 
lying in a single plane — was proof of the existence of God, who not 
only created the universe but also kept it in order by correcting from 
time to time the irregularities which crept into the heavenly motions 
— and by preventing the universe from collapsing altogether under the 
pressure of gravity. On the other hand, he fulminated at any criticism 
of his work, whether justified or not, displayed symptoms of persecu- 
tion mania, and in his priority fight with Leibniz over the invention 
of the calculus he used the perfidious means of carefully drafting in his 
own hand the findings, in his own favour, of the 'impartial* committee 
set up by the Royal Society. To quote M. Hoskin: 

No one supposes that the committee set up by the Royal Society of 
which Newton had then been president for several years, was im- 
partial. But we can only realize the extent of Newton's share in its 
conclusions when we examine a much-corrected draft summary of 
what were to be the findings of the committee. The draft is written 
in Newton's own hand, and it is fascinating to watch Newton 
debating with himself whether the committee ought to say 'We are 
satisfied that he [Newton] had invented the method of fluxions 
before' 1669, or whether it would sound better if they said 'We find 
that he invented the method of fluxions before' 1669; or deciding 
that to say 'We are satisfied that Mr. Newton was the first author of 
this method' was too terse, and that several more lines of explanation 
ought to be inserted before the conclusion 'for which reason we 
reckon Mr. Newton the first inventor'. 13 

Here is pettiness on a heroic scale — combined with a heroic vision 
of the universe worked out in minute detail: in other words, the 
mixture as before. 

The Mysticism of Franklin 

As we move on into the eighteenth century the towering genius of 
Benjamin Franklin sticks out of it like his Hghtning rod. Printer, 



686 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



journalist, pamphleteer, politician, wire-puller, diplomat, and states- 
man; pioneer of electricity, founder of the physics of liquid surfaces, 
discoverer of the properties of marsh gas, designer of the chevaux de 
frise which halted the advance of the British fleet on the Delaware, 
inventor of bifocal spectacles and of improved fireplaces, advocate of 
watertight bulkheads on ships and of chimney-shafts for the ventila- 
tion in mines— the list could be continued. And yet this 'first civilized 
American', as one of his biographers called him, 14 for all his incompar- 
able clarity of thought and lucidity of style, had formed his meta- 
physical outlook at the age of sixteen when he read a book by Tryon, 
a member of the group of British Pythagoreans. The members of this 
sect were chiefly known for their vegetarianism because, like the 
ancient Brotherhood, they believed in the transmigration of souls and 
wished to avoid the risk of feasting on some reincarnation of a human 
being. Franklin became a convert to vegetarianism and believed in 
transmigration to the end of his life. At the age of twenty-two he 
composed a Pythagorean epitaph for himself; at the age of eighty-four, 
the year of his death, he ordered that it should appear, unchanged, on 
his tomb. It reads: 

The Body 
Of 

BENJAMIN FRANKLIN 

Printer 

(Like the Cover of an Old Book 
Its Contents Torn Out 
And Stript of its Lettering and Gilding) 
Lies Here, Food for Worms. 
But the Work Shall Not Be Lost 
For It Will (As He Believed) Appear Once More 
In a New and More Elegant Edition 
Revised and Corrected 
By 

The Author 

His conviction that souls are immortal, that they cannot be des- 
troyed and are merely transformed in their migrations led him, by 
way of analogy, to one of the first clear formulations of the law of the 
conservation of matter. The following quotations will make the 
connection clear: 



APPENDIX II 



687 



The power of man relative to matter seems limited to the dividing 
it, or mixing the various kinds of it, or changing its form and 
appearance by differing compositions of it, but does not extend to 
the making or creating of new matter, or annihilating the old. 

This was written when he was seventy-eight. The following was 
written one year later: 

I say that when I see nothing annihilated, and not even a drop of 
water wasted, I cannot suspect the annihilation of souls, or believe 
that He will suffer the daily waste of millions of minds ready made 
that now exist, and put Himself to the continual trouble of making 
new ones. Thus finding myself to exist in the world, I believe I 
shall, in some shape or other, always exist. 

The argument seems to indicate that what one might call the prin- 
ciple of the 'conservation of souls' was derived from that of the 'con- 
servation of matter'. But in fact it was the other way round. As 
Kepler had transformed the Holy Trinity into the trinity of Sun — 
Force — Planets, so in Franklin's case, too, a mystical conviction gave 
birth, by analogy, to a scientific theory. And could there be a more 
charming combination of man's vanity with his transcendental 
aspirations than to pray for a 'more elegant, revised, and corrected 
edition of one's proud and humble self? 

The Fundamentalism of Faraday 

The nineteenth-century landscape is crowded with giants; I shall 
briefly comment on four of them. In the physical sciences Faraday and 
Maxwell are probably the greatest: Einstein, who ought to know, has 
put them on a par with Galileo and Newton; and Crowther, who 
wrote short biographies of both, makes the fine distinction of calling 
Faraday 'the greatest physicist of the nineteenth century' and Maxwell 
'the greatest theoretical physicist of the nineteenth century'. To these 
let me add, from the biological sciences, Darwin and Pasteur, to make 
up a foursome. 

Faraday, whom Tyndall described as 'the great mad child', was the 
most inhuman character of the four: the son of a sectarian blacksmith, 
self-taught, with a passionate temperament which was denied all 



688 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



human outlets except religion and science. This was probably the cause 
of the protracted episode of mental disorder, comparable to Newton s, 
which began when he was forty-nine. Characteristic of the coyness of 
science historians is the Encyclopaedia Britannicas reference to Faraday's 
clinical insanity: 'In 1841 he found that he required rest, and it 
was not till 1845 that he entered on his second great period of 
research/ 

At thirty, shordy after his marriage— which remained childless- 
Faraday joined an extreme fundamentalist, ascetic sect, the 'Sande- 
manians', to which his father and his young wife belonged, and 
whose services he had attended since infancy. The Sandemanians con- 
sidered practically every human activity as a sin — including even the 
Victorian virtue of saving money; they washed each other's feet, 
intermarried, and refused to proselytize; on one occasion they sus- 
pended Faraday's membership because he had to dine, by royal 
command, with the Queen at Windsor, and thus had to miss the con- 
gregation s Sunday service. It took many years before he was forgiven 
and re-elected an Elder of the sect. 

In his later years Faraday withdrew almost completely from social 
contacts, refusing even the presidency of the Royal Academy because 
of its too worldly disposition. The inhuman self-denials imposed by 
his creed made Faraday canalize his ferocious vitality into the pursuit of 
science, which he regarded as the only other permissible form of 
divine worship. 

The Metaphysics of Maxwell 

James Clerk Maxwell was of an altogether different, balanced, and 
happy disposition. In his case, too, religious belief became a spur to 
scientific activity, but in more subtle ways. He was a double-faced 
giant: he completed the classical edifice of the Newtonian universe, 
but he also inaugurated the era of what one might call the 'surrealistic 
physics of the twentieth century. 

As Kepler had embraced the Copernican system 'for physical or if 
you prefer, metaphysical reasons', so Maxwell confessed that the 
theories of his later period were formed 'in that hidden and dimmer 
region where Thought weds Fact. Does not the way to it pass through 
the very den of the metaphysician, strewed with the remains of former 
explorers and abhorred by every man of science?' 

The metaphysician in Maxwell had by that time long outgrown the 



APPENDIX II 



689 



crude materialism of mid-nineteen. th-cenrury science, and its equally 
crude forms of Christianity. Maxwell's religious beliefs were con- 
ceived in symbolic, almost abstract, terms; they compared to Faraday's 
fundamentalist creed as his abstract equations of the electro-magnetic 
field compare with the lines of force which to Faraday were 'as real 
as matter*. The connection between Maxwell's religious and scientific 
views is indeed just as intimate as in the case of Franklin or Kepler. 
I have mentioned before how, once he had arrived at his twenty 
general equations, Maxwell kicked away the scaffolding from under 
him — the physical model of vortices in the ether— and thus inaugurated 
the post-Newtonian era in physics, with its renunciation of all models 
and representations, in terms of sensory experience. 

There is a characteristic passage in one of his letters to his 
wife: 

*I can always have you with me in my mind — why should we not 

have our Lord always before us in our minds If we had seen Him 

in the flesh we should not have known Him any better, perhaps not so 
well/ In another letter to his wife, he says that he had been re-reading 
Ephesians vi. This is not a very inspiring chapter, dealing with re- 
lations between parents and children, masters and servants; yet Max- 
well comments: 'Here is more about family relations. There are things 
which have meanings so deep that if we follow on to know them we 
shall be led into great mysteries of divinity. If we reverence them, we 
shall even see beyond their first aspect a spiritual meaning. For God 
speaks to us more plainly in these bonds of our life than in anything 
that we can understand/ 

J. G. Crowther — who, as an adherent of the Marxist philosophy 
of history can hardly be accused of mystic inclinations — remarks on 
this curious passage: 'Here Maxwell accepts material relationships with 
the belief that acquaintance with them will lead to spiritual under- 
standing. He proceeds from the contemplation of material relation- 
ships to spiritual truth, from the model of the electro-magnetic field 
to the equations. The influence of the New Testament is seen also in 
hi sinterpretation of self-sacrifice. During the last years of his life, his 
wife was an invalid. He nursed her personally with the most assiduous 
care. At one period he did not sleep in a bed for three weeks, though 
he delivered his lectures and superintended the laboratory as usual. 
The modernity of Maxwell's science, and the antiquity of his sociology 
and religion appear incongruous. But it may be noted that though 



($90 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



his views on sociology and religion were antique, they were superior 
to those of nearly all his scientific, contemporaries. He at least thought 
about these problems, and if he was unable to find modern answers 
to them, he learned enough of them to avoid the intellectual phili- 
stinism of his time/ 

It was the time when Berthelot proclaimed: 'The world today has 
no longer any mystery for us'; when Haeckel had solved all his 
Weltratsel and A. R. Wallace, in his book on The Wonderful Century, 
declared that the nineteenth century had produced Wenty-four 
fundamental advances, as against only fifteen for all the rest of recorded 
history*. The Philistines everywhere were 'dizzy with success* — to 
quote once more Stalin's famous phrase of 1932, when factories and 
power dams were going up at great speed while some seven million 
peasants were dying of starvation. It had indeed been a wonderful 
century for natural philosophy, but at its end moral philosophy had 
reached one of its lowest ebbs in history — and Maxwell was well 
aware of this. He was aware of the limitations of a rigidly deterministic 
outlook; it was he who, in his revolutionary treatment of the dy- 
namics of gases, replaced mechanical causation by a statistical approach 
based on the theory of probability— a decisive step towards quantum 
physics and the principle of mdeterminism. Moreover, he was fully 
aware of the far-reaching implications of this approach, not only for 
physics but also for philosophy: 'It is probable that important results 
will be obtained by the application of this the statistical method, which 
is as yet litde known and is not familiar to our minds. If the actual 
history of Science had been different, and if the scientific doctrines 
most familiar to us had been those which must be expressed in this 
way, it is possible that we might have considered the existence of a 
certain kind of contingency a self-evident truth, and treated the 
doctrine of philosophical necessity as a mere sophism.' 15 

Already at the age of twenty-four he had realized the Hmitations of 
materialist philosophy: 'The only laws of matter are those which our 
minds must fabricate, and the only laws of mind are fabricated for it 
by matter.' 16 Twenty years later, at the height of his fame, he gave full 
rein to his hobby, satirical verse, to ridicule the shallow materialism 
of the Philistines. The occasion was the famous presidential address by 
John Tyndall to the British Association meeting in Belfast. TyncLall, 
a generous soul but a narrow-minded philosopher, attacked the 
'theologians' and extolled the virtues of the brave new materialist 
creed. Maxwell's satire is still valid today: 



APPENDIX II 



691 



In the very beginning of science, 

the parsons, who managed things then, 
Being handy with hammer and chisel, 

made gods in the likeness of men; 
Till Commerce arose, and at length 

some men of exceptional power 
Supplanted both demons and gods by 

the atoms, which last to this hour. 

From nothing comes nothing, they told us, 

nought happens by chance but by fate; 
There is nothing but atoms and void, 

all else is mere whims out of date! 
Then why should a man curry favour 

with beings who cannot exist, 
To compass some petty promotion 

in nebulous kingdoms of mist? . . . 

First, then, let us honour the atom, 

so lively, so wise, and so small; 
The atomists next let us praise, Epicurus, 

Lucretius, and all; 
Let us damn with faint praise Bishop Butler, 

in whom many atoms combined 
To form that remarkable structure, 

it pleased him to call — his mind. 

In another poem he wrote: 

. . . While down the stream of Evolution 

We drift, expecting no solution 

But that of the survival of the fittest. 

Till, in the twilight of the gods, 

When earth and sun are frozen clods, 

When, all its energy degraded, 

Matter to aether shall have faded; 

We, that is, all the work we've done, 

As waves in aether, shall for ever run 

In ever-widening spheres through heavens beyond the sun. 



6*92 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



And thus in the nineteenth century's most advanced scientific mind 
we meet once again, in a sublimated and ratified form, the ancient 
belief in the indestructibility of the numinous. 

The Atheism of Darwin 

Dr. Robert Darwin was an atheist who chose for his son Charles the 
career of a country clergyman — simply because this seemed to be the 
most gentlemanly occupation for a youth so obviously devoid of any 
particular ambition and intellectual excellence. Charles himself fully 
agreed with this choice. As a student at Cambridge he had read Pearson 
on the Creeds, and had come to the conclusion that he did not 'in the 
least doubt the strict and literal truth of every word in the Bible'. 17 
Even during the voyage of the Beagle he amused the officers by his 
naive orthodoxy, and he was deeply shocked when one of his ship- 
mates expressed doubts concerning the biblical account of the Flood. 
Such a rigid fundamentalist belief could not be reconciled with specu- 
lations about the origin of species; his loss of faith coincided with his 
conversion to the evolutionary theory. For a while he fought a rear- 
guard action against his doubts by day-dreaming about the discovery 
of old manuscript texts which would confirm the historical truth of 
the Gospels; but this did not help much. In the months following his 
return from the voyage the new theory was born and his faith in 
religion was dead. 

Darwin's arguments against religion were as crude and literal- 
minded as his belief had been: 'the miracles were not credible to any 
sane man'; the Old Testament gave a 'manifestly false history of the 
world, with the -Tower of Babel, the rainbow as a sign, etc., etc/ 18 
He took strong exception to the 'damnable doctrine' that non-believers, 
'and this would include my Father, Brother and almost all my best 
friends', will be everlastingly punished. As for Hinduism or Buddhism, 
and the persistence of religious aspirations throughout human history, 
he explained them— in an oddly Lamarckian argument — as the result 
of 'inherited experience*. 

Nor must we overlook the probability of the constant inculcation 
of a belief in God on the minds of children by producing so strong 
and perhaps an inherited effect on their brains, not as yet fully 
developed, that it would be as difficult for them to throw off their 



APPENDIX II 



693 



belief in God, as for a monkey to throw off its instinctive fear and 
hatred of a snake. 

Before the great turning point in his life, 'the nuclear discovery' of 
his theory, he had not only been an orthodox believer, but at least on 
one occasion, in the grandeur of the Brazilian forest, he had also felt 
that quasi-mystical, 'deep inward experience 5 that there must be more 
in man than 'the mere breath of his body.' 1 ® But after the turning 
point such experiences did not recur — and he himself wondered some- 
times whether he was not like a man who had become colour-blind. 
At the same decisive period, when he was about thirty, Darwin suffered, 
in his own words, a 'curious and lamentable loss of the higher aesthetic 
tastes'. An attempt to re-read Shakespeare bored him 'to the point of 
physical nausea'. 30 He preferred popular novels of the sentimental 
kind — so long as they had a happy ending. In his autobiography he 
complained: 

But now for many years I cannot endure to read a line of poetry. 
My mind seems to have become a kind of machine for grinding 
general laws out of a large collection of facts, but why this should 
have caused the atrophy of that part of the brain on which the higher 
tastes depend, I cannot conceive. The loss of these tastes is a loss of 
happiness, and may possibly be injurious to the intellect, and more 
probably to the moral character, by enfeebling the emotional part 
of our nature. 

Darwin's 'religious tastes', if the expression may be permitted, had 
been of an equally unsubtle nature. 'His sensibility was of that inverted 
order that is unable to extend to human beings the same sympathy and 
respect it has for animals. As a zoologist Darwin was naturally more at 
home in the realm of animal behaviour than of philosophy. This may 
be why so much of his discussion of religion, morality and aesthetics 
seems painfully naive/ 21 The concept of 'religious experience' did not 
mean to Darwin what it did to MaxweE — the intuition of an 'unknown 
reality which held the secret of infinite space and enternal time'; it 
meant to him believing the story told in Genesis, and also in eternal 
hellfire. In The Descent of Man, he had denied that language was a unique 
attribute of man because animals too use sounds and gestures to com- 
municate emotions. This confusion of sign and symbol equally pervades 
his discussions of religion. In his youth he had believed in the 'strict and 



694 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



literal truth of every word in the Bible'; later on he considered himself 
an atheist because he did not believe in the Tower of Babel. Neither 
attitude has much relevance to the unconscious, inner motivation of his 
work. More relevant is the fact that the kind of undefinable intuition 
which he had experienced in the Brazilian forest went out of his life at 
the same time as the 'atrophy of the higher tastes' set in. This was at the 
time when he made his basic discovery. The remaining forty odd years 
were spent on the heroic labours of its elaboration. 

Darwin, as we have seen, was like Copernicus, essentially a one- 
idea man. Each had his 'nuclear inspiration' early in life, and spent the 
rest of his life working it out — the ratio of inspiration to perspiration 
being heavily in favour of the second. Both lacked the many-sidedness, 
that universality of interest and amazing multitude of achievement in 
unrelated fields of research which characterized Kepler, Newton, 
Descartes, Franklin, Faraday, Maxwell, and hundreds of lesser but 
equally versatile geniuses. It is perhaps no coincidence that both Darwin 
and Copernicus, after the decisive turning point when their course 
was set, led a life of duty, devotion to task, rigorous self-discipline, and 
spiritual desiccation. It looks as if the artesian wells of their inspiration 
had been replaced by a mechanical water supply kept under pressure 
by sheet power of will. 

In Darwin's case, the magnitude of this power must be measured 
against the handicap of forty years of chronic ill health, which also 
afflicted his large family. The sense of duty which kept him going 
became his,, true religion. After the publication of the Origin and the 
Descent, he became one of the most celebrated personalities in Europe, 
but he continued to lead the same rigorously scheduled life, without 
allowing himself to bask in the sun, without getting spoilt or dis- 
tracted from his work. 'While others used the prestige of Darwinism 
to promote their social or political views, Darwin himself forebore 
doing so;' aia and when Marx proposed to dedicate to him the English 
translation of Das Kapital Darwin refused the honour. 

His last years were spent in churning out a number of technical 
books and papers; his very last book was called The Formation of Vege- 
table Mould through the Action of Worms. He had started this research on 
earthworms at twenty-eight, after his return from the voyage of the 
Beagle; now, after this momentous detour, he finished it at the age of 
seventy-two, one year before his death. It is a measure of the enormous 
vogue which Darwin enjoyed that the worm book, in spite of its un- 
prepossessing tide, sold eight thousand five hundred copies in the first 



APPENDIX II 



69S 



three years after publication— which would be quite a respectable 
success for a novel in our own days. 

On one occasion in his late years Darwin was asked to state his 
opinion on religion. He answered that while the subject of God was 
'beyond the scope of man's intellect', his moral obligations were 
nevertheless clear: 'Man can do his duty.* On another occasion — in an 
addendum to his autobiography — he explained that, even without a 
belief in God, a man 'can have for his rule of life . . . only to follow 
those impulses and instincts which are the strongest or which seem to 

him the best ones By degrees it will be more intolerable to hiir» to 

obey his sensuous passions rather than his highest impulses, which when 
rendered habitual may be almost called instincts. His reason may 
occasionally tell him to act in opposition to the opinion of others, 
whose approbation he will then not receive; but he will still have the 
solid satbfaction of knowing that he has followed his innermost judge 
or conscience.' He never realized that statements of this kind destroyed 
the very foundations of any strictly materialistic and deterministic 
philosophy, including his own — according to which human morality 
was derived from innate 'social instincts'. 'It can hardly be disputed', 
he wrote in his disastrous controversy against Mill, 'that the social 
feelings are instinctive or innate in the lower animals: and why should 
they not be so in men?' But from what source, then, would man derive 
the power to follow those instincts 'which seemed to him the best ones', 
to obey his 'highest impulses' as opposed to his 'sensuous passions'; 
and even 'to act in opposition to the opinion of others'? The source of 
that power must evidendy be the 'innermost judge, or conscience' — 
concepts of a transcendental nature and quite heretical from the point 
of view of a purely materialist world-view. 

It has been said that Darwin's philosophizing was 'painfully naive*. 
Yet his life bore witness, not to his philosophical rationalizations, but 
to his transcendental beliefs — he was a croyant malgri lui. The proof is 
in the closing passages of his two great books: 

It is interesting to contemplate a tangled bank, clothed with many 
plants of many kinds, with bkds singing on the bushes, with various 
insects flitting about, and with worms crawling through the damp 
earth, and to reflect that these elaborately constructed forms, so dif- 
ferent from each other, and dependent upon each other in so complex 
a manner, have all been produced by laws acting around us. . . . 
Thus, from the war of nature, from famine and death, the most 



6g6 THE ACT OF CREATION 

exalted object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the 
production of the higher animals, directly follows. There is grandeur 
in this view of life, with its several powers, having been originally 
breathed by the creator into a few forms or into one; and that, whilst 
this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, 
from so simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most 
wonderful have been, and are being evolved. 22 

Man may be excused for feeling some pride at having risen, though 
not through his own exertions, to the very summit of the organic 
scale; and the fact of his having thus risen, instead of having been 
aboriginally placed there, may give him hope for a still higher 
destiny in the distant future. But we are not here concerned with 
hopes or fears, only with the truth as far as our reason permits us to 
discover it; and I have given the evidence to the best of my ability. 
"We must, however, acknowledge, as it seems to me, that man with 
all his noble qualities, with sympathy which feels for the most 
debased, with benevolence which extends not only to other men but 
to the humblest living creature, with his god-like intellect which has 
penetrated into the movements and constitution of the solar system 
— with all these exalted powers — Man still bears in his bodily frame 
the indelible stamp of his lowly origin. 28 

Here is humility and wonder, and a sense of participation which 
transcends not only the individual self but the collective pride of 
homo sapiens. 

The Faith of Pasteur 

Louis Pasteur's character and life is an almost perfect illustration of 
ambition, pride, vanity, self-righteousness, combined with self-sacri- 
fice, charity, humility, romanticism, and religion, to make a happy 
balance of opposites. At the height of his fame, Pasteur related with 
evident relish that at an official reception the Queen of Denmark and 
the Queen of Greece had broken etiquette by walking up to him to 
pay their homage. But he also spent several months every year for 
five years in the mountains of Cevennes, to find a cure for an epidemic 
disease of silkworms. When he had found its cause, and saved the 
French silk manufacturing industry from ruin, the Minister of Agri- 
culture sent him for examination three lots of eggs which a famous 



APPENDIX II 



<597 



silk-worm breeder was distributing throughout the country, ignoring 
Pasteur's recommendations of his method to obtain healthy strains. 
Pasteur replied: 

M. le Ministre — These three samples of seed are worthless They 

will in every instance succumb to corpuscle disease For my part 

I feel so sure of what I affirm, that I shall not even trouble to test, by 
hatching them, the samples which you have sent me. I have thrown 
them into the river. 

And to a sceptical breeder, he wrote about the same time: 

M. le Marquis — You do not know the first word of my investiga- 
tions, of their results, of the principles which they have established, 
and of their practical implications. Most of them you have not read 
. . . and the others you did net understand. 

in his polemics against scientific adversaries he used the same im- 
passioned language — the style sometimes reminds one of Galileo. But, 
unlike Galileo, he engaged in controversy only after he had established 
his case beyond all possible doubt in his experimental laboratory, and 
had hardened it by countless painstaking repetitions. As a result, 
again unlike Galileo, he was invariably, and to his opponents infuria-- 
tingly, proven right. He even wrote an article in the Galilean dialogue 
style for a wine-growers trade journal. The dialogue was meant to be 
a report of Pasteur's conversation with the mayor of Vblnay, M. 
Boillot — which resulted in the conversion of M. Boillot to the Pas- 
teurization of Burgundy wines. This epic dialogue starts with: 

Pasteur: Do you heat your wines, M. Make? 

M. Boillot: No sir. ... I have been told that heating may affect 
unfavourably the taste of our great wines. 

Pasteur: Yes, I know. In fact it has been said that to heat these 
wines is equivalent to an amputation* Will you be good enough, M. 
Maire, to follow me into my experimental cellar? 

For the next two pages M. Boillot is shown what's what. He has to 
taste the treated and untreated wines of a score of vintages and vine- 
yards, until he capitulates and admits the superior quality of the 



698 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



pasteurized wines — including those which came from his own vine- 
yards: 

M. Boillot: I am overwhelmed. I have the same impression as if I 
were seeing you pouring gold into our country. 

Pasteur: There you are, my dear countrymen, busy with politics, 
elections, superficial reading of newspapers but neglecting the serious 
books which deal with matters of importance to the welfare of the 
country. . . . And yet, M. Maire, had you read with attention, you 
could have recognized that everything I wrote was based on precise 
facts, official reports, devastations by the most competent experts, 
whereas my opponents had nothing to offer but assertions without 
proof. 

M. Boillot: ... Do not worry, Monsieur. From now on I shall no 
longer believe those who contradict you and I shall attend to the 
matter of heating the wines as soon as I return to Volnay. 24 

Pasteur had grown up in the Arbois; he was a connoisseur of wine, 
and he despised beer. But after the defeat of France by the Prussians 
in 1871, he considered it his patriotic duty to improve the quality of 
French beer— with the declared intention to produce a 'biere de la 
revanche' , superior to the Germans* cherished national drink. He even 
invaded, armed with his microscope, the sacred premises of Whit- 
bread's in London; his laconic account of that historic visit makes one 
appreciate the drama that took place. 

Pasteur was reverently handed two casks of the famed brew. He put 
a drop of one under the microscope and — 'I immediately recognized 
three or four disease filaments in the microscopic £dd. These findings 
made me bold enough to state in the presence of the master-brewer, 
who had been called in, that these beers would rapidly spoil . . . and 
that they must already be somewhat defective in taste, on which point 
everyone agreed, although after long hesitation. I attributed this 
hesitation to the natural reserve of a manufacturer whom one compels 
to declare that his merchandise is not beyond reproach. "When I re- 
turned to the same brewery less than a week later, I learned that the 
managers had made haste to acquire a microscope.' It was not the least 
of the rmracles that Pasteur achieved. 

Silkworms, wine, beer — and before that studies on the souring of 
milk, the turning of wine into vinegar, of vinegar into acid, of beet- 
sugar into alcohol. *Louis ... is now up to his neck in beet-juice*, 



APPENDIX II 



699 



Madame Pasteur complained in a letter. Each, of these campaigns was 
conducted with the same crusading zeal, the same showmanship, the 
same patience and precision in method. Pasteur's father had been a 
sergeant in the Napoleonic army; after Waterloo he had become a 
tanner in the Arbois. He had probably heard the Emperor's famous 
speech at the Pyramids: 'Soldiers, from these summits forty centuries 
look down upon you/ Louis Pasteur, crouching with his microscope 
on top of one of the gigantic vats at Whitbread's, may have spoken 
the same words to the awe-stricken master-brewers. 

And that is hardly an exaggeration, for in Pasteur's work we see 
clearly how the trivial by a short step can lead to the momentous, 
and how the two are inextricably mixed up in the scientist's mind and 
motives. One of the landmarks of science is the publication, in 1877, 
of Pasteur's book with the unprepossessing tide, Etudes sur la Biere, 
Ses Maladies, Les Causes qui les Provoquent. Procede pour la Rendre 
Inalterable . . . followed, almost as an afterthought, by . . . Avec me 
Thiorie Nouvelle de la Fermentation. It contains the first complete 
statement of Pasteur's revolutionary discovery that yeast and all other 
agents which cause fermentation and putrefaction, are living beings of 
very small size — that is, micro-organisms, germs. In a similar way, his 
work on the silkworms had confirmed that contagious diseases were 
caused by microbes of different varieties. The principles of steriliza- 
tion and partial sterilization (pasteurization'); of immunization, of 
antisepsis and asepsis; our knowledge of the causative agents of 
disease and of the general conditions which determine the organism's 
receptivity for those agents; lasdy, the 'domestication of microbes 
and their use as antibiotics — all this grew out of Pasteur's often far- 
fetched researches into some specific technical problem, undertaken 
for apparently trivial motives. 

Yet there were other motivational factors at work which lent urgency 
and drive to each of these technical research projects, from the earliest 
(On the Turning of Milk) onward: the intuitive vision of a grand unitary 
design underlying all biochemical transformations, a design which 
embraced not only the utilization of energy by living organisms in 
health and disease, but also—as we shall see in a moment— the secret 
of the origin of life. And finally, each particular project— whether it 
was concerned with silkworms, wine, or the inoculation of cattle 
against anthrax— though carried through with consummate show- 
manship and a Gallic flourish, was nevertheless a crusade for the 
public benefit; the resulting self-gratification was no more than a 



700 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



delicious by-product. Through the same interaction of the trivial and 
monumental which led to Pasteur's intellectual triumphs, the pro- 
ponent of the hihe de la revanche became the greatest benefactor of 
mankind since Hippocrates. 

I have mentioned Pasteur's hope to discover 'the secret of life*. 
This is to be taken quite literally. 

The earliest discovery of Pasteur, and for him the most exciting in 
all his life, was the asymmetry of molecules as a specific characteristic of 
living organisms — in other words, the fact that the molecules of living 
matter come in two varieties which, though chemically identical, are 
in their spatial structure like mirror images to each other — or like 
right and left gloves. 'Left-handed' molecules rotate polarized light to 
the left, 'right-handed' molecules to the right; life substances are thus 
'optically active'. "Why this should be so we still do not quite know; but 
it remains a challenging fact that 'no other chemical characteristic is as 
distinctive of living organisms as is optical activity'. 

1 am on the verge of mysteries, and the veil which covers them is 
getting thinner and thinner. The night seems to me too long. . . . 
Life as manifested to us is a function of the asymmetry of the universe. 
, . . The universe is asymmetrical; for, if all the bodies in motion which 
compose the solar system were placed before a glass, the image in it 

could not be superimposed upon the reality Terrestrial magnetism 

... the opposition between positive and negative electricity, are but 
resultants of asymmetrical actions and movements. . . . Life is domi- 
nated by asymmetrical actions. I can even imagine that all living species 
are primordially in their structure, in their external forms, functions 
of cosmic asymmetry.' 25 

These intoxicating speculations caused Pasteur to embark on a 
series of fantastic experiments, aiming at nothing less than the creation 
of life by means of imitating the asymmetric action of nature in the 
laboratory, using powerful magnets and all kinds of optical tricks. It 
was this alchemist's dream which gave birth to the 'grand design* 
which I have mentioned and which— like a blue-print drawn in in- 
visible ink — remained the secret inspiration behind his researches. 
Luckily, circumstances compelled him to descend from the monumen- 
tal to the trivial level: Pasteur had to give up trying to create life and 
had to get 'up to his neck in beet-juice'. He had been appointed Pro- 
fessor of Chemistry in Lille; and no sooner was he installed than 
Monsieur Bigo, an industrialist engaged in the production of alcohol 



APPENDIX II TOI 

from beet-sugar, came to consult him about certain difficulties en- 
countered in the process. Since this was one of the main industries of 
the region, Pasteur embarked on the task with patriotic fervour— it 
was the first in the series of this type of venture, long before the silk- 
worms, the wine, and the beer. 

In exaniining the fermented juice of the beet, he found in it a com- 
ponent, amyl alcohol, which turned out to be optically active. There- 
fore its molecules must be asymmetrical; but according to the grand 
design, asymmetry is the privilege and secret of life; therefore fermenta- 
tion came from the activity of living things, of microbes. At this point 
the chain reaction set in which fused the germ theory of fermentation 
to the germ theory of disease. Thus did the alchemist's pipe-dream 
give birth to modern medicine — as Kepler's chimerical quest for the 
harmonies led to modern astronomy. 

Here, I believe, is the clue to the scientist's ultimate motivation — 
the equivalent of the meeting of the tragic and the trivial planes in the 
artist's mind. Peering through his microscope or polariscope, in a 
never-ending series of dreary, technical, specialized investigations of 
amyl acid, tartaric acid, butyric acid, Pasteur was attending on one 
level to the business in hand — the beets of Mr. Bigo; on another he 
was scanning the secret of life 'through veils getting thinner and 
thinner'. Thus did some early explorers nourish the secret, childish 
hope to find at the North Pole a crater revealing the axis on which the 
earth turns. So did the Phoenician seamen hope to find, beyond the 
Pillars of Hercules, the island of Atlantis. 

When he was thirty and newly married, Pasteur, though almost 
penniless, embarked on an expedition through Central Europe — a 
treasure-hunt for an elusive commodity dear to his heart: paratartaric 
acid, a chemical derived from the deposit in the vats of fermented 
wine (p. 193 f). He returned and described this Odyssey in an article 
in the Strasbourg newspaper La Veriti, ending with the epic words: 
'Never was treasure sought, never adored beauty pursued over hill 
and dale with greater ardour.* 

The dream which turned the tartar-crystals into a symbol of the 
secret of life proved immensely fertile. But since the actual experiments 
of creating life had failed, Pasteur, in his later years, reversed his 
opinions and embarked on another celebrated controversy to prove 
that the alleged 'spontaneous generation' of micro-organisms (without 
progenitors, out of fermenting or putrefying matter) was a legend. 
'It is a striking fact/ writes Dubos, 'perhaps worthy of the attention 



702 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



of psychoanalysts, that Pasteur devoted much of his later life to demon- 
strating that nature operates as if it were impossible to achieve what he 

— Pasteur— had failed to do Just as he had failed in his attempts to 

create or modify life, so he proved that others, who had claimed to be 
successful where he had failed, had been merely the victims of 
illusion/ 26 

This may indeed have been a factor which contributed to his change 
of attitude, but only a superficial one, like his childish boastings and 
showmanship. The obsession with the secret of life had bitten into 
deeper strata, where opposites cease to be opposites, the law of con- 
tradiction no longer applies, and a plus and minus sign become inter- 
changeable. Among his unpublished writings there is a passage 
written when he was approaching sixty: 

I have been looking for spontaneous generation for twenty years 
without discovering it. No, I do not judge it impossible. But what 
allows you to make it the origin of life? You place matter before 
life and you decide that matter has existed for all eternity. How do 
you know that the incessant progress of science will not compel 
scientists ... to consider that life has existed during eternity, and not 
matter? You pass from matter to life because your intelligence of 
today . . . cannot conceive things otherwise. How do you know that 
in ten thousand years one will not consider it more likely that matter 
has emerged from life . . . ? 26a 

At the age of forty-six Pasteur suffered a stroke which left his left 
arm and leg permanently paralysed. Yet his greatest work was done 
during the following two decades, when he was an invalid and had to 
use his assistants* hands to carry out his experiments. In old age he 
would often browse in his earlier publications. 'Turning the pages of 
his writings, he would marvel at the lands that he had revealed by dis- 
pelling the fogs of ignorance and by overcoming stubbornness. He 
would live again his exciting voyages, as he told Loir in a dreamy voice: 
"How beautiful, how beautiful ! And to think I did it all. I had forgotten 
it."'" 



2. INNOCENCE AND EXPERIENCE 



I have been discussing the motivational drive of scientists. Can we 
make any generalizations regarding their intellectual characteris- 
tics — in addition to those described earlier on (Chapters V-X)? 

Precociousness 

In the first place, such data as we possess confirm the popular belief 
that scientists reach their peak of creativity at an earlier age thai? 
artists. Most scientists made their basic discoveries when they were 
under forty — exceptions like Faraday or Pasteur always granted. In a 
valuable study on Nobel Prize winners by L. Moulin 28 we find the 
average age at which a person is awarded the prize to be fifty-one; but 
for physicists it is forty-five. (The award, of course, often lags by a 
number of years behind the discovery.) It is interesting to note that 
the stupendous increase, over the last half-century, in the volume of 
knowledge to be mastered had no significant influence on the age 
at which the award is received: between 1901 and 1930 the average, 
for physicists, was forty-five years, between 193 1 and i960, forty-six 
years. The average for chemists was fifty years for the first, fifty-one 
for the second period; for the award-winner in medicine it fell from 
fifty-five in the first, to fifty-three in the second period — presumably 
as an effect of increasing team-work. The figures also indicate an age- 
gradient from the more 'theoretical* to the more 'empirical' or 'applied' 
sciences. This is in keeping with the well-known fact of the pre- 
cociousness of mathematicians — the most 'theoretical' among scien- 
tists (unfortunately there is no Nobel Prize for mathematics). 

A related phenomenon is the dazzling multitude of infant prodigies 
among scientists: for every Mozart there are about three Pascals, 
Maxwells, Edisons. To quote only a few examples: the greatest 

703 



704 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Renaissance astronomer before Copernicus, Johann Mueller from 
Koenigsberg, called Regiomontanus (1436-1476), published at the age 
of twelve the best astronomical yearbook for 1448; was asked at 
fifteen by the Emperor Frederick III to cast a horoscope for the im- 
perial bride; went to the University of Leipzig when he was eleven, 
and at seventeen enjoyed European fame; he died at forty. Pascal had 
laid the foundations for the modern treatment of conic sections before 
he was sixteen. Jeremiah Horrocks (1619-1641) applied Kepler's laws 
to the orbit of the moon and made other fundamental contributions 
to astronomy before his death at the age of twenty-one. Evariste 
Galois (1811-1832), one of the most outstanding geniuses in the history 
of mathematics, was killed in a duel at the age of twenty-one (cf. p. 
111). The notes which he left behind amount to no more than sixty 
pages of his collected works'; but those sixty pages inaugurated a new 
epoch in the theory of equations, and 'contain more mathematics 
than is to be found in some libraries crammed with books bearing 
mathematical tides'. 29 Clerk Maxwell, who lived to forty-eight, had 
his first mathematical paper read before the Royal Society at the age of 
fifteen; in the discussion, the geometrical construction which was the 
subject of the paper was described .as superior to Newton's and Des- 
cartes' discussion of the same problem. 

In contrast to this streak of precocity, however, is the fact that the 
majority of geniuses seem to have done rather badly in the normal 
school curriculum—often including the very subject on which later 
on they were to leave their mark^ 'In his student days Einstein had 
been a lazy dog,' his erstwhile teacher Minkovsky remarked: 'He never 
bothered about mathematics at all/ 80 



Scepticism and Credulity 

But the paradox is not too difficult to resolve. I have emphasized before 
(Book One, X) that the scientific genius is a curious mixture of scep- 
ticism and credulity. At school he is frequendy bored by and cynical 
about orthodox doctrines which unimaginative and tradition-bound 
masters try to cram into his head. To quote Einstein once more: 
'Physics too [as taught in the classroom] were split into special fields 
each of which could engulf a short life's work without ever satisfying 
the hunger for deeper knowledge. For the examinations one haul to 
staff oneself with sill this rubbish, whether one wanted to or not; 



APPENDIX II 705 

This compulsion had such a terrifying effect on me that after my final? 
the consideration of any scientific problems was distasteful to me for a 
whole year.' 31 

The student's matrices of thought are still fluid— later on, when they 
have hardened, he will only be able to recapture his erstwhile inno- 
cence at inspired moments. Under propitious conditions, inexperience 
can be an asset: it entices the novice into asking questions which nobody 
has asked before, into seeing a problem where nobody saw one before. 
That is what young Maxwell probably did when he was lying on the 
grass before his father's house, looking at the sky and wondering. That is 
what Einstein did when at the age of sixteen he indulged in the fantasy 
of travelling at the speed of light; and what Edison did when 'his 
demands for explanations of what seemed obvious to his elders created 
the belief that he was less than normally intelligent*. 

Einstein has compared the intellectual appetite of youth 'to the 
voraciousness of a healthy beast of prey*. When the child has learned 
that eveiything has a name, it develops a 'naming mania'. When it 
has learned that all events have 'becauses' it develops the mania of 
asking 'Why? — Why? — Why?' A fool, says the Bible, can ask more 
questions in a minute than a sage can answer in a week. But sages are 
scarce, and the child soon learns to accept answers which are not real 
explanations but conventional formulae or evasions, and to be content 
with them; the keen edge of its appetite for knowledge has become 
blunted. Only geniuses preserve their infantile voracity for 'becauses' 
— and the naive hope that there are real answers to every question. 
'Why is the moon round? Why does the apple fall from die tree? 
Why are there five planets instead of twenty, and why do they move 
as they do? Why does milk go sour? Why could the dairymaid not 
get the pox? Why is the colour of a sailor's blood in the tropics a 
brighter red than in Hamburg? Why did the dead frog's legs twitch?* 
One of the hallmarks of genius is that he has never lost the habit of 
asking foolish questions like these — each of which led to a momentous 
discovery. 

Abstraction and Practicality 

The reasons for this peculiarity have already been discussed: scepticism 
towards the conventional answers, the refusal to take anything for 
granted, the freshness of vision of the unblinkered mind. Taken 
together, these cceate an acuity ofpcxception^ a. gifefor seeing the: banal 



706" 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



objects of everyday experience in a sharp individual light — as painters 
and poets do, each in his own way; to observe details and notice 
trivia which escape the attention of others. This leads us to a second 
pair of complementary qualities (the first was scepticism paired with 
credulity) in the scientist's make-up: the coexistence of abstract and 
concrete moulds of thought, the faculty of combining high flights of 
theory with a keen sense of the practical and down-to-earth — a knack 
for picking up trivial clues. Pythagoras in search of the harmony of 
the spheres enters the blacksmith's workshop; Archimedes gets his 
solution from observing a smudge in his bath-tub; Galileo exhorts his 
friends to learn natural philosophy from the craftsmen in the arsenals of 
Venice; Kepler notices that the slit in his roof which let the rain through 
can be used as the aperture of a camera obscura to observe the sun; 
Claude Bernard takes the temperature of a rabbit's denervated ear and 
is led to the discovery that blood-vessels are controlled by nerves. 

Throughout history, genius displays these complementary qualities 
of making lofty generalizations based on humble clues. 'It is very 
necessary', wrote Maxwell, 'that those who are trying to learn from 
books the facts of physical science should be enabled to recognize these 
facts when they meet with them out-of-doors. Science appears to us 

with a very different aspect after we have found out that we may 

find illustrations of the highest doctrines of science in games and gym- 
nastics, in travelling by land and by water, in storms of the air and of the 
sea. This habit of recognizing principles amid the endless variety of 
their action . . . tends to rescue our scientific ideas from that vague 
condition in which we too often leave them buried among the other 
products of a lazy credulity/ 32 

To have one's head in the clouds does not prevent one from having 
one's feet firmly on the ground. The scientist, as the artist, must live 
on several planes at once— look at eternity through the window of 
time. All great geniuses of science were endowed with this particular 
dualism of their faculties: a head for generalizations and an eye for 
minute particulars; searching for the secret of life in the beet-juice of 
M. Bigo; tilting at windmills without falling off the horse. 

Multiple Potentiab 

I must mention one more characteristic property shared, apparently, by 
most great scientists: one may call it the multiple potential*. It helps to 



APPENDIX II 707 

explain the paradox of the apparently haphazard way in which scien- 
tists are often launched on their career or on a particular line of re- 
search. 

Kepler was designated to become a theologian when he was un- 
expectedly offered the job of a mathematician at a provincial school. 
Haiiey was a botanist when the accident of dropping his friend's 
precious spar crystal made him change to crystallography, and become 
a pioneer in that field. Darwin, preparing to become a country curate, 
had the good luck of being invited to join the expedition of the Beagle 
— without that chance it is extremely doubtful whether he would have 
written The Origin of Species. The direction of all of Pasteur's later re- 
searches was determined by his first discoveries about the optical 
activity of paratartaric acid: he himself said that he had become 'en- 
chained to the inescapable logic' by which one discovery gave birth 
to the next. As for Alexander Fleming, the coincidences which deter- 
mined his initial choice of career are about as fantastic as the actual 
circumstances of his discovery. He had adopted the medical profession 
because his brother was a doctor; he had gone to St. Mary's where he 
was to spend the whole of his life, because he had played against their 
water-polo team; and he chose bacteriology as his branch of research 
because Freeman, the assistant of Almroth Wright, wanted to keep 
Heming, who was an excellent shot, in St. Mary's rifle club. 

The answer to the paradox is, apparently, that given the type of 
mind which Fleming had, he would in all likelihood have left his 
mark on any other branch of experimental science into which the 
wind of chance had blown him. In Pasteur's case, for instance, Dubos 
has convincingly shown that 'the inescapable logic' which his researches 
followed was by no means inescapable; for in Pasteur's notebooks and 
casual remarks there are projects and germs of discoveries which, had 
he only had the time to follow them up, or had the wind of circum- 
stance blown from a different direction, would have brought an 
equally fertile harvest. 

True genius, according to Dr. Johnson, 'is a mind of large general 
powers, accidentally determined to some particular direction, ready 
for all things, but chosen by circumstances for one'. Dubos, after 
quoting the Doctor, fully concurs with his opinion: e It is often by a 
trivial, even an accidental decision, that we direct our activities into a 
certain channel, and thus determine which of the potential expressions 
of our individuality become manifest. Usually we know nothing of 
the dtimate orientation or of the outlet towards which we travel, and 



708 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



the stream sweeps us to a formula of life from which there is no 
returning. Every decision is like a murder, and our march forward is 
over the stillborn bodies of all our possible selves that will never be/ 33 
This moving confession of a great scientist seems to be based on the 
assumption that creativity is a kind of convertible energy which can 
be applied to various forms of activity — as the pressure of steam can 
be converted into electricity or motion. Stated in this extreme form, 
it is certainly an exaggeration: you cannot convert the creative energy 
of a painter into the composition of an opera. But it is nevertheless 
true that the particular type of intuition which makes the scientific 
genius can be focussed on problems as wide apart as colour-theory and 
celestial mechanics in Newton's case, or electro-magnetism and the 
theory of gases in Maxwell's — with equally striking results. The versa- 
tility, the quicksilvery mobility of minds like Archimedes', Galileo's, 
Descartes', Franklin's, Faraday's, or Edison's is truly phenomenal; they 
seemed to walk through life charged with static electricity, so that 
whatever object they touched, they drew a spark. One-idea men, such 
as Copernicus or Darwin, seem to be the exceptions among the truly 
great, and multi-potentiality the rule. The ominous trend towards 
over-specialization, its dangers to the creative mind, and the educa- 
tional and administrative reforms needed to remedy it, are outside the 
scope of this book. . 

NOTE 

To p, 677. The Artistarchian system and the motion of the earth had been 
discussed or taught by Copemicus's forerunners, the astronomers Peurbach and 
Regiomontanus, by his teachers Brujewski and Novara, and by his colleagues 
at the University of Bologna, Calcagnini, Ziegler, etc. (cf. The Sleepwalkers 
pp. 205-10). 



REFERENCES 



BOOK ONE 
The Art of Discovery and the Discoveries of Art 

PREFACE 

I, The Sleepwalkers (1959). 2, The Lotus and the Robot (i960). 

PART ONE THE JESTER 

I. THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 

1, Sully, J. (1902). 2, Duchenne de Boulogne (1862). 3, Ribot, T. A. (1896). 
4, Quoted in the *This England' column of the New Statesman and Nation, January 
1946. 5, December 31, 1946. 6, Polanyi (1958), p. 50. 7, Bartlett (1958). 8, Bergson 
(1916), p. 59. 9, Lorenz, K. L. in Whyte, L. L. ed. (1951), pp. 176-8. 10, SantiUana 
ed. (1953). P- 469- 11, Br. J. Psychology (1962), 55, 3, p. 229. 

II. LAUGHTER AND EMOTION 

1, Gregory, J. C. (1924). 2, Quoted by Gregory, op. cit. 3, Foss, B. in the New 
Scientist, 6.7.1961. 4, Bain, A. (1868). 5, Bergson (1916). 6, McDougall, W. (1920). 
7, Freud, Gesammelte Werke, VI (1940). 8, Freud, op. cit. 9, The Guardian, 5.9.1962. 
10, See Ref. 3. 11, Bergson, op. cit. 12, Huxley, Aldous, in Control of the Mind, 
Farber, S. M. and Wilson, H. L. ed. (1961). 13, Auden, W. H. (1944). 

III. VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 

I, Love*s Labour's Lost, V. ii, 2, Sawyer, W. W. (1955), p. 143. 3, Gregory, op. cit. 

IV. FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY 

I, SantiUana (1955), p. 124. 

PART TWO THE SAGE 

V. MOMENTS OF TRUTH 

I, Kohler, W. (1957), p. 35- 2, Ibid., pp. 93-4. 3, Ibid., p. 94. 4, Ibid., p. 97. 5, 
Merton, R. K. (1961). 6, Polanyi (1958), p. 11. 7, Hadamard (1949), p. 119. 8, 
Ibid, p. 120. 9, Dubos (1960), p. 117. 9a, Ibid, p. 336, 10. Quoted in The Creative 
Process, Ghiselin, ed. (1952). 11, Hadamard, op. cit., p. 8. 12, de Launay, L. (1925). 
13, Montmasson (193 1), p. 77. 14, Polya, G. (I954-), p- 76. 15, Findlay A. (1948), 
pp. 36-8. 

709 



7io 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



VI. THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 

1, Histoire de V Invention de VImprimerie par les Monuments, ed. Hofer, Paris 1840. 

2, Mysterium Cosmographicum, Preface. 3, Ibid. 4, Opera Omnia, Vol. XIII, pp. 33 fT. 
5, Ibid., Vol. I, cap. 20. 6, Ibid., Notes 2 and 3. 7, Astronomia Nova, II, cap. 18. 
8, Ibid., cap 44. 9, Op. Omnia, Vol. XV, pp. 134 seq. 10, Letter of 5.9.1857. 
11, Footnote to the Historical Introduction to The Origin of Species. 12, Notebooks, 
quoted by Himmelfarb, G. (1959), p. 153- *3> Life and Letters, II, p. 215. 
14, To Lyell; ibid., II, p. 241. 15, To Fawcett, More Letters, 1, 195. 16, Ibid., I, 36. 
I7» Origin, 6th ed., p. 2. 18, Ibid., p. 3. 19, Lamarck (1914), pp. 109-10. 

20, Nordenskiold, History of Biology, p. 42, quoted by Himmelfarb, op. cit., p. 153. 

21, British Medical Journal, 4.8.1956". 22, Himmelfarb, op. cit., p. 156. 23, Origin, 
6th ed., p. 3. 24, Himmelfarb, op. cit., p. 234. 25, My Life, I, p. 359. 26, Ibid., I, 
pp. 232, 362. 27, Ibid., I, pp. 362 fT. 28, Himmelfarb, op. cit., p. 239. 29, Ibid., p. 
238. 30, Loc. cit. 31, Ibid., p. 331. 

VII. THINKING ASIDE 

I, Whyte, L. L. (1962), p. 25. 2, Ibid., p. 63. 3, Ibid., pp. 88-9. 4, Ibid., p. 90. 

5, Ibid., p. 91. 6, Ibid., p. 93. 7, Ibid., p. 95. 8, Ibid., p. 107. 9, Ibid., p. 108. 
io, Ibid., pp. 119-20. 11, Ibid., pp. 124-5. 12, Ibid., pp. 150-1. 13, Ibid., p. 104. 
14, Ibid., p. 147. 15, Ibid., p. 154. 16, Ibid., p. 154. 17, Ibid., p. 152. 18, Ibid., 
pp. 160-1. 19, Herrigel (1959), 3rd ed., pp. 57-8. 20, Suzuki, D. T. (1959)* p- 94- 
21, Principles of Psychology (1890), Vol. I, p. 255. 22, Inquiries into Human Faculty, 
1883. 23, Findlay, A., op. cit., p. 42. 24, Kendall, J. (1955), p. 138. 25, Crowther, 
J. G. (1940), I, p. 135. 26, Hadamard, op. cit., pp. 142-3. 27, Ibid., p. 85. 
28, Quoted by Hadamard, p. 94. 29, Roman Jakobson, quoted by Hadamard, 
p. 97. 30, Seelig (1954), p. 71. 31, Ibid. 32, Sidney Hook, Consciousness in Japan*, 
Commentary, New York, Jan. 1959. 33, Whyte, L. L. (1962), p. 41. 34, Tractatus, 
Prop. 4121. 

VIII. UNDERGROUND GAMES 

I, Civilization and its Discontents (1930). 2, Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist 
(i949)» p. 53* 3» Loc. cit. 4, Scientific American, June 1961. In fact the problem 
originates with Carl Duncker. 5, The Integration of Personality (1940), p. 16. 

6, Crowther, J. G. (1940) p. 325. 7, Loc. cit. 8, *Ow Psychic Research', ed. Gardner 
Murphy and Bellon, R. O. (1961). 9, Ueber den Gegensinn, der Urworte, Ges. 
Werke VIII, p. 216. 10, Die Verneinung, G. W. XIV, p. 1 1 . 1 1, Montmasson (1931), 
p. 137. 12, Enc. Brit., 13th ed., article on Photography. 13, Beveridge (1950), p. 69. 
14, Sachs, H. (1946), p. 98. 15, Bronowski (1961) p. 31. 16, Crowther (1937), 
p. 77. 17, Ibid., p. 69. 18, Loewi, O. (i960). 19, Loc. cit. 

IX. THE SPARK AND THE FLAME 

I, Quoted by Ghiselin, op. cit.2, Beveridge, op. cit., p. 5. 3, Ibid. 4, Harmonice 
Mundi, Introduction to Book V. 5, Quoted by Beveridge, op. cit., p. 105. 
6, Astronomia Nova, IV. cap. 58. 7, The Sleepwalkers (i959). 8, Jones, E. (1953), 
Vol. I, p. 55. 9, Ibid., p. 103. 10, Ibid., p. 101. 11, Ibid., p. 104. 12, Ibid., p. 97. 
13, Lorimer (1929), p. 91. 14, Markey (1928), p. 42. 15, The Story of My Life 
(1902). 

X. THE EVOLUTION OP IDEAS 

I, "Whitehead (1953). 2, The Sleepwalkers, pp. 515-16". 3» Pyke, M. (196*1), p. 215. 
4, Pledge, H. T. (1939), p. 100. 5, Burnet, J. (1908), p. 29. 5a, Pope's Epitaph for 
Newton, and Hilairc Belloc's Answer to it. 6, Bartlett (1958), pp. 98, 122, 134, 



REFERENCES 



711 



I36-7- 7> (i94 8 )> P- 16 7- 8 » ^ e Sleepwalkers, p. 70. 9, Taton, R. (1957), pp. 1 34-5- 
10, Butterfieid (1949), pp. 1-2. 10a, The Sleepwalkers, 11, Butterfield, p. 7. 
12, Heath, Th. L. (1932), p. 170. 13, For a critical account of the Galileo conflict 
see Tke Sleepwalkers. 14, Polanyi (1958). pp. 156-8. 15, Dubos (i95o)> P* ^1. 
id, Polanyi, op. cit., p. 168. 17, Ibid., pp. 12-13. *7a» Scientific American, May 
1963. 18, Popper (1959), p. 280. 19, Dubos (i960), pp. 133-5. 20, Voyage to 
Laputa. 

XI. SCIENCE AND EMOTION 

I, Quoted by Kretschmer (1931), p. 136. 2, Beveridge, op. cit., p. 75. 3, Jones, E. 
(1953). I, P- 348. 4» Quoted by Farrington, B. (i953)> PP- 130-1. 5, Quoted by 
Seelig, op. cit., p. 45. 6, Harmonice Mundi, Lib. IV, cap I. 7, Whyte, L. L. (1962), 
p. 66. 8, Op. cit., p. 105. 9, Seelig, op. cit., p. 44. 10, Planete. Paris, No. 1, 1961. 



PART THREE THE ARTIST 
A The Participatory Emotions 

XII. THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 

1, Hilgard (1957), pp. 129 f. 2, Cf. Gellhorn, E. (1943 and 1957). 3, The Expression 
of the Emotions in Man and Animals. 4, Cf. e.g. Valentine (1946), and Clarke, Hunt, 
and Hunt (1947)- 5. Cf. Mutch, R. T. (1944)- 6, Montagu, A., Science, Vol. 130, 
p. 1572. 7, Kling, C. (1933). 

XIII. PARTNESS AND WHOLENESS 

I, Penfield (i959)i p. 249. 

XIV. ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 

I, Piaget (1930). 2, Civilization and its Discontents, p. 13 £f. 3, LeVy-Bruhl (1923 
and 1926). 4, Cf. Polanyi, op. cit., p. 55. 

B. Verbal Creation 

XV. ILLUSION 

1, Compressed from The Observer, London, 2.12.1962. 2, Levy-Bruhl (1926), 
p. 76. 3, Ibid., p. 385. 4, Fitzmaurice Kelly, J., article on 'Literature* in Enc. Brit., 
13th ed. 

- XVI. RHYTHM AND RHYME 

i» (1927), p. 139. 2, Le CStS de Guermantes. 3, A.R.N.M.D. (1940), Vol. XX, p. 732. 
4, The Name and Nature of Poetry. 5, Quoted from Ghisehn, ed. (1952). 

XVII. IMAGE 

1, Sachs, H. (1946). 2, (1925), p. 270 f£. 3, Kretschmer (1934)- 

XVIII. INFOLDING 

1, What is Art? 2, Richards, I. A. {1924). J, Cohen, J. (1958). 

XIX. CHARACTER AND PLOT 

I, Memento Mori. 2, Brandt, G. W., in CasselVs Enc. of Literature (i953)» VoL I, 
p. 422. 3, (1930), pp. 25 seq. 



712 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



XX. THE BELLY OF THB WHALE 

I, See, for instance, Jung, Psychology of the Unconscious (191 6); M. Bodkin, 
Archetypal Patterns in Poetry (1934); Toynbee, A Study of History (1947). 2, Jung 
(1928), p. 395- 3» Op. cit. 

C. Visual Creation 

XXI. MOTIF AND MEDIUM. 

I, Cf. Newton, E. (1941). 2, Listowel (1933). P- 217. 3» Beauty and Ugliness (1912). 
4, Jaensch (1930)- 5. Gris, Juan, Horizon, August, 1946. 6, Picasso in a conversation 
with the editor ofCahiers a" Art (1935), quoted by Goldwater and Treves (1945). 
7, Wollberg, L. R. (1945). 8, Quoted by Reid, L. (1931). 9, Quoted by Gombrich 
(1962B), p. 159. 10, A New Method of Assisting the Invention in Drawing Original 
Compositions of Landscape (1765). n, Gombrich (1962B), p. 123. 12, Ibid., p. 122. 
13, Diirer und die italienische Antike (1905). 14, Gombrich (1962B), p. 75. 1 5, Ibid., 
p. 12. 16, Ibid., pp. 61 ff. 17, Ibid., p. 145. 18, Ibid., p. 12. 19, Ibid., p. 10. 

XXII. IMAGE AND EMOTION 

I, Kepes, G. (1956), p. 102. 2, Ibid., pp. 286-7. 

XXIII. ART AND PROGRESS 

I, (1949), p. 97. 2, Quoted by Gombrich (1962B), p. 246. 3, (1949), p. 105. 
4, Gombrich (1962B), p. 20. 5, Ibid., p. 169. 6, Ibid., pp. 174-5- 

XXIV. CONFUSION AND STERILITY 

1, Some lengthy passages in this chapter are lifted without acknowledgements 
from my essay on 'The Anatomy of Snobbery* in The Trail of the Dinosaur (1954). 

2, Time, January 26, 1962. 3, See Note 1. 4, Quoted from 'This England', The New 
Statesman and Nation, August 14, 1954. 



BOOK TWO 
Habit and Originality 

INTRODUCTION 

1, Jef&ess, A., ed. (1951), p. 113. 

I. PRE-NATAL SKILLS 

I, Woodger (1929)* P« 327. 2, Hyden (i960), p. 307. 2A, Hyden (1962). 
3, BertalanfEy (1952), p. 134. 4. Schrodinger (1944), p. 71- 5» Cf. e.g. Buttin, G. 
1962. 6, Kschberg, M. and Bladder, A. W. (1961). 7, Sillier, Weiss, and 
Hamburger {1955), p. 338. 8, Hamburger (1955A), p. 67. 9, Waddingtoa (1932), 
quoted from Polanyi (1958), p. 350*. io» Weiss (i939)» P« 290. 11, Hamburger 
(?955b), p. 978. 12, Brachet (i955)> PP- 389 ff. 13, Hamburger, loc. cit. 14, Bert- 
aianffy (1952), p. 47. 

II. THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 

i» e.g. Coghill (1929), Carmichael, L. (1954). 2, Needham, J. (1932). 3, Spencer H. 
(1870-2). 4,Heidenhain (1923). 5» Jefrress, A., ed. (i95*)»pp. 140 ff. 6, Pribram 



REFERENCES 



713 



(i960), p. 6. 7, Hyashi, T. (1961), pp. 184 seq. 8, Pribram (i960), p. 8. 9, Hoist, V. 
(1937, 1948). 10, Petermann (1932), p. 124. 11, Quoted from Petermann, op. cit., 
pp. 127 ff. 12, Ibid., p. 130. 13, Ibid., pp. 131 £ I4» Ibid., p. 132. 15, Quoted by 
Miller et al. (i960), p. 92. 16, Jef&ess, op. cit., p. 141. 17, Quoted from Tinbergen 
(I95i)» p. 129. 

III. DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 

I, Pribram (i960), p. 4. 2, Tinbergen (1951)* p- 126. 3, Thorpe (1956), pp. 28-30. 
4, Needham, A. E. (1961). 5» Child, C. M. (1924). 

iv. 'reculer pour mibux sauter* 

I, Child, C. M. (1924), p. 151. 2, Ibid., p. 150. 3, Smithers (i960), p. 108. 4, Ibid., 
pp. 106-7. 5» Lashley (i960), p. 239. 6, Lashley (1929). 7, Bertalanfty, op. cit., 
p. 114. 8, Loc. cit. 9, Kretschmer (1931), p. 138. 10, Miller et al, op. cit., p. 199. 

II, Polanyi (1958), p. 400. 13, Needham, A. E. 1961. 

V. PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION 

1, Pribram (i960). 

VI. CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR 

I, Tinbergen (1951), pp. 189, 195. 2, e.g. Spurway and Haldane (1953), quoted by 
Thorpe (1956). 3, Tinbergen (i953)» p- 55- 4» Tinbergen (1951), p. 9. 5, Sir Julian 
Huxley. 6, Kuo, Z. Y. (1932). 7» Lehrman, D. S. (1961). 8, Beach, F. A. (1961). 

9, Tinbergen (1951), p. 142. 10, Hilgard (1958), p. 3. 11, Thorpe (1956), p. 133. 

12, Ibid., p. 18. 1 3, Ibid., p. 28. The term 'innate releasing mechanism' is a transla- 
tion by Tinbergen of the German 'das angeborene, auslbsende Schema' (von Uexhitfl 
— Lorenz). 14, Tinbergen (1951). p. 103. 15. Loc. cit. 16, Tinbergen (1953). P- 9- 
17, For a brief survey see 'The Concept of "Ritualization" ' by A. D. Blest in 
Current Problems in Animal Behaviour, ed. Thorpe and Zangwill (1961). 18, Thorpe 
(1956), p. 132. 19. Ibid., p. 31- 20, Woodworth (1918). 21, Tinbergen (1951), 
pp. 105-6. 22, Ibid., p. no. 23, Ibid., pp. 104-5. 24, Thorpe (1956), p. 41. 25, Ibid, 
p. 42. 26, Ibid., p. 19. 27, Loc. cit. 28, Thorpe (1956), p. 26. 29, Ibid., p. 262. 
30, Hingston (1927), quoted by Thorpe (1956), p. 38. 31, Hingston, op. cit., 
quoted by Thorpe (1956")* p. 39- 32, Lindauer, M. (1952). 33, Tinbergen (1953), 
p. 102. 34, Ibid., p. 116. 

VII. IMPRINTING AND IMITATION 

I, Hilgard (1957). P- 125. 2, Heinroth, O. (1938). 3» Thorpe (i95<5), P- 375. 
4, Thorpe (1956), p. 356. 5, Lashley (1913). 6, McDougall (1936).' 7, Thorpe 
(1956), p. 375- 8, Ibid., p. 374. 9, Ibid., p. 356. 

VIII. MOTIVATION 

I, Mowrer, O. H. (1952). 2, Freud (1920), pp. 3-5. 3, Hilgard (1958), p. 428. 
4, Hebb (1949), pp. 178-80. 5, Cf. i.a., Zener (1957); Loucks (1935, 1938); 
Hovland (1937); Hilgard and Marquis (1940); and for a concise summary Hebb 
(i949)» pp. 174-6. 6\ For a review of the literature, cf. e.g. Pribram (1960)- 
7, Miller et al., op. cit., p. 30. 8, Pribram (i960), p. 3. '9, Skinner (1938), p. 9. 

10, Ibid., pp. 40. 11, Miller et al., op. cit., p. 22. 12, Hilgard (1958), p. 105. 

13, Humphreys, L. G. (1939). *4» (i95^), p. 350. 15, Hilgard (1958), p. 177. 
16, Berlyne, D. E. (i960), p. 225. 17, Allport, G.W. (i957)« 18, Goldstein, K. 
(1939). 19. Cf. e.g., Jencks B. and Potter, P. B., Journal of Psychology, Vol. 49, 



714 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



p. 139. 20, Nissen, H. W. (i954)- 21, Berlyne, op. cit., p. 115. 22, Ibid., p. 116. 
23, Ibid., p. 127. 24, Ibid., p. 117. 25, Ibid., p. 117. 26, Ibid., p. 119. 27, Ibid., 
pp. 133-4. 28, Lorenz (1956). 29, Compressed from The Descent of Man (1913 ed.), 
pp. 108-10; and The Expression of the Emotions (1872), p. 43. 30, Berlin, 1917; 
London and New York 1925. 31, Berlyne, op.cit.,p. 148. 32, Harlow etal. (1950). 
33, Harlow (1953), p. 25. 34, Woodworth (i947)» P- 123. 35, Berlyne, op. cit., 
p. 170. 36, Loc. cit. 37, Pavlov (1927). 38, Darchen, R. (1952, 1954, and 1957), 
quoted by Berlyne, op. cit., p. 104. 39, Thacker, L. A. (1950)- 40, Thorpe (1956), 
p. 9. 41, Ibid., p. 12. 42, Craik, K.J. W. (1943). p. 61. 43, Allport, G. W. (1955), 
p. 67. 

IX. PLAYING AND PRETENDING 

I, Thorpe (1956). 2, Berlyne, op. cit., p. 5. 3, Thorpe (1956), p. 87. 4, Loc. cit. 
5, Ibid. p. 355- 

X. PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 

I, Galambos (1956). Cf. also 269. 2, Moray, N., The Listener, 19.4.1962. 3, e.g. 
Hilgard (1958), p. 442 seq. 4, Ittelson, W. H. (195a), quoted fromPolanyi (1958), 
p. 96. 5, Wever, E. G. (1949). 6, Osgood (1960), p. 111. 7, Pringle, J. W. S. 
(1951). 8, Hyden (i960, 1962). 9, Whitfield (1949), p. 367. 10, Miller et al., 
op. cit., pp. 134 fF. ioa, Bartlett (1961), cap. V. 11, See e.g. Hebb (i949)» cap. 2. 
12, Ibid. 13, Ibid. 14, Ibid. 15, Exner (1891), quoted by Thorpe (1956), p. 129. 
16, See, for instance, Miles *s (193 1) fascinating kinephantoscope. 17, Dubos, p. 94. 
18, Babbage (1830), quoted by Hanson (1961), p. 184. 19, Barlow (1959), pp. 552 
seq. 20, Quoted by KofFka (1935), p. 143. 21, Woodworth (1938), p. 561. 

22, Cf. Osgood (1960), p. 641, Kluever, H. (1955) and Jaensch, E. R. (1930). 

23, Kluever, op. cit. and Jaensch, op. cit. 24, Kluever, op. cit. 25, Pierre, T. H. 
(i955)- 26, Kluever, op. cit. 27, Jaensch, op. cit. 28, Ibid., p. 97. 29, Semon, R. 
1921), p. 149. 30, Woodworth (1938), p. 42. 31, Head (1926), p. 232. 32, Quoted 
by Penfield (1959), p. 226. 33, Fry, D. B. and Denes, P., in Mechanization of 
Thought Processes (1959), p. 378. 34, Paget (1930). 35, Fry and Denes, op. cit., 
p. 381. 36, Paget, op. cit. 37, Ladefoged, P., in Mechanization of Thought Processes 
(1959), p- 407. 38, Ibid., p. 411. See also Mackay, D. M. and Sutherland, N. S., 
ibid., pp. 607-9. 3'9» Drever, J., 2nd. in Annual Review of Psychology (i960), p. 131. 
40, Ibid., pp. 153-4. 4i» Thorpe (1956), p. 119. 42, Loc. cit. 43, Thorpe (1956), 
p. 411. 44, Ibid., p. 119. 45, Quoted by Wilenski, R. H. (1940), p. 202. 
46, c£ Ladefoged, P., in Mechanization of Thought Processes (1959), p. 402. 47, 
Bartlett (1961), p. 200. 48, Ibid, p. 213. 49, Time, March 2, 1962. 

XI. MOTOR SKILLS 

1, Psychological Review, 1899* 6, pp. 345-75- 2, Woodworth (1938), p. 159. 3, 
Book, W. F. (1908). 4, "Woodworth (1938), p. 45. 5, New Scientist, March 1, 
1962. 6, Miller et al. (i960), p. 86. 7, Lashley in the Hixon Symposium, p. 
123. 8, Ruch, T. C. (1951), p- 205. 

XII. THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY 

I, (1927), pp- 32-3. 2, Skinner, quoted by Hilgard (1958), p. 117. 3, Ibid., p. 106. 
4, Ibid., p. 152. 5, Kohler: The Mentality of Apes, Gestalt Psychology. KofFka: 
Principles of Gestalt Psychology, The Growth of the Mind. 6, Watson (1928), pp. 198 fF. 
7, Watson (1924). p- 281.8, Watson (1928), p. 199. 9, Loc. cit. 10, Hilgard (1958), 
p. 121. 11, Guthrie (1935). P- 25. 12, Skinner (1953a), quoted by Hilgard (1958), 
p. 115. 13, Hull (i945)r p. 56. 14. Hilgard (1958), p. 152. 15, Osgood (1953). 
p. 655- i<S» Hebb (1949), p. 59- I7» Hilgard (1958), pp. 8 fF. 18, Ibid., p. 335. 



REFERENCES 



715 



19. Polanyi (1958), p. 71 • 20, Craik (1943)* P- 121. 21, Hebb (1949), p. 127. 
22, Thorpe (1956), PP- 96, 100, 106. 23, Ibid., pp. 229, 231. 24, Ibid., pp. 229, 231, 
232, 235. 25, Ibid., p. 227. 26, Russell (1927), p. 41. 27, Osgood (1953), p. 451. 
28, Rosenthal, R., and Fode, K. L., 'The Effect* of Experimenter Bias on the Per- 
formance of the Albino Rat' in Behavioral Science, Vol. VIII, 3, July 1963. 29, 
Earl Ubell in the New York Herald Tribune, January i960. 30, Thorndike (1913- 
14), p. 134- 3i» Osgood, op. cit., p. 604. 32, Hilgard (1958), p. 15. 32a, Tolman 
(1937), P- 33, Hilgard (195S), p. 65. 34, Krechevsky (1932). 35, Ibid. 36, 
Hilgard (1958), p. 470. 37, Osgood, op. cit., p. 604. 

XIII. THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 

I, Kohler (i957)» p. H3- 2, Ibid., p. 113 n. 3, Osgood (i960), p. 637. 4, Kohler 

(1957) » P- 164. 5, Yerkes (1943), p. 156. 6, Osgood, op. cit., p. 611. 7, Loc. cit. 

8, Kohler (1957)* P- 43- 9, Ibid, p. 44. 10, Ibid., cap VII. 11, Ibid., p. 44. 12, Ibid., 
p. 45- 13, Ibid., p. 167. 14, Yerkes (1943)- 15, Birch H. G., in J. Comp. Psychol., 
I945» P- 382. 16, Thompson, W. R. and Heron, W. (1954), quoted by Hebb 

(1958) , p. 219. 17, Kohler (i957)» P* I<5 4- l8 , Ibid., p. 167. 19, Kohler (1930), 
p. 277. 20, Ibid., pp. 272 seq. 21, Craik (1943). pp. 52. 22, Cf. e.g. Kohler (1957), 
p. 27. 23, Piaget (1954). P- 359- 24, Craik, op. cit., p. 1. 25, Russell (1927), pp. 279- 
80. 26, Ibid, p. 83. 27, Kohler (1930), p. 225. 28, Petermann (1932). 29, Hixon 
Symposium, p. 69. 30, Polanyi (1958), p. 341. 31, Koffka (1935), p. 570. 
32, Kohler (1930). P- 215. 33. Hebb (1949), P- 134- 34, Ibid., p. 164. 35, Hebb 
{1958), pp. 204-5. 36, Hilgard (1958), pp. 475-<5, 477-8. 

XIV. LEARNING TO SPEAK 

I, James (1890), Vol. I, p. 253. 2, Ach quoted by Humphrey, G. (1951), p. 260. 

3, Osgood, op. cit., p. 686. 4, Piaget (1954), P- 359- 5» Hilgard (1957), p. 315- 
6, Piaget (1954). 7, Ibid., p. 92. 8, Penfield and Roberts (1959), pp. 228-9. 

9, Quoted by Woodworth (1938), p. 148. 10, Thorpe, op. cit., p. 119. 11, Head 
(1926), pp. in, 112. 12, Woodworth (1938), p. 809. 13, Humphrey (1951), p. 
252. 14, Penfield and Roberts (1959), p. 226. 15, Loc. cit. 16, Ibid., p. 228. 17, 
Chapter on language and Thought*. 

XV. LEARNING TO THINK 

i, Russell (1927), p. 58. 2, Lorimer (1929), p. 95. 3, Cf. Book One, p. 322. 

4, Lorimer (1929), p. 94* 5» Markey (1928), p. 71- 6, Ibid., p. 50. 7, Hebb (1949), 
p. 118. 8, Ibid., pp. 117 ff. 9, Quoted by Humphrey, op. cit., p. 25. 10, Osgood, 
op. cit, <589. 11, Cf. e.g. Hebb (1949), p. 176. 12, Lorimer, op. cit., pp. 103 flf. 
13, Koffka (1930), p- 347- I4» Riaget (1930), p. 243. 15, Piaget (1928), p. 229. 
16, Ibid., p. 227. 17, Lorimer (1929), pp. 124-6. 18, Craik, op. cit., p. 121. 19, 
See Levy-Bruhl (1926), pp. 181 seq. 20, Ibid. 21, Dantzig (1930). 22, Herodotus, 
Historia, Bk. VII. 23, Dantzig, op. cit., pp. 9 ff. 24, Cf. e.g. Haas, W. S. (1956). 

XVI. SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 

I, Cf. Koestler (i960). 2, Cf. Hyden (i960, 1962). 3, Penfield and Roberts, op. cit., 
p. 233. 

XVII. ASSOCIATION 

I, Osgood, op. cit. 2, Humphrey, op. cit., p. 1. 3, Quoted by Woodworth (1938), 
p. 370. 4, Quoted by Woodworth (1939) pp. 350 £ 5» Woodworth (1939) pp. 
352 ff. 



7i6 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



XVIII. HABIT AND ORIGINALITY 

I, Quoted by Polya (1938), p. 164. 2, Polya (1948), p. 158. 3, Ibid., p. 58. 

4, Loc. cit. 5, Osgood, op. cit., p. 633. 

APPENDIX I. ON LOADSTONES AND AMBER 

I, De Magnetic, Book V, cap. 12. 2, Ibid., VI, 4. 3, Cap 6. 4, Pledge (1939), p. 121. 

5, Quoted from F. Sherwood Taylor (1949). p- 258. 6, Article on 'Electricity' in 
Enc. Brit. (1955 ed.) VIII, p. 189. 7, Crowther (1940), p. 348. 

APPENDIX II. SOME FEATURES OF GENIUS 

I, The Elizabethan World Picture (1946). 2, Science and Imagination (1956). 3, Quoted 
by Farrington (1953). pp- 130-1. 4, Butterfield (1949), p. 29. 5, Dreyer, J. L. E. 
Tycho Brake (1890), p. 14. 6, II Saggiatore. 7, Dialogue on the Great World Systems, 
p. 469. 8, 12 Saggiatore, Opere, VI, p. 232. 9, Dialogue Concerning Two Sciences, p. 1. 
10, Dialogue on the Great World Systems, pp. 68-9. 11, Drake Stillman (1957), 
pp. 256-8. 12, Harmonice Mundi, cap. 7. 13, Hoskin, M., 'The Mind of Newton', 
The Listener, 19.10.61. 14, Philips, R. (1927). I5> Crowther, J. G. (1940), p. 129. 
16, Ibid., p. 316. 17, Himmelfarb, G., op. cit., p. 26. 18, Ibid., pp. 314-17. 
19, Ibid., p. 317. 20, Ibid., p. 119. 21, Ibid., pp. 307-8- 21A, Ibid. p. 357. 22, Origin 
of Species (1873), p. 429. 23, The Descent of Man (1913) ed., pp. 946-7. 24, Dubos 
(1950), p. 72. 25, Dubos (i960), p. 36. 26, Dubos (1950), p. 114. 26A, Ibid, p. 
396, f. 27, Ibid, p. 87. 28, La Personne du Prix Nobel (in the press). 29, Enc. Brit., 
13th ed. onjalois. 30, Seelig, op. cit., p. 28. 31, Ibid., p. 26. 32, Crowther (1940), 
pp. 356 ff. 33. Dubos (1950), p. 383. 



WORKS MENTIONED IN THIS BOOK 



Ach, N., Analyse des Willens. Berlin, 1935. 

Aixport, G. W., Personality: A Psychological Interpretation. New York: H. Holt, 
1937- 

Aixport, G. W., Becoming. Yale Univ. Press, 1955. 
A.R.N.M.D., The Hypothalamus, Vol. XX, p. 732. Baltimore, Md., 1940. 
Auden, W. H., The Sea and the Mirror. New York: Random House, 1944. 
Babbage, C, The Decline of Science in England. London: R. Clay, 1830. 
Baerends, G. P., 'Fortpflanzungsverhalten und Orientierung der Grabwespe 

Ammophila campestris* in Jur. Tijd. voor Entom, 84, 71-275, 1941. 
Bain, A., Manual of Mental and Moral Science. London: Longmans, 1868. 
Bard, ed., Macleod's Physiology in Modern Medicine. St. Louis: Mosby, 1941 (9th 

ed.). 

Barlow, H. B., in Mechanisation of Thought Processes. London: H.M. Stationery 
Office, 1959. 

Bartlett, Sir Frederick, Thinking. London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1958. 

Bartlett, Sir Frederick, Remembering. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1961. 

Beck, E. See Gastaut, H. 

Beixon, R. O. See James, William. 

Bergson, H. L., LeRire. Paris: F. Alcan, 1916 (15th ed.). 

Berlyne, D. E., Conflict, Arousal and Curiosity. London, New York, Toronto; 

McGraw-Hill, i960. 
von Bertalanffy, L., Problems of Life. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1952. 
Beveridge, W. I. B., The Art of Scientific Investigation. London: Heinemann, 

1950. 

Birch, H. G., in J. Comp. Psychol, 382, 1945. 

Birney, R. C. and Teevan, R. C, eds., Instinct, Princeton, N. J., and London: 

van Nostrand, 1961. 
Blacklbr, A. W. See Hschberg, M. 

Blest, A. D., in Thorpe and Zangwill, eds., Current Problems in Animal Behaviour. 

Cambridge Univ. Press, 1961. 
Bodkin, M., Archetypal Patterns in Poetry* Oxford Univ. Press, 1934. 
Book, W. F., The Psychology of Skill Missoula, Mont.: Univ. of Montana, 1908, 
Brachet, J. L. A., article on 'Embryology, Human' in Encyclopaedia Britannkct, 

Vol. Vm, 389B (1955 ed.). 
Brachet, J. L. A., See Hyden, H., i960. 

Bragg, Sir Lawrence, The History of Science. London: Cohen & West, 1951. 
Brandt, G. W., article on 'Plot* in CasselVs Enc. of Literature, Vol, L London, 
1953* 

Bronowski, J., Science and Human Values. London: Hutchinson, 1961. 
Bryan, W, L. and Harter, N., in Psychol Review, £ 345-75* 1899. 
Burnet, J., Early Greek Philosophy. London: Blackwell, 1908. 

717 



7 i8 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Burt, Sir Cyril, 'The Structure of the Mind* in Br. J. of Educ. Psychol , Vol. XDC, 

June and November, 1949. 
Burt, Sir Cyril, 'The Concept of Consciousness' in Br. J. of Psychol., 53, 3, 1962. 
Burt, Sir Cyril, 'The Psychology of Laughter', Health Education Journal, Vol. 

HI, 1945. 

Butterheld, H., The Origins of Modem Science. London: G. Bell, 1949. 
Buttin, G., in Discovery. London, August 1962. 
Calvin, A. D., ed., Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
Cannon, W. B., Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear and Rage. New York: 

D. Appleton & Co., 1929 (2nd ed.). 
Carmichael, L„ in Manual of Child Psychology, pp. 43-166. New York: J. 

Wiley & Sons, 1954 (2nd ed.). 
Child, C. M., Physiological Foundations of Behaviour. New York: H. Holt & Co., 

1924. 

Cobb, S., Emotions and Clinical Medicine. New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1950. 
Coghhx, G. E., Anatomy and the Problem of Behaviour. Cambridge Univ. Press, 
1929. 

Cohen, J., in The New Scientist, pp. 950 if. London, 2.10.1958. 

Copernicus, N., On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres. Tr. Wallis, C. G. 
Chicago Univ. Press, 1952. 

Cozens, A., A New Method of Assisting the Invention in Drawing Original Com- 
positions of Landscape, 1765. 

Craig, W., in Biol. Bull., 34, 91-107, 1918. 

Craik, K. J. W., The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1943. 
Crile, W. G., The Origin and Nature of the Emotions. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders, 
1915. 

Crowther, J. G., Famous American Men of Science. London: Seeker & Warburg, 
I937- 

Crowther, J. G., British Scientists of the Nineteenth Century (2 volsi). London: 

Penguin Books, 1940. 
Dantzig, T., Number the Language of Science. London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1930. 
Darchen, R., in Z. Tierpsychol., p, 362-72, 1952. 
Darchsn, R., in Z. Tierpsychol, 11, i-ri, 1954. 
Darchen, R., in J. Psychol Norm. Path., 34, 190-205, 1957. 
Darwin, C. R., The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals* London: 

J. Murray, 1872. 

Darwin, C. R., The Origin of Species. London: J. Murray, 1873 (6th ed). 
Darwin, C. R. t Descent of Man. London: J. Murray, 1913 ed. 
Darwin, C. R., Life and Letters, ed. Francis Darwin, 3 vols. London, 1887. 
Darwin, C. R., More Letters, ed. Francis Darwin and A. C. Seward, 2 vols. 

London, 1903. 
Dbnes, P. See Fry, D. B. 

DntAC, P. A. M., in Scientific American, Vol. 208, No. 5, May 1963. 
Drake, Stuxman, Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo. New York: Anchor 
Books, 1957. 

Drever, J., 2nd, in Annual Review of Psychol Palo Alto, Calif.: Annual Reviews 
Inc., i960. 

Drever's Dictionary of Psychology. London: Penguin Books, 1962. 

Drhyer, J. L. E., Tycho de Brake. Edinburgh: A. & C. Black, 1890. 

Dubos, R., Louis Pasteur. Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1950. 

Dubos, R., Pasteur and Modem Science. New York: Anchor Books, i960. 

Duchenne (de Boulogne), G., Le Mdchanisme de la Physionotnie Humaine. Paris: 

P. Asselin, 1862. 
Albert Einstein; Philosopher^-ScientisL Illinois: Evanston, 1949. 



WORKS MENTIONED IN THIS BOOK 



719 



Empson, W., Seven Types of Ambiguity. London: Chatto & Windus, 1930. 
Evans, S. M., in The New Scientist. London, 2.5.1963. 

Exnbr, S., Die Physiohgie der facettierten Augen von Krebsen und Insekten. Leipzig 
und Wien: 1891. 

Farber, S. M. and Wilson, R. H. L., eds., Control of the Mind. New York and 

London: McGraw-Hill, 1961. 
Farrington, B., Greek Science. London: Pelican Books, 1953. 
Findlay, A., A Hundred Years of Chemistry. London: Duckworth, 1948 (2nd ed.). 
Fischberg, M. and Blackler, A. W., in Scientific American, September 1961, pp. 

13 1-8. 

Fode, F. L- See Rosenthal, R. 

Foord, E. N, See Hebb, D. O. 

Foss, B., in The New Scientist. London, 6.7.1961. 

Freud, Sigmund, Gesammelte Werke, Vols. I-XVTO. London: Imago Publishing 
Co., 1940-52. 

Fry, D. B. and Denes, 'P., in Mechanisation of Thought Processes (2 vols). London: 

H.M. Stationery Office, 1959. 
Galambos, R., in J. Neurophysiol., 19, 424-37, 1956. 
Galantbr, E. See Miller, G. A. 
Galileo, Galilei, Opere. Florence: Ediz. Naz., 1929-39. 
Galileo, Galilei, Dialogue Concerning Two New Sciences. Tr. H. Crew. Evanston, 

111., 1950. 

Galileo, Galilei, The Star Messenger, The Assay er, etc. See Drake, Stillman. 
Gallagher, J. J., in Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
Galton, F., Inquiries into Human Faculty. London and New York: Macmfllan, 

1883 (isted.). 
Gardner Murphy. See James, "William. 

Gastaut, H. and Beck, E., in The New Scientist. London, 1.3.1962. 
Gellhorn, E., Autonomic Regulations. New York: Inter-Science Publishers, Inc., 
1943. 

Gellhorn, E., Autonomic Imbalance. New York: Inter-Science Publishers, Inc., 
1957. 

GmsELiN, B., ed., The Creative Process. Univ. of Cali£ Press, 1952. 

Gibson, J. J., in Psychol Bull, 3$, 781-817, 1941. 

Gilbert, W., De Magnete. London, 1600. 

Goldstein, K., The Organism. New York: American Books, 1939. 

Goldstein, K., Human Nature in the Light of Psychopathology. Cambridge, Mass.: 

Harvard Univ. Press, 1947. 
Goldwater, R. and Treves, ML, eds. t Artists on Art. London: K. Paul, 1947. 
Gombrich, E. H., The Story of Art. London: Phaidon Press Ltd., 1962a. 
Gombrich, E. H., Art and Illusion. London: Phaidon Press Ltd., 1962b. 
Goodheld, J. See Toulmin, S. 

Graves, Robert, Poetic Unreason. London: Cecil Palmer, 1925. 
Gregory, J. C, The Nature of Laughter. London: K. Paul, 1924- 
Greig, J. Y. T„ The Psychology of Laughter and Comedy. London: G. Allen H 

Unwin, 1923. 
Gris, Juan, in Horizon, London, August 1946. 
Guthrie, E. R., The Psychology of Learning. New York: Harper, 1935. 
Haas, W. S., The Destiny of the Mind. London: Faber, 195& 
Hadamard, J., The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field. Princeton 

Univ. Press, 1949. 
Haldanb, J. B. S. See Spurway, H. 

Hamburger, V„ article on 'Regeneration* in Encyclopaedia Britanmca } VbL XIX, 
p. <*7 (1955 



720 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Hamburger, V., article on 'Experimental Embryology' in Encyclopaedia Britan- 

nica, Vol. VIII, p. 978 (1955 ed.). 
Hamburger, V. See WiUier, B. H. 

Hanley, C, in Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
Hanson, N. R., Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1961. 
Hardy, G. H., A Mathematician's Apology. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1940. 
Harlow, H. F., in Psychol. Rev., 60, 23-32, 1953. 

Head, Sir Henry, Aphasia and Kmdred Disorders of Speech. Cambridge Univ. 
Press, 1926. 

Head, Sir Henry, in B.J. ofEduc. Psychol, Vol. XIX, II and III, June and Novem- 
ber, 1949. 

Heath, T. L., Greek Astronomy. London: Dent, 1932. 

Hebb, D. O., The Organisation of Behaviour. New York: Wiley, 1949. 

Hebb, D. O., in Psychol. Rev., 62, 1955. 

Hebb, D. O., A Textbook of Psychology. Philadelphia and London: Saunders, 
1958. 

Hebb, D. O. and Foord, E. N., in J. Exp. Psychol, 35, 335-48, 1945- 
Heidenhain, M., Formen und Krdfte in der lebenden Natur. Berlin, 1923. 
Heinroth, O., Aus dem Leben der Vogel Leipzig, 1938. 
Heron, W. See Thompson, W. R. 

Herrick, C. J., The Thinking Machine. Chicago Univ. Press, 1929. 
Herrigel, E., Zen in the Art of Archery. London: Routledge & K. Paul, 1959 
ferded.). 

Hesse, M. B., Forces and Fields. London: T. Nelson, 1961. 
Helgard, E. R., Introduction to Psychology. London: Methuen, 1957. 
Hilgard, E. R., Theories of Learning. London: Methuen, 1958 (2nd ed.). 
Hilgard, E. R. and Marquis, D. G., Conditioning and Learning. New York: 

Appleton-Century, 1940. 
Himmelfarb, G., Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution. New York: Anchor 

Books, 1959. 

Hingston, R. W. G., in J. Bombay Nat. Hist. Soc., 31, 1926-7. 
Hixon Symposium. See JefFress, L. A., ed. 
Hobbes, T., Leviathan, %6$i. 

Hofer, ed., Histoire de V Invention de VImprimerie par les Monuments. Paris, 1840. 

VON Holst, E., in Naturwiss., 25, 1937. 

von Holst, E. in Experientia, 4, 1948. 

Hook, Sidney, in Commentary, New York, January 1959. 

Hooker, D„ in Genetic Neurology, ed. Weiss, P., 1950. 

Hoskin, M., in The Listener, London, 19.10.1961. 

Housman, A. E., The Name and Nature of Poetry. New York: Cambridge Univ. 
Press, 1933. 

Hovland, C. L, in J. Genet. Psychol, 51, 279-91, 1937. 

Hull, C. L., Principles of Behaviour. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1943. 
Hull, C. L., A Behaviour System. New Haven, Conn.: Yale Univ. Press, 1952. 
Humphrey, G., Thinking. London: Methuen, 195 1. 
Humphreys, L. G., in Exp. Psychol, 25, 141-158, 1939. 
Huxley, Aldous, in Control of the Mind, eds. Farber, S. M. and Wilson, H. L., 
1961. 

Hyden, H., Chapter 5 in The Cell, Vol. IV, eds. Brachet, J. and Mirsky, A. New 

York: Academic Press, i960. 
Hyden, H. ( in Macromolccular Specificity and Biological Memory, ed. Schmitt, 
F. O., 1962. 

Ittelson, W. H.» The Ames Demonstration in Perception. Princeton Univ. Press, 
195*. 



WORKS MENTIONED IN THIS BOOK 



721 



Jaensch, E. R., Eidetic Imagery. London: K. Paul, 1930. 
James, William, The Principles of Psychology. New York: H. Holt, 1890. 
James, William, in On Psychic Research, eds. Gardner Murphy and Bellon, R. O., 
1961. 

Jeefress, L. A., ed. Cerebral Mechanisms in Behaviour — The Uixon Symposium, 

New York: Wiley t 195 1. 
Jbncks, B. and Potter, P. B., in J. of Psychol, 4% 139. 
Jones, E., Sigmund Freud (3 vols.). London: Hogarth Press, 1953-7. 
Jones, E., in B. Med. J., 4, 8, 1956. 
Jones, M. R. See Nissen, H. W. 

Jung, C. G., Psychology of the Unconscious. New York: Moffat, Yard, 1916. 
Jung. C. G., Contributions to Analytical Psychology. London: K. Paul, 1928. 
Jung, C. G., Modern Man in Search ofJtis Soul London: K. Paul, 1933. 
Jung, C. G., The Integration of Personality. London: K. Paul, 1940. 
Keller, Helen, The Story of my Life. London: Hodder & Stoughton (1959 ed.). 
Kelly, J. Fitzmauricb, article on literature' in Encyclopaedia Britannica (12th 
ed.)- 

Kendall, J., Michael Farraday. London: Faber, 1955. 
Kepes, G., The New Landscape. Chicago: P. Theobold, 1956. 
Kepler, Johannes, Opera Omnia, ed. Ch. Frisch. Frankofurti et Erlangae, 
1858^71. 

Kepler, Johannes, Gesammelte Werke, ed. Caspar, v. Dyck and Hammer. 
Munich, 1938. 

Kluever, H., article on *Eidetic Images*, in Encyclopaedia Britannica, Vol. VIH 
(1955 ed.). 

Koestler, A., Insight and Outlook. London and New York: Macmillan, 1949. 
Koestler, A., The Sleepwalkers. London: Hutchinson, 1959. 
Koestler, A., The Lotus and the Robot. London: Hutchinson, i960. 
Kofeka, K., The Growth of the Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1930. 
Koffka, K., Principles of Gestalt Psychology. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1935. 
Kohler, W., Gestalt Psychology. London: G. Bell, 1930. 
Kohler, W., Dynamics in Psychology. New York: Liveright, 1940. 
Kohler, W., The Mentality of Apes. London: Pelican Books, 1957. 
Krechevsky, I., in Univ. Calif. Publ. Psychol, 6, 27-44* 1932. 
Kretschmer, E., The Psychology of Men of Genius. London: K. Paul, 193 1. 
Kretschmer, E., A Textbook of Medical Psychology. Trs. with an introd. by Strauss, 

E. B. London: H. Milford, 1934. 
Kortlandt, A., in Arch. Nierl Zool, 4, 401-42. 
Kuo, Z. Y., in J. Comp. Psychol, 14, 109-21, 1932. 

Ladefoged, P., in Mechanisation of Thought Processes. London: H.M. Stationery 
Office, 1959. 

Lamarck:, J. B., Zoological Philosophy. London: Macmillan, 1914. 
Lashley, K. S., in f. Anim. Behav.,^ % 361-6, 1913. 

Lashley, K. S., Brain Mechanisms and Intelligence. Chicago Univ. Press, 1929. 
Lashley, K. S./ The Neuro-Psychohgy of Lashley (Selected Papers). New York: 

McGraw-Hill, i960. 
Lashley, K. S. and Wade, M., in Psychol. Rev., 53, 72-87, 1946. 
de Launay, L., he Grand Ampere. Paris, 1925. 
Lawrence, W., in Mechanisation of Thought Processes, p. 411, 1959. 
Lee, Vernon (pseud. Paget, Violet), Beauty and Ugliness, and Other Studies in 

Psychological Aesthetics. London: J. Lane, 1912. 
Lehrman, D. S., in Instinct, eds. Birney, R. C. and Teevan, R. C. Princeton, 

N. J. and London; van No&trand, 1961. 
IivY-BRum, 1^ Primitive Mentality . London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1923. 



722 



THE ACT OP CREATION 



Levy-Bruhl, L., How Natives Think. London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1926. 
Lindauer, M., in Z. vergl Physiol, 34, 299-345. *952. 

Ltndsley, D. B., in Handbook of Experimental Psychology, ed. Stevens, S. New 
York: Wiley, 1951. 

Listowel (W. F. H.), Earl of, A Critical History of Modern Aesthetics. London: 

G. Allen & Unwin, 1933. 
Loewi, O., in Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, Vol. IV., No. l. Chicago Univ. 

Press, i960. 

Lorenz, K. L., in VInstinct dans le Comportement de V Animal et de VHomme. 

Paris: Masson et Cie, 1956. 
Lorenz, K. L., in Aspects of Form, ed. "Whyte L. L., 1951. 
Lorimer, F., The Growth of Reason. London: K. Paul, 1929. 
Loucks, R. B., in J. Psychol, j, 5-44, 1935. 
Loucks, R. B., in J. Comp. Psychol, 25, 315-32. 
McConnhx, J. V., in Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
McDougah, W., The Group Mind. New York: Putnam, 1920. 
McDougali, W., An Outline of Psychology. London: 1936. 
McGuigan, F. J., in Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
Mackay, D. M. and Sutherland, N. S., in Mechanisation of Thought Processes, 

1959- 

Macubod's Physiology in Modern Medicine, ed. Bard (9th ed.). St. Louis: Mosby, 
1941. 

Maixarme, S., Enquete sur VEvolution Littiraire. Paris, 1888. 

Markey, J. F., The Symbolic Process. London: K. Paul, 1928. 

Marquis, D. G. See Hilgard, E. R., 1940. 

Maubois, A., Alexander Fleming. London: Cape, 1959. 

Mechanisation of Thought Processes. London: H.M. Stationery Office, 1959. 

Merton, R. K., in The New Scientist. London, 2.11.1961. 

Miles, w. R., in Am. J. Psychol, 43, 193 1. 

Miller, G. A., Galanter, E. and Pribram, K. H., Plans and the Structure of 

Behaviour. New York: Holt, i960. 
Mirsky, A. See Hyden, H., i960. 
Montague, A., in Science, Vol. 130, p. 1572. 

Montmasson, J.-M., Invention and the Unconscious. London: K. Paul, 1931. 
Moray, N M in The Listener. London, 19.4. 1962. 

Mowrbr, O. H., in Annual Review of Psychology. Palo Alto, Calif.: Annual 
Reviews, 1962. 

Munn, N. L., Handbook of Psychological Research on the Rat. Boston: 1950. 
Mutch, T. R., in B.J. Ophthal, 28, 317-36, 1944. 
Needham, A. E., in The New Scientist. London, 2.11.1961. 
Needham, A. E., in Nature, 30.12.1961. 
Needham, J., in Scientia, 26, 1932. 

Newton, Eric, European Painting and Sculpture. London: Penguin Books, 1941. 
Newton, Eric, An Introduction to European Painting. London: Longmans, Green, 
1949. 

Newton, Sir Isaac, Opera Omnia. London, 1779-85. 

Nicholson, M., Science and Imagination. New York: Cornell Univ. Press, Great 
Seal Books, 1956. 

Nissen, H. W., in the Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, II, Current Theory 
and Research in Motivation, ed. Jones, M. R. Lincoln, Nebr.: Univ. of Nebraska 
Press, 1954. 

Nordenskioeld, E.» History of Biology. New York: K. Paul, 1928. 
Olds, J., in Proceedings of ike First International Congress of Neuro-Pharmacology. 
Amsterdam-London-New York-Princeton: Elsevier Publishing Co., 1959. 



WORKS MENTIONED IN THIS BOOK 



723 



Olds, J., in Psychiatric Research Reports of the American Psychiatric Association. 
January, i960. 

Osgood, C. E., Method and Theory in Experimental Psychology. New York: 

Oxford Univ. Press, 1953, i960. 
Paget, Sir Richard, Bt., Human Speech. London: K. Paul, 1930. 
Pavlov, L P., Conditioned Reflexes. Oxford Univ. Press, 1927. 
Penheld, W. and Roberts, L., Speech and Brain Mechanisms. Princeton Univ. 

Press, 1959. 

Pbtermann, B., The Gestalt Theory. London: K. Paul, 1932. 
Piaget, J.. Judgment and Reasoning in the Child. London: K. Paul, 1928. 
Piaget, J., The Child* s Conception of Physical Causality. London: K. Paul, 1930. 
Piaget, J., The Construction of Reality in the Child. New York: Basic Books, 1954. 
Picasso. See Goldwater, R. and Treves, M. 

Pierre, T. H., article on 'Imagery' in Encyclopaedia Britannica (1955 ed.). 
Pledge, H. T., Science since 1500. London: H.M. Stationery Office, 1939. 
Polanyi, M., Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge & K. Paul, 1958. 
Polya, G., Wie Sucht Man die Losung Mathematischer Aufgaben? Acta Psychological 

IV, 2, Haag-Martinus NijhofF, 1938. 
Polya, G., How To Solve It. Princeton Univ. Press, 1945. 
Polya, G., Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning. Oxford Univ. Press and Princeton 

Univ. Press, 1954. 

Popper, K. R., The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson, 1959. 
Pribram, K. H. See Miller, G. A., i960. 

Pribram, K. H., in Annual Review of Psychology, Vol. II. Palo Alto, Calif.: 

Annual Reviews, i960. 
Pringlb, J. W. S., in Behaviour ; 3, 174-215, 195 1. 
Pyke, M., The Boundaries of Science. London: Harrap, 1961. 
Rauxin, J. M., Le Rire et les Exhilarants. Paris, 1899. 
Reid, L. A., A Study in Aesthetics. London: G. Allen & Unwin, 193 1. 
Ribot, T. A., La Psychologie des Sentiments. Paris: F. Alcan, 1896. 
Richards, I. A., Principles of Literary Criticism. London: K. Paul, 1924. 
Roberts, L. See Penfield, W. 

Rosenthal, R. and Fodb, F. L., in Behavioural Science, Vol. 8, Part 3, July 1963. 
Ruch, T. C, in Stevens' Handbook of Experimental Psychology. New York: Wiley, 
1951. 

Russell, Bertrand, An Outline of Philosophy. London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1927. 
Russell, Philips, Benjamin Franklin , The First Civilised American. London: Benn, 
1927. 

Sachs, H., Master and Friend. London: Imago Publishing Co., 1946. 

de Santxllana, G., ed., Galileo Galilei Dialogue on the Great World Systems. 

Chicago Univ. Press, 1953. 
de Santhxana, G., The Crime of Galileo. Chicago Univ. Press, 1953. 
Sawyer, W. W., Prelude to Mathematics. London: Penguin Books, 1955. 
Schlosberg, H. See Woodworth, R. S. 

Schmitt, F. O.^ed., Macromolecular Specificity and Biological Memory. Cambridge, 

Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1962. 
Schrodinger, E., What is Life? Cambridge Univ. Press, 1944. 
ScsrvEN, M., in Psychology. Boston, Mass.: Allyn & Bacon, 1961. 
Seeiig, K., Albert Einstein. Zurich: Europa Verlag, 1954. 
Semon, R., The Mneme. London: G. Allen & Unw'n, 1921. 
von Senden, M., Raum- und Gestaltauffassung bet operierten BUndgeborenen vor 

und nach der Operation. Leipzig: Barth, 1932. 
Sherrington, C. S., Integrative Action of the Nervous System. New York: Scribner, 

1906. 



724 



THE ACT OF CREATION 



Sherwood Taylor, F., Science Past and Present. London: W. Heinemann, 1949. 
Skinner, B. R, The Behaviour of Organisms. New York: Appleton-Century, 
1938. 

Skinner, B. F., Science and Human Behaviour. New York: Macmillan, 1953. 
Skinner, B. F., in Amer, Psychologist, 8, 69-78, 1953. 

Smithers, D. W., A Clinical Prospect of the Cancer Problem. Edinburgh and London: 

Livingstone, i960. 
Spearman, C, Creative Mind. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1930. 
Spencer, H., Principles of Psychology. London: Williams & Williams, 1871. 
Spencer, H., in Essays on Education and Kindred Subjects. London: J, M. Dent, 1911. 
Spurway, H. and Haldane, J. B. S., in Behaviour, 6, 8-24, 1953. 
Stevens, S. S., ed., Handbook of Experimental Psychology. New York: Wiley, 

1951. 

Suixy, J., An Essay on Laughter. London : Longmans, Green, 1902. 

Sutherland, N. S. See Mackay, D. M. 

Suzuki, D. T., Zen and Japanese Culture. London: Luzac, 1959. 

Taton, R., Reason and Chance in Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson, 1957. 

Teevan, R. C See Birney. 

Thacker, L. A., in J. Comp. Physiol Psychol. 43, 86-98, 1950. 
Thompson, W. R. and Heron, W., in Canad.J. Psychol, 8, 17-31, 1954. 
Thorndike, E. L., Educational Psychology. New York: Lemcke and Buechner, 
1903. 

Thorndike, E. L., Animal Intelligence. New York: Macmillan, 191 1. 
Thorpe, W. H., teaming and Instinct in Animals. London: Methuen, 1956. 
Thorpe, W. H. and Zangwill, O. L., Current Problems of Animal Behaviour. 

Cambridge Univ. Press, 1961. 
Tulyard, E. M. W., The Elizabethan World Picture. London: Chatto & Windus, 

1946. 

Tinbergen, N., The Study of Instinct. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951. 
Ttnbergen, N., Social Behaviour in Animals. London: Methuen, 1953. 
Toiman, E« C, in Psychol Rev. t 45, 1-41, 1938. 
Tolstoy, L., What is Art?, Vol XVIII. Oxford Univ. Press, 1929. 
Toulmtn, S. and Goodfield, J. The Architecture of Matter. London: Hutchinson, 
1962. 

Toynbee, A., A Study of History. Oxford Univ. Press, 1947. 
Treves, M. See Goldwater, R. 

Waddington, C. H. in Phil Trans. Roy. Soc, B. f 221, 1932, 
Wade, M. See Lashley, K. S. 

Wallace, A. R., My Life (2 vols.). London: Chapman & Hall, 1905. 
Watson, J. B., Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviourist. Philadelphia and 

London: Lippincott, 1924. 
Watson, J. B., Behaviourism. London: K. Paul, 1928. 

Webster, D. L., article on 'Electricity' in Encyclopaedia Britannica, Vol. VIII 
(1955 ed.). 

Weiss, P., Principles of Development. New York: Holt, 1939. 
Weiss, P., in The Hixon Symposium. See Jem-ess, L. A., ed. 
Weiss, P., ed., Genetic Neurology. Univ. of Chicago Press, 1950. 
Weiss, P. See Willier, B. H., 1955. 
Wells, F. L., in Psychol Rev., 18, 229-33, 1911. 

Wernicke, C., Der aphasische Symptomen-Komplex. Breslau: Cohn und Weigert, 
1874. 

Wbver, E. G., Theory of Hearing. New York: Wiley, 1949. 
White, J. C. and Smithwick, R. H., The Autonomic Nervous System (2nd ed.). 
New York: Macmillan, 1941. 



WORKS MENTIONED IN THIS BOOK 



72S 



Whitehead, A. N., Science and the Modem World. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1953. 
Whitfield, I. C, in Mechanisation of Thought Processes, 1959. 
Whyte, L. L., ed., Aspects of Form. London: Lund Humphries, 1951. 
Whyte, L. L., The Unconscious Before Freud. New York: Anchor Books, 1962. 
Welenski, R. H., Modern French Painters. London: 1940. 
Weuer, B. H., Weiss, P. and Hamburger, V., Analysis of Development. Phila- 
delphia and London: W. B. Saunders, 1955. 
Wilson, R. H. L. See Farber, R. M. 

Wittgenstein, L., Tractates, Logico Philosophicus. London: K. Paul, 1922. 

Wolberg, L. R., Hypnoanalysis. New York: Grune & Stratton, 1945. 

Wolf, A., A History of Science, Technology and Philosophy. London: G. Allen & 

Unwin, 1950 (2nd ed.). 
Woodger, J. H., Biological Principles. London: K. Paul, 1929. 
Woodworth, R. S., Dynamic Psychology. New York: Columbia Univ. Press, 

1918. 

Woodworth, R. S., Experimental Psychology. New York: Holt, 1938; London: 

Methuen, 1939. 
Woodworth, R. S., in Am. J. Psychol, 60, 1 19-124, 1947. 
Woodworth, R. S. and Schlosberg, H., Experimental Psychology (revised ed.). 

New York: Holt, 1954. 
Ybrkes, R. M., Chimpanzees: A Laboratory Colony. New Haven: Yale Univ. 

Press, 1943. 
Zangwhx, O. L. See Thorpe, W. H. (1961). 
Zener, K., in Am. J. Psychol., 50, 384-403, 1937. 



SOME REFERENCES ON THE PSYCHOLOGY AND 
PHYSIOLOGY OF WEEPING 



A. General Psychology, Theories, etc. 

Barnett, S. A., 'The expression of emotions*, New Biol 22, 73-90» *957 
Dana, C. L., *The Anatomic Seat of the Emotions— A Discussion of the 

James-Lang Theory', Arch. Neurology and Psychiatry, 1921. 
Darwin, C, The Expression of Emotions, D. Appleton & Co. 136, 208, 373, 
1896. 

Enroth, E., 'Om Graat\ Finska LakSallsk. Handl. 77, 76-88, 1935. 
Kxineberg, Social Psychology, 196, 1940. 

Lund, F. H., *Why do we weep?', J. Soc. Psychol 1, 136-51, 1930. 
Lund, F. H., Emotions, etc. Ronald Press Co., New York, 47 ff., 1939, 
Plessner, H., *Das Problem von Lachen und Weinen*, Tijdschr. Phil. 2, 
317-84, 1940. 

Plessner, H., Lachen und Weinen, Araheim, Netherlands, 1950. 
Rtjckmick, C. A., The Psychology of Feeling and Emotion, McGraw Hill, 

New York, 338 ft, 193& 
Spitz, C, Zur Psychologie des Weinens, Zeulenroda, Sporn., 1935. 
Sulley, J., An Essay on Laughter, Longmans Green, London, 67-70, 1902. 



72(5 THE ACT OP CREATION 

Young, P. T., 'Laughter and weeping, etc. in students*, J. Soc. Psychol. 8, 
311-34, 1937 

Young, P. T., Emotions in Man and animal, J. Wiley and Sons, London, 1943. 
Weeping in chimps, 22; 
Utility of, 58; 

Cultural determination, 184; 
Patterns of, 254-8; 

Developmental, 164, 167, 177-9, 354. 255. 

B. Physiology 

Arnold, M. B., Emotion and Personality, Vol. 2, Neurological and Physio- 
logical Aspects, Cassell, London, i960; 
Weeping in thalamic disease, 12, 13; 
Weeping and eeg, 162. 
Chorobski, S., 'The Syndrome of Crocodile Tears', Arch. Neur. and Psy- 
chiatry, 1951. 

Ford, 'Paroxysmal lacrimation etc.', Arch. Neurol. Psychiat. Chicago, 29, 
I933- 

Geoffrey Walsh, E», Physiology of the Nervous System, Longmans Green, 

London, 1957. 

Crocodile tears, 408. 
Kling, C, 'The Role of the Parasympathetic in Emotions*, Psychol. Rev., 

1933. 

Mutch, T. R., "The lacrimation reflex', Brit. J. Ophthal. 28, 317-36, 1944- 
Rowbotham, G- F., 'Observations on the effect of trigeminal denervation', 

Brain, 62, 364-80, 1939. 
White, J. C. and Smithwick, R. H. et al (3rd ed.), The Autonomic Nervous 

System, 40, 41, 250, 1952 

C. Weeping and Personality Development 

Hunt, J. Mc. V. (ed.), Personality and the Behaviour Disorders, Vol. 1, Ronald 
Press, Chap. 3, Mowrer, O. H., Dynamic theory of personality, 89, 1944- 

Riviere, Interntl.J. of Psychoanal. 17, 395-422 (Psychological development 
in infancy.) 1936. 

Sullivan, H. S., Conceptions of Modern Psychiatry, Tavistock Pbns., London, 
15, 17, 89, 1953. 

Symonds, P. M., Dynamic Psychology, Appleton Century Crofts, New York, 
48, 280, 1949. 

Symonds, P. M., The Ego and the Self, Appleton Century Crofts, New York, 
13, 1951. 

D. Ontogenetics of Weeping 

Ames, L. B-, 'Motor correlates of infant crying*, J. Genet. Psychol., 59, 239- 
47, 1941. 

Bayley, N., 'A study of crying in infants etc.*, J. Genet. Psychol, 40, 306-29, 
1932. 

Borgquist, A., 'Crying*, Am. J. of Psychol., 1906. 

Clarke, Hunt and Hunt,/. Gen. Psychol. 17, 398-402 (Weeping and startle 
pattern.), I937- 

Goodenough, F. L., Anger in Young Children, 66-9, 244-9, 1931. 
Goodenough, F. L., J. Abn. Soc. Psychol. 27, 328-33 (Weeping in blind and 

deaf children.), 1932. 
Goodenough, F. L., Developmental Psychology (2nd ed.), Appleton Century. 

201, 257; Individual differences, 273, 1945 



REFERENCES 



727 



Kanner, L., Child Psychiatry, Tanner, Illinois. 35, 599, i960 
Landis, C. and Hunt, W. A., The Startle Pattern, Farrar and Rhinehart, New 
York, 141, 1939- 

Landreth, C, 'Factors associated with crying in young children', Child 

Dev. 12, 81-97, i°4i- 
Mowrer, O. H. and Mowrer, W. M., 'The meaning and measurement 

of crying', Child Study, 15, 104-7, 1938. 
Munn, N. L., Evolution and Growth of Human Behaviour, Riverside Press, 

Cambridge, Massachusetts, 407 ff., 1955. 
Rosenzweig, S., 'Babies are taught to cry; a hypothesis/,. Ment. Hyg. New 

York, 38, 81-4, 1954 
Ruja, H., 'The relation between neonate crying and length of labour*, J. 

Genet. Psychol 73, 53-5 (Test of Rankian birth cry hypothesis.), 1948* 
Valentine, C. W., Psychology of Early Childhood (3rd ed.), Methuen, London, 

1946. 

Early Appearance, 86 f£; 
Inhibition of, 117; 
Social, 293; 
Resentment of, 297; 
Sympathy, 298. 

E. Psychopathotogy and Weeping 

Davison, C. and Keiman, 'Pathological laughing and crying*, Arch. Neurol. 

Psychiat. 42, 595-^33* 1939- 
Greenacrb, P., 'Pathological weeping', Psychoandl. Quart. 14, 62-75, 1945. 
Greenacrb, P., 'Urination and weeping', Am. J. Orthopsychiat, 15, 81-8, 
I945- 

Kbt.t.y, G. A., The Psychology of Personal Constructs, Vol 2 } Clinical Diagnosis 
and Psychotherapy, Norton and Co., New York, 896 ft., 1113 ff., 1955. 

Lacombe, P., 'A special mechanism of pathological weeping*, Psychoanal 
Quart. 27, 248-51, 1958. 

R Depth Psychological Formulation* 

Abraham K., Selected Papers on Psychoanalysis, Hogarth Press, 483 (Weeping 
in women as unconscious wish to urinate like a man.), 1954 

Breuer, J. and Freud, S., Studies in Hysteria, Hogarth InterntL Psycho- 
analytical Library No. 50, 162 ft, 163 fh. (Weeping and abreaction arrears.), 
1056. 

Beldman, S. S., 'Crying at the happy ending*, J. Am. Psychoanal Ass. 4, 

477-85, 195<5. 
(See Greenacrb 1945, 2, in Section E above.) 
Heilbrunn, G., 'On weeping', Psychoanal. Quart. 24, 245-55, 1955- 
Montague, ML F. A., 'On the physiology and psychology of swearing', 

Psychiat., 189-201 (Weeping in women as aggression outlet, substitute 

for function swearing performs for men.), 1942. 
Peto, E., 'Weeping and laughter*, Intern. J. of Psychoanal 27, 120-33, 1956. 
Weiss, J., 'Crying at the happy ending*, Psychoan. Rev., 1952. 

G. Relation of weeping to Psychosomatic Pathology. 

Alexander, F., Psychosomatic Medicine etc., G. Allen and Unwin, London, 
1952; 

and Asthma, 139; 
Hysterical, 58; 
and Urticaria, 203. 



728 THE ACT OF CREATION 

Dunbar, R, Emotions and Bodily Changes, Columbia, New York, 43 (Weep- 
ing and neurosis in Urticaria.), 1954- 

Halliday, J. C, 'Approach to asthma', Brit. J. Med. Psychol. 17, 1, 1937. 

Saul, L. J. and Bernstein, C, 'The emotional settings of some attacks-of 
Urticaria', Psychosom. Med. 3, 349, 1941. 



ACKNO WLEDGEMENTS 



The author and publishers wish to thank the following for permission to quote 
from various works: Basic Books, Inc., New York (The Unconscious Before 
Freud, by L. L. Whyte); Doubleday & Co., Inc., New York {Pasteur and Modern 
Science, by Rene Dubos, © i960, by Educational Services, Inc. (Anchor Science 
Study Series), and Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, by Gertrude Himmelfarb, 
© 1959, 19^2, by Gertrude Kristol); the Clarendon Press, Oxford [The Study of 
Instinct, by Dr. N. Tinbergen); John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York (Cerebral 
Mechanisms in Behaviour— The Eixon Symposium, ed. L. A. Jeffress); Litde, Brown 
& Co., Boston (Louis Pasteur, by Rene Dubos, © 1950, by Rene Dubos); George 
Allen & Unwin, Ltd., London (Thinking, by Sir Frederick Bardett); Europa 
Verlag, Zurich (Albert Einstein, by Carl Seelig); Cambridge University Press, 
New York (The Name and Nature of Poetry, by A. E. Housman); G. Bell, London 
(Gestalt Psychology, by "W. Kohler); Allyn & Bacon, Boston (Psychology, ed. 
A. D. Calvin, © 1961, by Allyn & Bacon); Methuen & Co., London (Learning 
and Instinct in Animals, by "W. H. Thorpe); Roudedge & Kegan Paul Ltd., London 
(Personal Knowledge t by Michael Polanyi, Mentality of Apes, by W. Kohler, The 
Symbolic Process, by J. F. Markey, The Growth of Reason, by F. Lorimer, and 
Invention and the Unconscious, by J.-M. Montmasson). 



2A* 



INDEX 



Absolute pitch, 521 
Abstract art, 374 
Abstract painting, 370 
Abstract thought, 607-10 
Abstraction, 607-10 

and practicality, 705-6 

perceptual and conceptual, 535-6 
Adam, 47 
Adaptation, 448 

second order, 450 
Addams, Charles, 52 
Adrenal-sympathico system, 274 
Adrenalin, 205 
Aesculapius, ix 
Aesop, 101 
Aesthetic experience 

bisociative patterns in, 383-5 

difficulty of analysing, 391 

•essence of, 328, 329, 383 
Aesthetic judgement, 

snobbery and, 400 et seq. 
Aesthetic satisfaction, difference from 

sensory gratification, 385 
Aesthetics, hedonist, 385 
Affinity, association by sound, 314-15 
After-images, 529 
Age of enlightenment, 147 
Aggressive-defensive impulses, sublima- 
tion of, 259 
Aggressive-defensive tendency in humour, 

52, 54, 56, 62, 89, 92, 95 
Agrippa, 256 
Albert the Great, 255 
Alchemist's Rosarium, 145 
Alchemists, 256 
Algebra, rules for learning, 638 
Alice, 78, 174 
AUchazen, 255 
Allport, G. W. t 501, 507 
Amber, loadstones and, 661 et seq. 
Amino-adds, 418 



Ammophila, 566 

Ampere, A. M., 117, 230, 668, 669 

An Essay on the Principle of Population, 140 

Analogies, hidden, 179 

Analogy, intuition and, 199-207 

Analytical geometry, 230 

Anarchy, creative, 229-30, 335 

Anatomists, 256 

Anatomy, 26$ 

Anaximander, 131, 137 

Ancient Mariner, The, 362 

Animal behaviour, patterns of, 477 

Animal electricity, 667 

Animal Farm, 90 

Animal Intelligence, 570 

Animal learning, 562-5 

Animals 

exploratory drive in, 505-6 

fear and curiosity, 502-3 

inquisitiveness of, 502 et seq. 

latent learning in, 498 

originality in captivity, 493 

tournament fights between, 475 (see also 
Chimpanzees, Dogs) 
Annalen der Chemie, 240 
Anthropomorphism, 296 
Antibiotics, 194 
Anticipatory behaviour, 576 
Apes, see Chimpanzees 
Aphasic patients, 599, 601, 602 

note on, 604, 605 
Aphrodite, 47 

Apollonius of Perga, 102, 335 
Appetitive behaviour, 480-4 
Archetypes, 3$3~4* 3*9, 300 
Archimedes, 212, 676 

principle of, 105-8, 109 
Aristarchus, 234, 677 
Aristophanes, 53, 73 
Aristotle, 53, I3i» *7<S> 258, 3°7 

on motivation, 675-6 



731 



732 



INDEX 



Aristotelian physics, 216, 228 
Art 

and progress, 393 ec seq. 
appraisal of work of, 404-5 
ascending gradients in, 390-1 
bisociative patterns in, 383-5 
bisociative processes in, 371-3 
cliches in, 376, 377, 378 
cumulative progress in, 393-5 
economy in, 335-40 
evolution of, 335 

explicit statement to implicit hint, 337-8 

folded in, 338 et seq. 

forgeries, 400, 401, 402 

form of communication, 266 

Greek, 394, 395-6 

history of, 336, 367-9, 393-6 

infolding, 398, 399 

Italian, 394-5, 397 

law of infolding and, 387-8 

motif, 372-3 

motion and rest in, 387-90 
originality and emphasis, 333-5 
period-consciousness, 406-7 
pigment and meaning in, 370-1 
progress not towards unitary laws, 
353 

relationship with science, 27, 28 
school of self-transcendence, 328 
statement and implication, 396-9 
taste and distaste, 385-7 
unity in, 387-90 
visual inferences, 373-6 
visual representation m, 367-9 
Art and Illusion, 378 

Art-forms, turning points in history of, 

334-5 
Articulation, 534 
Artist, 27, 255, 257 

and caricature, 70-2 

bisociative act a juxtaposition of experi- 
ence, 352 

catharsis of experiences, 328 

deadening influences on, 336-7 

element of explorer inherent, 507 

his medium, 333-4 

individual style of, 334 

law of infolding and the, 341-2 

measure of originality, 334 

stale techniques and the, 336 
As You Like It, 68 
Asexual reproduction, 451 
Association, 642 et seq, 

by sound affinity, 3 14-1 5 



by similarity, 200, 646, 651 
controlled, 646 
free, 646 

in memorizing, 538-9 

types of, 646-7 
Association tests, 39-40 
Associationism, 642, 646-7 
Associative contexts, 38, 40 

condensation in, 179 
Associative learning, 587 
Associative routine, criteria distinguishing 

bisociative originality from, 657-60 
Astronomers, 48, 242, 251, 252 (see also 

Universe, Copernicus, Kepler) 
Astronomy, synthesis with Physics, 124 
(see also names of astronomers, e.g. 
Copernicus, Kepler) 
Atheism, Darwin and, 692-6 
Atoms, hooked, 164-6 
ATP, 420, 421, 437 
Attunements, multiple, 642-6 
Auditory perception, 513 et seq. 
Augustine, 148 

Automatization of skills, 155, 156 
Autonomous activities, 468 
Autonomous nervous system, 57, 58, 
62 

Autotomy in animals, 451 
Awareness, 632 

defined, 155 

degrees of, 154-7 

linear gradient of, 156 

linear scale of, 180 

peripheral, 159 

periphery of, 164 

subsidiary, 159 
Axial gradients in regeneration, 455 



Bacon, Francis, 53, 74, 251, 342 
Bacon, Roger, 227 
Baerends, G. P., 476, 565, 567 
Bain, A., 17, 53 » 200 
Balancing skills, 42, 548 
Ball, John, 326 
Ballad of Reading Gaol, 77 
Balzac, H., 83, 318 
Bambi, 67 

Bartlett, Sir Frederick, 43, 515, 525, 539 

quoted, 231 
Basilar membrane of car, 516 
Bates, H. W., 141 
B.B.C. Brains Trust, 80 



INDEX 



733 



Beagle, H.M.S., 134, 135, 6gz, 694 
Beauty 

a function of truth, 331 

truth and, 327-31 
Beck, E., 550 
Becquerel, H., 195-6 
Bede, the Venerable, 255 
Beerbohm, Max, 53 
Behaviour 

acquired, 509 

anticipatory, 576 

appetitive, 480-4 

exploratory, 501, 502, 504-7 

functional analysis, 497 

genetics of, 475-7 

innate, 509 

unit of, 499 

verbal, in speaking, 593 
Behaviour of Organisms, 556 
Behaviour-patterns, instinct-based, 485-8 
Behavioural matrices, 549 
Behaviourism, 44, 495, 496 

Watsonian, 559 
Behaviourists, 557, 558 

and the unconscious, 157 
Benevolent Magician, 255, 256, 257 
Bergson, H. L., 32, 46, 47, 49, 52, 53, 61, 

78, 92, 312, 363 
Berlyne, D. £., 501, 505, 509, 510 
Bernard, Claude, 706 
Beveridge, W. I. B , 211, 213, 254 
Bicycle, riding a, 42, 548 

stamping-in, 550 
Binet-Mueller test, 532 
Biological evolution, 226 
Biological ripeness, 109 
Bird-song, 491-2 
Birds 

counting ability of, 492 

prclinguistic number sense of, 535-6 
Birkhoff, G. D., 177 
Bishop, the Marquis and the, 33-4 
Bisociated contexts, clean-cut example of, 
78 

Bisociation, 35 et seq. 
artistic, 352 

chimpanzee and, 573-5 
displacement of attention, 77-8 
impersonation, 67-8 
in caricature and satire, 70-4 
incompatible matrices, 59 
metaphorical and literal meanings, 66 
misfits and, 74-5 
of child-adult, 68-9 



of coincidence, 78 
of incompatibles, 622 
of man and animal, 67 
of nonsense humour, 78-9 
of pun, 64-5 

of rhythm and meaning, 312 

of sound and meaning, 90 

of structure and function, 75-7 

of tickling, 79-81 

of trivial and exalted, 69-70 

of wine-press and seal, 123 

play of ideas, 65-6 

professional and commonsense logic, 

65-6 
scientists and, 72 
synthesis of signs and things, 222 
the clown and, 81-2 
Bisociative mechanisms, and the comic, 

182 

Bisoaative originality, criteria distinguish- 

uig associative routine from, 657-60 
Bisociative patterns, 45 
in aesthetic experience, 383 
in dreams, 179 
Bisociative thinking, passive, in dreaming, 
178 

Bit learning, 522 

Black Magician, 257, 259 

Blackborough, Peter, 663 

Blake, William, 316, 322, 326, 340, 362 

Blimp, Colonel, 61 

Blood-brother ceremony, 294 

Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear and 

Rage, 55* 280 
Bodily changes, in weeping and crying, 

271-2 
Bodkin, Maud, 362 
Boehme, Jacob, 148 
Bohr, Niels, 198, 669, 671 
Boillot, M., 697, 698 
Boltzmann, 265 
Bond, Henry, 663 
Bom, Max, 245 
Botticelli, 329, 330 
Bore, H., 204 
Bragg, Sir L„ 233 

Brain, conceptual and speech mechanisms 

of, 602 
Brain surgery, 315, 316 
Brain-teaser, example of, 183-4 
Brain-twisters, 91 
Brandt, G. W., 353 
Braque, 329 
Brave New World, 73 



734 



INDEX 



Bronowski, J., 200, 230 

note on, 254 
Browne, Sir Thomas, 207 
Brucke, Professor, 217 
Bryan, W. L., 432, 544 
Buddhist monk problem, 183-4, 189 
Budding, 451 

Button, Comte de, 131, 132, 228 

Burnet, J., 229 

Burt, Sir Cyril, 23, 48, 603 

note on, 96 
Butler, Samuel, 144 
Butterfield, H., 235, 260 



Caddis-ply larva, 486 
Calculus, infinitesimal, 110 
Calderon, 53 

Cannon, W. B., 55, 205, 211, 280, 286 

Cantor's theory of infinite aggregates, 331 

Caricature, 70-2, 90 

Caricaturist, 182 

Carlyle, T., 329 

Carpenter, W. B., 152 

Carracci, Annibale, 402 

Carroll, Lewis, 67 

Cartoons, 70-2 

Cat, auditory nerve of, 514 

Cat in the Rain, 339 

Catharsis, 306-9 

Catholic Universe Bulletin, 37 

Cats, 568-71 

Causal sequencies, reversal of, 179 
Causality, 6x5-18 

physical, 584 
Cavendish, 666 

Cell, nucleus and cytoplasm, 421-3 
Cell-matrix, 419-21 
Centipede, paradox of the, 75-7 
Central nervous system, control of motor 

activities by, 447 
Centrosomes, 420 

Cerebral cortex, regenerative adaptations 

of, 458 
Cervantes, 148 
Cezanne, 329, 538 
Chambers, Robert, 132 
Champollion, 186 
Chaplin, Charlie, 61, 305 
Character-types, technique of creating, 68 
Characters, fictional, 345 et seq. 
Charcot, 152 
Chekhov, A., 69 



Chemistry, learned by explicit verbal 

form, 637 
Chess, 40-2, 639, 650 

problems, 91 
Child, C. M., 452, 453 
Child-Adult, bisociation of, 68-9 
Children 

and causality, 616 

contradictions due to scales of relevant 

values, 627 
learning to speak, 594 et seq. 
picture-strip language of, 606 
questioning mania of, 616-18 
stage where symbolic relations become 

relevant, 628 
symbols as action-words, 606-7 
vocabulary of, 221 
Chimpanzees 
and tools, 573-4 

experiments with, 101-2, 103-5, 108, 
110, 119, 220, 504, 556, 573-5, 
576-82 
Chloroplasts, 420 
Chromosomes, 419, 420, 421 
Chronological matrices, 640 
Cicero, 53, 74 
Circular motion, 128, 129 
Classificatory codes, 640 
Closure principle, 387 
Clown, 81-2 
Cocaine Episode, 218-19 
Cocteau, Jean, 182 

Codes and coding, 38, 40, 42, 43, 44, 64, 
96, 163,209,416, 4x8-21,424,428,464, 
471-3, 479, 484, 518. 524, 552, 572, 
593, 636-9, 642 et seq., 645, 656 et seq. 

autonomy of, 552 

explanation of, 39, 40 

in piano-playing, 547 

in playing soccer, 549 

logical, 625 

mode of operation, 40 

of organisms, 4x7 et seq. 

of perception, 376-80 

suspension of, at discovery stage, 178 
Coghill, G. E., 430, 431, 447, 506 
Cognitive theories, 561-2 
Cohen, J., 342 

Coincidence, bisociation of, 78 
Coleridge, S. T., 152, 166*, 167, 169 
Colour, temperature values of, 375 
Comedy, 304 
Comic 

Bergson's interpretation of the, 46, 47 



INDEX 



735 



bisociative mechanisms of the, 182 
defining the, 31-2 
Comic simile, 340 

Comic technique, 82-6 (see also Humour, 

Laughter) 
Common sense, 636 
Complexes, repressed, 181 
Composing music, 547 
Concepts, 642, 645 

defined, 597 
Concretization, and symbolism, 182-6 
Conditional fear reflex, 610 
Conditional reflex, 498 
Conflict, 350-2 
Connoisseurship, 537 
Conscious 

and unconscious experiences, 154 

ante-chamber of, 160, 161 

code guiding focal beam of, 163 

levels of, 658 

linear scale of awareness distinguished 

from hierarchic levels, 632 
presence chamber of, 160 
protoplasmic, 154, 292 
symbiotic, 292 

two-way traffic with unconscious, 18 1-2 
verbal thinking dominating, 600 
Conservation of Energy, Principle of, 
239 

Constable, 378, 379. 381, 382 
Consumxnatory act, 480-4 
Cotttes Drolatiques, 83 
Context level, in telegraphy, 545 
Contradiction 

law of, 627, 628 

three stages in law of, 627 
Contradistinction, law of, 625 
Controls, supra-ordinate, 468 
Controversy, scientific, 240 et seq. 
Convention and creation, 380-2 
Copernicus, 124, 125, 128, 216, 217, 225, 
234, 240, 6*77 

fear of ridicule, 238 
Cordelier, Frere, 122 
Coronation Street, 302-3 
Cosmic vortices, theory of, 663 
Costa of Haarlem, 122 
Coue\ E., 313 
Coulomb, 664, 666 
Counting, 623, 624 
Course in Poetics, A, 317 
Coward, Noel, 67 
Cozens, Alexander, 376 
Crab, ambulation of, 439 



Craig, W., 481, 492 

Craik, K.J-, 506, 564, 585, 618, 634 

Creation 

act of, based on an underlying pattern, 
330 

convention and, 380-2 

judging an act of, 330-r 

visual, 366 et seq. 
Creative act 

bisociation of two genetic codes, 452 

dreamlike phases of, 325 

musical composition, 547 

psychologists' views on, 12-13 

regression in, 315, 316 

relaxing of controls in, 178 
Creative activity 

a regression, 462 

humour and, 31 

operates on two planes, 35, 3d 

patterns of, 27 
Creative anarchy, 229-30, 335 
Creative emphasis, 82, 83 
Creative instability, 498 
Creative Mind 

note on, 177 
Creative originality, 82-3, 131 
Creative synthesis, see 'Discovery' 
Creativity 

regeneration and, 463-5 

starts where language ends, 177 
Crowther, J. G., on Maxwell, 689-90' 
Crustaceans, regeneration in, 451 
Crying 

comparison with weeping, 271-2 

in hunger, 281 

in pain, 280 

with fear, 281 
Cubist, 376 
Curiosity, 501-4 
Cutting of an Agate, The, 674 



Daguerse, 195 
Daily Express, 405 
Dante, 14S 
Dantzig, T., 624 
Darchen, R., 505 

Darwin, C, 29, 8o, 131, 13*. 133 et seq., 
213, 225, 503. 692-6, 707 

natural selection and, 131-44 

note on, 254 

on pain, 280 
Darwin, Dr. E», 132. *37» I43i 26s 
Darwin, K, 692 



736 



INDEX 



Data, collecting, 233 
Daumier, 72 
Davy, H., 668 
Day-dreaming, 635 

dreaming and, 180 
Death-and-Rebirth motif, 358 et seq. 
Deformity, bisociation of, 74-5 
de Gaulle, General, 70 
Degradation theory of laughter, 53 
De Magnete, 662 
de Mere, Chevalier, 103 
Denes, P., 534 

De~particularization, in hearing, 515 
Descartes, Rene\ 53, 148, 149. 211, 228, 

250, 342, 663 
Descent of Man, The, 503, 693 
Desdemona, 33, 58 

Destructive environmental conditions, 449 
Dialogue Concerning Two New Sciences, 265, 
679 

quoted, 680-2 
Dickens, Charles, 75 
Dictionary of Psychology, 510 
Dimensional variables in thinking, 630-1 
Dirac, Paul, 245, 329 
Discovery 

analogies related to scientific develop- 
ment, 224 

animal, 101-2, 103-4 

anti-rabies vaccine, 114 

'blindness' of thinkers, 216-20 

by analogy and intuition, 199-207 

by misadventure, 192 et seq. 

chance and ripeness, 108-18 

collective, 335 

concept of the unconscious, 147-54 

data and, 233-5 

derivations of artistic, 328 

false inspirations and, 212-14 

faulty integrations and, 214-16 

Fuchsian functions, 1 14-16 

independent multiple, 1x0 

influence on art-forms, 334-5 

inoculation, 1 12-13 

letter-press, 123 

links in history of, 230 

magnetism and electricity, 661 et seq. 

mathematical, 114-18, 164 

mechanism of the solar system, 124-30 

multiple, 335 

natural selection, 13.1-44 

principle of Archimedes, 105-8 

principle of relativity, 1 1 1 

printing press, X21-4 



rare in Art, 393 
recurrent cycles in, 335 
rediscovery, 335 
Relativity Theory, 175-6 
rules of, 652 

scientists and, 190, 66x et seq. 

suspension of codes of disciplined 
reasoning in, 178 

unexpected, 145 et seq. 

vaccination, 1 12-14 
Discrimination, 610-11, 625 

learning process, 490 
Disease, controversies over origins of, 242 
Disney, Walt, 67 
Displacement, 189-91 

activities, 485 

of emphasis, 464 

phenomenon of, 179 
Disraeli, B., 133 
DNA, 417 et seq., 421 
Dogmatic matrices, 640 
Dogs, 563-4. 565 
Don Quixote, 38, 305 
Donald Duck, 67 
Donne, John, 229, 359, 363, 674 
Double entendre, 91 
Double identity, 179 
Dramatic art 

conflict, 350-2 

identification and, 345-6 

origin of, 308-9 

paradox and climax, 350-1 
Dreamer, gullibility of the, 179 
Dreaming 

essential part of psychic metabolism, 181 

displacement in, 189 

passive bisociation in, 178 

restorative powers of sleep derived from, 
462 

reversal of logic in, 191 
Drever.J., 535 
Dubos, R., 113, 247, 26 x 
Duncker, Carl, 189 
Dfllrer, 329 

Dynamic equilibrium, 449 
Dynamo, electrical, 194, 670 



Ear, and hearing, 5x3 
Eastman, Max, 79 
Echo, 48 
Eclogues, 146 
Economy, 335-40. 397 
in authonhtpv 339 



INDEX 



737 



Eddington, 251, 265 

Edison, T., 190, 196, 197, 256, 705 

Effect, Law of, 495» 496 

Egg, fertilized, 417 ec seq. 

molecules of, 417-18 
Ego, 292-3 
Egoxnorphism, 296 
Egyptian painting, 368, 376, 377 
Eidetic images, 530-1 
Einstein, A., 111, 146, 173, 175-6, i76-7t 
183, 211, 213, 214, 234, 243, 249, 251, 
256, 258, 461, 672, 704-5 

and cosmic religiousness, 262 

description of working methods, 171-2 
Electric motor, 194 
Electrical conduction, 665 
Electricity 

and magnetism, 661 et seq. 

unification with magnetism, 230 
Electromagnetic radiation, 670 
Electrostatic field, 666 
Elements, transmutability of chemical, 215 
Eliot, T. S., 12, 45 
Embryo 

organizers and inducers, 425-8" 

regulative and mosaic development, 
423-4 

Embryonic development, motivation in, 
4<$7 

Emerson, 388, 389 
Emma Bovary, 310 
Emotion 

earthing of, 328 

science and, 255 et seq. 
Emotional catharsis, 383 

at moment of discovery, 87-8 

bodily changes of self-asserting, 56 

catharsis of, 87, 88 

inertia of, 55-63 

James-Lange theory of, 286 

laughter and, 53 et seq. 

participatory tendencies, 54, 271 et seq. 

physiological effects of, 57 

reason and, 56 

self-transcending tendencies, 54, 88, 285 
three-dimensional theory of, 276 

Emotive potentials, 321-2, 328 

Emotive response, law and order in, 325-6 

Empathy, 188 

projective, 296V 374» 386, 387 

Empedokles, 131 

Emphasis, 334 

Empsoa, W„ 353 

Engrains, 519-20, 523 



Environment, 448, 469 

variable, 450 
Enzyme-producing genes, 419, 422 
Enzymes, 418 
Epicureans, 131 
Epicutur, 164 

Epileptics, induced fits in, 3 11 
Equilibrium, 448-50 
Erasmus, 256 
Erewhon, 73 
Escapism, 306 
Essay on Man, 16 
Ether-drift, 244 
Eudoxus, 256 
Euhemerus, 11 
Evolution, 226 

regeneration and, 465-6 

surplus of needs an inherent character- 
istic, 493 
Evolutionary doctrine, 131 
Evolutionary process, complementary 

aspects of, 416-19 
Exaggeration, 333 
'Excitation clang', 442 
Experiment, verification by, 214 
Experimental science, Galileo's, 680 
Explanation, gradations in, 619-20 
Exploratory drive, 87, 501, 502. 504-7 

in organisms, 506-7 

inherent, 507 
Expressionist art, 370 
Eyesight, 158 
Eysenck, 242 



Facts, collecting, 233 
Falstaff, 61 

Faraday, Michael, 170, 171, 190, 194. 213, 

230, 321, 668, 670, 687-8 
Fear reflex, conditioned, 610 
Fechncr, 153, 495 

Fermentation, controversy on, 240-1 
Fey, Dietrich, 400 
Fibonacci sequence, 329 
Fichte, I. H., 151, 152, 159 
Fiction, identification in, 345-6 
Fidelio, 68 

Finnegans Wake, 339 
Fish 

nest-building, 479-8o 

swimming motions of, 438 
Flatworm, 45*» 454 
Fleming, A*, 145. I94» 200» 707 
Flower, the root and the, 362-3 



738 



INDEX 



'Fluency', 12 

Focal awareness, 180 

Fogg museum, Harvard, 402 

Following response, 489-91 

Fontanelie, 228 

Foreshortening, 374 

Forgetting, 190 

Formation of Vegetable Mould through the 

Action of Worms, 694 
Forster's syndrome, 315-16 
Fragonard, 336 

Frames of reference, 35. 38. 40, 43t 63, 
320 

France, Anatole, 73 

Frankenstein, 256 

Frankenstein monsters, 47 

Franklin, Benjamin, 202-4, 256, 66$, 666, 

685-7 
Free association, 646 

choice, 632-3 
French Revolution, 132 
Freud, S., 32, 55, 59, 86, 139, 153, 159, 166, 

181, 191, 192, 200, 218, 256, 257, 265, 

292, 320, 495. 496 
quoted, 33 
Fringe, 159 
Fry, D. B., 534 
Fry, Roger, 395 * 
Fuchsian functions, 1 14-16 
Full consciousness, 208 
Function, reorganization of, 457-60 
Functional integration, 416, 417 
Fundamentalists, 131 



Gabor, D., 23 
Galambos, R., 513 
Galanter, E., 433 
Galatea, 47 

Galileo, 48, 94, 102, 110, 125, 131, 176, 217, 
228, 236, 239, 240, 256, 265, 507, 662, 
679-83 

Gall, F. J., 215, 234 

Galois, Everist, n 1, 704 

Galton, Sir Francis, 160, 165, 166 

Galvani, Luigi, 667 

Games, parlour, 38-9 
strategy of, 39 

Gastaut, H., 550 

Gauss. K. F., 117-18 

Generalization, learning process, 490 

Genes, 4x8 

Genetic code, 417-19, 421 
Genetics, controversies over, 241 



Genius, corporate orthodoxy the curse of, 
239 

Germ theory, 247 

Gestalt school of psychology, 109, 387, 
432, 497, 560 

ambiguities of, 582 

pitfalls of, 573 et seq. 

theory, 517 
Gibson, J. J., 50 
Gilbert, W., 228, 662, 665 
Gladstone, W. £., 143 
Goethe, 14, 132, 151, 257 
Goldstein, K., 501 

note on, 382 
Golem of Prague, 47 
Gombrich, E. H., 378, 395, 398 
Goose, imprinted, 489 
Gradients, ascending, 390-1 
Grafting operations, 459 
Graves, R M 321 

Gravity, controversy on theory of, 240 

Gray, Asa, 132, 665, 666 

Greek art, 369, 372, 376, 377, 378, 395-6 

Greek science, 675-6 

Grcig,J.Y.T., 32 

Gris, Juan, 374 

Groddcck, 153 

Growth, controlled by genetic code, 432 

Guarini, 335 

Guericke, 665 

Guided learning, 575, 612 

Guilford, Professor, 13 

Gulliuer in Laputa, 257 

Gulliver's Travels, 73 

Gutenberg, J., 121, 163 

Guthrie, E. R., 496, 559 



Habit, 44-5 

and originality, 649 et seq. 
Habit-formation, 155 
Habits, mechanization of, 154-7 
Hadamard, J., 116, 120, 147, 329 

inquiry into working methods of 
mathematicians, 171-2 
Haeckel, Ernst, 250, 342 
Halley, 663, 664 
Hamburger, V., 424 
Hamlet, 345 
Hamman, 173 

Handbook of Psychological Research on the 

Rat, 567 
Handwriting, 552 
Hardy, G. H., 329 



INDEX 



739 



Harlow, H. E, 501, 504 
Harmony of the Spheres, 260, 261 
Harter, N., 432. 544 
Hartmann, E. von, 153 
Harvey, W., 228, 234 
Hauptmann, G., 351 
Hauy, Abbe, 192-3, 707 
Head, Henry, 532, 599, 601 
Hearing, 513 et seq. 

filtering process in, 518-19 

melody, 520-1 

selective control of input, 514-16 
Heath, T. L., 237 

Hebb, D. O., 497, 498, 505, 519, 526, 527, 

538, $6i, $6z % 565, 590, 607, 646 
Hegel, 151 
Heideshain, M., 432 
Heine, H., 89, 90 
Heinroth, O., 491 
Helmholtz, von, 170, 217, 231 
Hemingway, A., 69 
Henry, Joseph, 194 
Herder, 151 
Hermes, 11 
Hero, 102, 109 
Herodotus, 623 
Heron, W., 502 
Herscliel, 614 
Herz, H. R., 671 

Hierarchy, die concept of, 287-91 
Hierarchic levels of consciousness, 632, 
*33 

Hierarchies of environment, 483 

Hierarchies of feedback, 483 

Hilgard, E. R., 496, 500, 556, 559, 562, 

S<S9, 590 
Himmelfarb, G., 139 
Hingston, R. W. G., 486 
Hipparchus, 234 
Hippasos, 215 
Hippocratic 'humours', 48 
Hippocratic Oath, 675 
Hippocratics, 675 
Histoire Natutelle, 131 
History of Art 

discoveries of new techniques, 393—4 

stagnation and cross-fertilization, 395-6 

visual representation, 367-^ 
History of Physics, 664 
History of Science, 224 et seq. 
History of Science, The, 234 
Hixon Symposium, 413, 433 
Hobbes, T., 53, 89, 214, 646 
Hogarth, 72 



Homer, 353 
Homeric laughter, 30 
Homunculus, 47 
Honey-bee, 487, 567 
Hook, Sidney, 176 
Hooked atoms of thought, 164-6 
Horrocks, J., 704 
Horsley, Miss E., 23 
Hoskins, JML, 685 
Housman, A. E., 317, 318, 354 
How Natives Tliink, 624 
Hull, C. L., 497, 499, 500, 557, 559 
Human, perceptual and sensory-motor 
skills, 513 

Human figure, proportions of, note on, 

331-2 
Humorist 

bisociative process of the, 93, 94 

the creative act of the, 94 
Humour 

aggression and, 52, 54, 56, 62 

creation of, 91-3 

defined, 31 

economy in, 84 

emotional dynamics of, 55 et seq. 

identification in, 54 

implication in, 84 

interpolation and extrapolation, 84 

Law of Infolding and, 340 

procedure for dissecting, 64 

riddle in, 85, 86 

technique of implication, 82-4 

transformation, 85 

varieties of, 64 et seq. 

(see also 'Comic technique*, 'Laughter') 
Humphrey, G., 601, 603, 646 
Humphreys, L. G., 499 
Huxley, Aldous, 62 
Huxley, T. H., 144, 213, 214, 218, 233 
Huyghens, 228, 240 
Hyden, H., 23, 519 
Hydra, 451 
Hypnosis, 297 
Hypno-therapy, 297 
Hypnotism in dental surgery, 239 



Icarus, 46 
Ideas 

combination of, 164 
concretizatton of abstract and general, 
179 

evolution of, 224 et seq. 
history of, 21 



740 



INDEX 



Identification 

in literary work, 345-6 

in weeping, 278, 279 

magic and, 308-9 

visual, 527 
17 Saggiatore, 682 
Illusion, 301-10 

and escapism, 306 

cathartic value of, 306 

direct speech and, 310 

dynamics of, 304-9 

identification in, 308 

power of, 301-3 

the value of, 303-4 
Image, 320 et seq. 

concrete, 179 

logical and didactic appeal to intellect, 
325 

Imagery, dependence on emotive poten- 
tials, 321 

Imitation, imprinting and, 489 et seq. 
Imitative bird-song, 491-2 
Impersonation, 56, 90, 179 

benefits of, 187-8 

bisociation of, 68 

parody an aggressive form of, 69 
Implication, the technique of, 84 
Impressionist painting, 398 
Imprinting 

and imitation, 489 et seq. 

defined, 491 

improvisation, musical, 547 
Inducers, 425, 426, 427 
Infolding, 333 et seq. 
Inheritors, The, 168 
Innate behaviour, 477 
Innate releasing mechanism, 478 
Inoculation, 112 
Input, in hearing, 513-16 
Insects, insight and, 565-7 
Insight 

Gestalt use of the term, 582-4 
insects and, 565-7 

not learned but dependent on learning, 
590 

perception of relations, 548 
Insight and Outlook, 11, 22, 149 
Insight learning, 521-3, 576 

characteristics of, 577, 580 

criteria of, 577-9 

preconditions of, 579-82 
Inspirations, false, 212-14 
Instinct 

learning and, 477-8 



sublimation of, 320 
Instinct-behaviour, 475 et seq. 
codes, 478 

cyclic patterns of, 483-4 

genetics of, 476 
Integrations, gradual, 220 
Intellectual illumination, 383 
Intermittent reinforcement, 499 
Introjection, 296 
Intuition 

analogy and, 199-207 

logic and, 1 12-18 
Irony, 73-4 

Irrational numbers, 215 
Island, 73 



Jack-in-the-Box, 46, 49, 90 
Jackson, Hughlings, 432 
Jaensch, E. R., 374 
Jakobson, R., 173 
James, Henry, 265 

James, William, 12, 4,3, 152, 158, 159, 191, 

265, 516, 592, 593 
Janus principle m organic hierarchies, 

467-8 
Jeans, J., 265 
Jenner, Edward, 112, 113 
Jester, 27, 255, 257 
John of Salisbury, 613 
Johnson, Samuel, 30, 366, 401, 707 
Joke, seeing the, 89 
Jonah and the whale, 360-1 
Jones, Ernest, 139, 218 

note on, 507 
Joyce, James, 339. 353 
Jung, C. E., note on, 211 
Jung, C. G., 166, 187, 353, 462, 647 
Juvenal, 72, 505 

Juxtaposition of aspects of experience, 
352 



Kafka's Castle, 73 
Kant, E., 131, 150 
Kantor, W., 244 
Keats, J., 321, 330 

Kekule, F. A. von, 118, 169, 170, 171, 185. 

240, 321 
Keller, Helen, 222, 595 
Kelvin, Lord, 199 
Kepes, G., 388, 389 



INDEX 



741 



Kepler, J., 48, 103, 124, 125, 126, 127, 128, 
I3i» *45> 148, 163. 176, 199, 213, 217. 
220, 228, 234, 237, 260, 261, 265, 290, 
327. 330, 461, 463, 507, 576, 625, 649. 
662, 675, 683-4, 707 
Galileo and, 679 

Kepler's laws, 124-5 

Kinetosomes, 420 

King Solomon's Ring, 48 

Kircher, A., 663 

Kluever, H , S3* 

Knowing and seeing, 527-8 

Koehler, Otto, 492, 535, 599, 623 

Koenigstein, 219 

Koffka, A., 517* 557. 584. 587* 622 
Kohler, Wolfgang, 101, 103, 108, 109, 110, 

220, 266, 492, 504, 517, 554, 55<S. 557. 

5<5o, 573, 575, 577, 578, 579, 581, 583, 

587, 588, 589 
Krechevsky, I., 566, 571 
Kretschmer, E., 168, 265, 322, 323, 325, 

460, 463, 606 
Kruesi, J., 197 
Kubla Khan, 166, 167, 168 



La Ronde, 36 
Laboratory disaster, 192 
Lamarck, 132, 133, 134, 135, 136, 137, 138, 
143 

Lamartine, 150 
Lamb, Charles, 186 
Lancaster, Osbert, note on, 86 
Language 

a thought-crystallizer, 173-7 

note on, 604 

pictorial, 168, 322-5 

snares of, 173 et seq. 

the dawn of, 220-3 

thinking and, 603 
Language matrices, 640-1 
Laplace, 103 

Lashley, K. S., 413, 434, 458, 481, 491, 

552, 554, 609, 636 
Laughing through one's tears, 277 
Laughter, 27 et seq. (See also Comic 
technique, Humour) 
and emotion, 51 et seq. 
and weeping, 271-3 
audible, 29-30 

breathing changes in, 29, 30, 59 
defined, 29 

discharge mechanism, 55 
hinders biological drives, 51 



illustrations of, 32 et seq. 

laboratory experiments, 30 

list of occasions for, 60 

logic of, 32 et seq. 

mechanisms of, 59-61 

muscle contractions in, 29, 30, 59 

Old Testament references to, 52-3 

paradox of, 30-1 

prevents biological drives, 51 

rebellion against habit, 63 

theory of degradation, 53 

weeping and crying contrasted with, 272 
Laughter reflex, 28-30 
Law and order, 325-7 
Lawrence, D. H., 90, 496 
Lawrence, T. E., 67 
Lawrence, W., 534 
Laycock, Sir T , 152 
Le Corbusier, 329 
Le Mire, 32 
Learning 

a bisociative process, 588-90 

ability, differences in, 496-7 

animal, 562-5 

anticipatory behaviour of, 576 
associative, 587 
by trial and error, 576, 577 
criteria of insight, 577-9 
definitions of, 477 
drive-reduction theory, 497, 504 
feedback process in, 491 
guided, 575, 612 
in telegraphy, 544-5 
insight, 576 
instinct and, 477-8 
motivation for, to learn, 506 
motor, 550, 552 
optimum, 496 

perception and memory involved in, 
513 

perceptual, 490 
piano-playing, 546-7 
preconditions of insight, 579-82 
serial, 545 

skills, summarized, 549-54 
stamping in, 577 
symbolic coding, 533 
through play, 509 
to speak, 592 et seq. 
to think, 606 et seq. 
uniform factors in, 575-6 
visual, 526-7 
Learning potentials, reserve surplus of 
needs, 493 



742 



INDEX 



Learning processes, 490 

reversal of hierarchic sequence of opera- 
tions, 547 
Learning theory 

basic differences of psychological schools, 
561-2 

pitfalls of, 556 et seq. 

retrospect, 556-7 
Lee, Vernon, 374 
Leerlauf activities, 484-5 
Leibniz, no, 131, 150, 228, 240 
Lenin, 194 

Leonardo da Vinci, 72, 329, 333. 375* 394 
Leonine verse, 314 
Letter-habit, 551 

in telegraphy, 544 

in touch-typing, 546 
Leverrier, 234 

note on, 254 
Leviathan, 53 

Iivy-Bruhl, L., 293, 309, 624 
Lewin, K., 498 

Leyden jars, 202, 203, 204, 666 

Libido-theory, 496 

Lichtenburg, 150 

Lidice, 297 

Liebig, 240 

Light 

corpuscular theory of, 240 

speed of, 243, 244 

wave-theory of, 240 
Lightning conductor, 202, 203 
Lindauer, M., 487 
Lindsley, D. B., 505 
Linear awareness, 632 
Linnaeus, 131, 132, 228 
Linne\ Carl von, 131, 132 
Linnean Society, 142 
Literature 

archetypal patterns, 353-5. 354~7> 358- 
65 

archetypes, 353-4 

art of, defined, 301 

conflict in novels, 350-2 

dawn of, 309-10 

forgeries, 401 

identification in, 345-6 

puppets and strings, 355-7 

villains in, 351 
Loadstones and amber, 661 et seq. 
Locke, John, 131, 149 
Locomotor actions offish and crab, 438-44 
Locomotor hierarchies, 432-8 
LoebJ„48 



Loewi, Otto, 204-5, 206, 207, 220 
Logic, 625-9 

and intuition, 1 12-18 

limits of, 145-7 

mechanical, 160, 161, 162 

reversal of, 191-9, 464 
Lombroso, 11 
Longitude Found, The, 663 
Longitude Not Found, The, 663 
Longtailed Tits, consummatory acts of, 483 
Lorenz, K. L., 48, 478, 481, 482, 492, 502, 

506, 511, 557 
Lorimer, F., 616 
Lot's wife, 48 

Lotus and the Robot, The, 177 note 
Lucretius, 131 
Ludic, 511-12 

Ludic behaviour, 509 et seq. 
Ludicrous, the, 511-12 
Lysozyme, 194 



McDougall, W., 12, 17, 53, 491, 501 
McGill University, 158 
McGlashan, A., 23 
Mach, Karl, 649 
Machine, man and, 45-9 
Macpherson, James, 401 
Maestlin, 625 
Magic, 626 

identification and, 308-9 

of names, 613-14 

of the stage, 308 

participation in, 294 

primitive and contemporary, 308 

sublimation and, 258-63 

word and symbol, 293 
Magic Mountain, 90 
Magical thinking, 261 
Magician, Benevolent, 255, 256, 257 
Magician Pope, 255 
Magnetism 

and electricity, 661 et seq. 

unification with electricity, 230 
MaiUet, de, 131 
Maimonides, 255 
Maliphant, R., 23 
Mallarme", 337 
Malskat, L., 400, 401 
Malthus, 140, 141, 142, 143, 207 
Mammalia, regeneration in, 451 
Man and animal, bisociation of, 67 
Man and machine, 45-9 



INDEX 



743 



Manet, 69 

Mangold, Hilde, 425 

Manipulation, 558 

Mantras, 313 

Marbe's Law, 644 

Marie, Pierre, 532 

Mariner's compass, 661 

Marquis, the Bishop and the, 33-4, 56, 92 

Mars, orbit of, 128 

'Martyrdom of St. Sebastian', 386-7 

Marx, Groucho, 61 

Marx, K., 694 

Maskelyne, 230 

Masochist, 65 

Mass-psychology, 297 

Mathematical games, 91 

Math.ematkia.ri s Apology, 329 

Mathematicians 

aesthetic feeling of, 329 

dependence on irrationalities, 147 
Mathematics, 621-5 

abstraction of individual numbers, 622 

counting, 623 

discovery a bisociative act, 164 

intuitionists v formalists, 241 

learned in explicit verbal form, 637 

matching, 623, 624 

number concept, 622, 623 

thought processes, 39, 40 
Matrices, 38, 44, 66, 76, 96, 221, 222, 424, 
431, 471-3, 490-1, 524, 592, 640-1, 
642 et seq., 654, 656 et seq., 705 

and codes, note on, 50 

any two can produce a comic effect, 66 

bisociation of incompatible, 59, 220 

blocked, 224-5 

collision of, 45 

dual control of, 415 

emotive potential of, 321 

flexibility of auditory-vocal, 492 

language, 640-1 

of verbal thought, 38 
Matrix 

defined, 38 

note on term, 50 

remedy for a blocked, 163 
Mau-Mau oath, 294 
Maximts et Pensies, 53 
Maxwell, James Clerk, 230, 258, 265, 669, 
670, 671, 687. 688-92, 704, 705, 706, 
708 

Mayer, Robert, 239 
Measure and meaning, 312-14 
Mechanical encrusted on the living, 46 



Mechanical logic, 160, 161 

interference with, 162 
Mechanisms, physiological, 48 
MechnikofF, E., 199 
Medium, artist's, 333-4 
Meister, Josef, 114 
Melody, tracing a, 520-1 
Melville, H., 361 
Memory 

analysing-devices, 524-6 

association, 538-9 

auditory, 533-5 

discrimination, 537 

generalization of input, 537 

images, 531-3 

in all learning processes, 576 

levels of, 528-31 

perception and, 513 et seq. 

photographic, 529 

picture-strip recall, 524-6, 530, 531 

recognition and recall, 539-41 

related to auditory perception, 518-19 
Memory-formation, 347, 348 

parsimony in, 523 
Memory-systems, hierarchy of, 523 
Mendel, note on, 254 
Mental evolution, 226 
Mental scanning, comparison with visual 

161 
Mentality 

difference between primitive and 

modern, 626 
tribal, 308 

Mentality of Apes, The, 101, 504, 560, 579* 

582, 583 
Mesmer, 239 256 
Messenger UNA, 419 
Metaphors, 167, 320, 321 
Metaphysics, Maxwell and, 688-92 
Metric patterns, 314 
Michelson, 243 
Microbiology, 194 
Midsummer Nighfs Dream, A, 53, 172 
Miller, D. C, 244, 433* 443, 499 

note on, 254 
Milton, J., 674 
Minkovsky, 175 

Misadventure, discovery by, 192 et seq. 
Mispronunciation, bisociation and, 76-7 
Mitochondria, 420 
Mitty, Walter, 179 
Mnemic processes, 528-31 
Moby Dick, 361 

Molecular constitution, theory of, 169-70 



744 



INDEX 



Molecules, theories on structure of 

organic, 240 
Momentary regressions, 169 
Mondrian, 389, 390 
Monotony, 551 
Montaigne, 14S 

Morgan, Lloyd, 145, 513, 559. 5<5o 
Morphogenesis 

axial gradients in, 455 

specialization in, 423 
Morphogenetic fields, 423, 424 
Motif, in Art, 372-3 
Motivation, 495 et seq., 635 

Aristotle on, 675-6 

by expectancy, 497, 500 

for learning, 506 

in embryonic development, 476 

negative type, 495 et seq. 

secondary drives, 497, 500 

summary of psychologists' views on, 
495-8 

Motivational drive in scientists, 675 
Motor activities 
controlled and modified by the CNS, 
447 

independence of, 444 
Motor-car, driving a, 469-70 
Motor learning, 550, 552 
Motor-patterns, self-assertive tendencies 
of, 552 

Motor reflexes, in laughter, 30-1 

Motor responses, lowering of in emergency 

reactions, 57 
Motor skills, 544 et seq. 
automatization of, 632 
complex 
emergency-reorganizations in, 554 
verbal symbolism and learning, 599 
Moulin, L., 703 

Mountains like White Elephants, 339 

Mourning, as reason for weeping, 274-6 

Mowrer, O. H., 495 

Mueller, Johann, 704 

Multiple potential, 706 

Munn, N. L., 567 

Muscles 

functioning of, 435-7 

selective response of, 442 
Music, 3I3-I4. 515 et seq. 

aesthetic appreciation, 385-6 

composing, 547 

reversability in, 198 
Musical phrase, in piano-playing, 546 
Myers, P. W. H., 69, 152 



Mysteries of nature, 260 
Mysterium Cosmographicum, 125 

Name and Nature of Poetry, The, 435 
Names, magic of, 613-14 
Napier's logarithms, 625 
Narcissus, 48 

Natural selection, Darwin and, 131-44 
Nature, looking at, 366-9 
Nature of Explanation, The, 506 
Ncedham, J., 426, 432, 467 
Neo-Behaviourists, 561 
Neoplatonists, 131, 148 
Nerve-impulses, Chemical transmission of, 
204-7 

Nervous system, 426, 427 

control on growth completion, 432 

development of the, 430-2 

super flexibility of functions, 459 
Neumann, J. von, 32 
Neurology, reflex-formula and, 498 
Neurophysiology, 231 

and exploratory drive, 505, 506 

controversy, 241 
New Astronomy Based on Causation or 
Physics of the Sky, A, 124, 128, 129, 
217, 234. 265 
New Landscape, The, 388 
New Yorker, 37, 85 
Newton, Alfred, 144 
Newton, Eric, 388, 394, 395 
Newton, Sir I., 69, no, 124, 131, 176, 200, 
228, 240, 256, 290, 663, 684-5, 708 

first Law of Motion, 237 
Nicolas of Cusa, 260 
NicoUe, Charles, 257 
Nicolson, Marjorie, 674 
Nietzsche, 153 
Night journey, 358-60 
1984, 90 

Nissen, H. W., 502 
Noise, 514 

Non-representational art, 370 
Nonsense humour, bisoriation of, 78 
Nordau, ix 

Normal conditions, defined, 449 

Norris, John, 149 

Note habit, in piano-playing, 546 

Novel, conflict, 350-2 

Nucleus, action of cytoplasm on, 422 

Number-concepts, 622 

individual, 622-3 

personalized, 623 
Numbers, irrational, 2x5 



INDEX 



745- 



Objective verifiability, 28 
Oceanic feeling, 88, 260, 263, 
Oceanic wonder, 327, 328, 634 
Oedipus Rex, 355 
Oedipus story, 32, 35, 68 
Oersted, H. C, 230, 668 
Oistrakh, D., 59, 60 
Old Testament 
quoted, 323 

references to laughter, 52-3 
On Growth and Form, 466 
On the Face in the Disc of the Moon, 237 
On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, 

i*5» 677 
Ontogenesis, 451 
Operant behaviour, 496^499 
Operators, 419 
Optical pun, 179, 182 
Optical realism, 585 
Optics, 131 

Order, law and, 325-7 
Organelles, 420 

Organic life governed by rules, 631 

Organisms 
adaptations, 448, 450 
code for making, 417 et seq. 
function of nervous system, 506 
incentive to exploratory activities, 507 
not masses reacting to environment, 
498 

regenerative span of, 450-2 

super-flexibility of, 450 
Organization 

perceptual, 587 

principles of, 467 et seq. 
Organizers, 425 

Origin and Nature of the Emotions, The, 285 
Origin of Spedes, The, 132, I34» I35» 142, 

707 
Originality 

and emphasis, 333-5 

criteria distinguishing routine from, 654 

degrees pf, 654-7 

forgetting a prerequisite of, 190 

habit and, 44-5, 649 et seq. 
Orphic mysticism, 260 
Orthodox, pitfalls of, 639 
Orwell, George, 67, 73. 323 
Osgood, C. E., 559, 568, 644 
Ossian, 401 
Othello, 33, 56 
Over-learning, 551 

Overshooting characteristic of evolution, 
493 



Over-statements of the body, 58 



Paget, Sir, R_, 534 

Painter, engaged in learning to see, 507 

Pantheon, 11 

Papageno, 61 

Paracelsus, 148, 256 

Paradox, the humorist and, 93-4 

Paradoxes, logical, 91 

Paranormal conditions, 449 

Parasympathetic reactions, 305 

Parasympathetic system, 274 

Parody, bisociation in, 69-70 

Parrot-talk, 491-2 

Parsimony, Principle of, 495 

Participation, Law of, 293 

Participatory tendencies, 54 

Pascal, 103, 228, 704 

Pasteur, Louis, 112, 113, 114, 145, 200, 225, 
241, 256, 261, 696-702, 707 

germ theory, 247 

study of crystallography, 193 
Pathology of thought, 235-40 
Pattern-learning, 522 

Pavlov, I. P., 498, 504. 505, 557, 57«, 584, 
6x1, 628 

Pavlov's dogs 563-4, 565, 580, 582 
Pendulum problem, 189-90 
Penfield, W., 597, 599, 601, 602 
Penicillin, 194 
Perception 

and memory, 513 et seq. 

conditioning and insight in, 521-2 

of relations, 548 

of sound patterns, 533 
Perceptual codes, 347, 348, 376-80 

learning, 490 

organization, 587 

projection, 295, 373 
Peregrine, Peter, 227, 661 
Peripheral awareness, 159, 180 
Personal equation, 231 
Perspective, 374 
Persuaders, hidden, 42-4 
Phagocytes, 199 
Philosophic Zoologique, 138 
Philosophy of the Unconscious, 153 
Phoenix of Astronomy, 678 
Phonetic matrices, 640 
Phonograph, 197 
Photography, 195 
Photosynthesis, 420 
Phrase-habit, 551 



74<S 



INDEX 



Phrenology, 215 
Physical causality, 584 
Physics, science of 
reasons for delay in emergence of true, 
236 

synthesis with Astronomy, 124 
Physiological isolation, 452-3 

creativity and, 463 
Physiological regeneration, 451 
Piaget, J., 292, 585, 596, 598, 614, 627 
Piano-playing, 42, 551, 552 

learning habits in, 546-7 
Picasso, 71, 92, 120, 402 

and the 'fakes', 82, 84 
Pictorial thinking, 168, 322-5 
Picture postcards, 383-5 
Picture-strip language, 606 
Picture-strip recall, 524-6, 530, 531 
Pigment, 370-1 
Place-learning, 545 
Planck, Max, 147, 213 
Platner, E., 151 
Plato, 12, 131 
Plato's Cave, 73 
Play 

definitions o£ 509-10 

learning through, 509 et seq. 
Play of ideas, 65-6 
Pleasure* derivation of, 495 
Pledge, H. T., 228 
Plotinus, 148 
Plots, 345, ct seq. 

cataloguing, 354-5, 355-7 
Plutarch, 237 
Poet 

element of explorer inherent, 507 
imagery produced by metaphor, 167, 
320 

Poetic inspiration, 3*5 
Poetry, learning, 521 

Poincare\ Henri, 145, *47» 164, 165, 166, 
2ii, 212, 334, 329. 330 
discovery of Fuchsian functions, 114-16 
Pointillist, 376 

Poiinyi, M., 23, 159, 242-3, 244> 464. 564, 
58$ 

Political cartoon, 70 
lolya, G., IT7» 650, 652 
Polyp, 45t 

marine, 456 
Popper, K. R., 176, 246 
Practicality and abstraction, 705-6 
Pre-coascLous state, 152, 159 
Pribram, K. H„ 433 



Priestley, Joseph, 204 
Principa, 663 

Principle of Cotttemplementary, 198 
Principles of Cestalt Psychology, 517 
Pringle.J. W. S., 519 
Printing-press, 12 1-4 
Probability, theory of, 103 
Problem-solving, 635, 649 et seq. 
Problems 

routine of solving, 651 

searching for a code, 652-4 

solution by analytical method, 650 

solving by synthetic method, 650 
Projective empathy, 296, 374, 386, 387 
Prometheus, 11 
Proteins, 418 
Proust, 312 
Provisional tries, 571 
Pseudo-proverb, 79 
Psychoanalysis, 188 
Psychological field theory, 498 
Psychology 

and motivation, 495 et seq. 

educational, 17 

fashion in, 248 

new orientation, 498 et seq. 

self-transcending emotions and* 285 et 
seq. 

Psychology from the Standpoint of Behaviour- 
ist, 557 

Psychology of Laughter and Comedy, 32 
Psycho-physical isomorphism theory, 588 
Psychoses, hallucinatory, 324 
Psychotherapy, 188, 242 
aims of, 465 

free-association method, 631 

regeneration and, 461 
Ptolemy, X28, 234 
Puerperal fever, 239 
Pulsation, 311-12 
Pun, 77, 179 

bisociation of single phonetic form with 
two meanings, 64-5 

optical, 182 

sound amnity, 314, 315 
Punch and Judy, 48, 49 
Punning, 186-7 

compulsive, 315-16 
Punning mania, 65 
Purchases Pilgrimage, 166, 168 
Pure consciousness, 635 
Puzzle box, cat in, S68-70 
Pygmalion, 47 
Pyke, M., 227 



INDEX 



747 



Pythagoras, m, 191, 255 

discovery of musical pitch, 11 1, 191 
Pythagorean revival and Shakespeare, 674 
Pythagorean Scale, 260 
Pythagoreans, 48, 215, 227, 259-60, 675 



Quantum mechanics, 245 
Quantum physics, 199 
Quixote, Don, 46 



Raptness, as reason for weeping, 273-4 

Rationality of nature, 686 

Rats, experiments with, 458-9, 500, 502, 

520, 556, 5S8, 567-8 
Reading, 534 
Reason, emotions and, 56 
Reasoning, unconscious processes and, 163 
Reasoning skills, 40 
Recall, 539-41 
Receptors, 435 
Red Queen, 629 
Reflex 

defined, 28-9, 499 

laughter, 28 et seq. 
Reflex arc, 498 
Reflexes, twin, 62 
Regeneration 

axial gradients in, 455-6 

creativity and, 463-5 

evolution and, 465-6 

pychotherapy and, 461 
Regenerations 

routine, 457 

structural, 454-5 
Regenerative equilibrium, 454 
Regenerative span, 450-2 
Regiomontanus, 704 
Regression 

of poetic inspiration, 315, 3x6 

value of, 173 
Regressions, momentary, 169 
Reik, T., 188 

Relativity, Theory of, 183, 243-tf 

discovery of principle of, 11 1, 175-6 
Relevance, 625 

Relief, as reason for weeping, 276-8 
Religion, scientists and, 260-3 
Rembrandt, 69, 328 
Renan, Ernest, 147, 261 
Renoir, 554 

Repetition of syllables, 314 



Repressed complexes, 181 
Repressors, 419 
Responses, 499 

Reticular activating system, 505 
Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, 217 
Rhyming, 314 
Rhythm 

and rhyme, 311 et seq. 

Law of Infolding and, 340-1 
Rhythmic periodicities, 313 
Ribot, T. A., 32 
Richards, I. A., 311, 340 
Richardson, O. W„ 230 
Richter, Jean-Paul, 151 
Riddle, 85, 86 

Riddles of the Universe, The, 250 
Richmann, M., 204 
Ripeness, 144, 145 

for discovery, 108 et seq. 
RNA, 427, 455 
Roberts, L., 601 
Rock-n'-Roll, 311 
Rohrschach, 375, 376 
Rohrschach test, 538 
Romeo and Juliet, 68 
Rontgen, W. K., 195 
Root and the flower, the, 362-3 
Rosalind, 68 
Rosenthal, R-, 568 
Rosetta stone, 90, 186 
Royal Society, X32 
Ruch, T. C, 443. 553 
Ruskin, 395 

Russell, Bertrand, 200, 251, 262, 265, 556, 

567, 586, 5$7» 606 
Rutherford, 176, 671 



Sadist, 65 
Sage, 27, 255 

Saint-Hilaire, GeofFroy, 132. 133 
St. Thomas Aquinus, 148, 228, 255 
St. Vitus's dance, 311 
Salamander, 426, 430 
normal function of transplanted limb, 
457 

regeneration of eye lens, 456 
regeneration of lost limb, 454 

Saxnmelweiss, Ignaz, 239, 240 

Sancho, 38 

Sandemanians, 688 

Sarsi, Father, 240 

Sarton, George, 224 

Satire, 72-4 



748 



INDEX 



Scanning 

objects and rules of the process, 162 

visual and mental, 158 et seq. 
Schilling, 151 
Schiller, F., 257, 318 
Schizophrenic symbols, 324 
Schopenhauer, 36, 354 
SchrSdinger, Erwin, 245, 26,5 
Science 

boredom of, 263-6 

boundaries of, 248-52 

emotion and, 255 et seq. 

fashions in, 246-8 

history of, see Science, History of 

hypnotism and, 239 

Law of Infolding and, 342-3 

martyrology of, 239 

orthodoxy and, 238, 239 

progress towards universal laws, 352 

relationship with art, 27, 28 

religion and, 261-2 

religious mysticism and, 260-1 

'river-delta' pattern of progress, 352 

words as tools and traps for, 176 
Science, history of, 224 et seq. 

controversies, 240 

impact of religion and politics, 238, 239 

neither continuous, nor cumulative, 253 

twenty-six centuries of, 227-8 
Science and Human Behaviour, 17, 556, 557 
Scientific evidence, 242 
Scientific Revolution, 260 

leaders of, 677-84 
Scientists 

abstraction and practicality, 705-6 

and the infinite, 261-3 

bisociation and, 72 

catharsis of problems, 328 

destruction of the self-evident, 176-7 

discovery and, 190 (see also Discovery) 

intellectual characteristics of, 703-8 

irrationality in, 146 

motivational drive, 675 

multiple potential, 706-8 

precodousness of, 703-4 

religion and, 260-3 

the Benevolent Magicians, 255-6 

the creative and his audience, 263-6 

the Mad Professors, 256 

the uninspired Pedant, 256-7 

the White Magician, 257-8 

-visual imagery and, 169-73 
Scott, SirW., 211 

Screening activity in hearing, 513 et seq. 



Selection, 333 
Selective emphasis, 397 
Self-amputation in animals, 451 
Self-assertive tendencies, 255, 257, 259, 
305 

in humour, 52, 56, 57, 95 

in organic hierarchy, 449 

of part-behaviour, 468 

sublimation of, 259 
Self-awareness, degrees of, 633-5 
Self-pity as reason for weeping, 280 
Self-transcendence, 303 

voluntary, 294 
Self-transcending emotions, 54, 258, 263, 
285, 298, 305, 328 

in weeping, 273-4 

sublimation of, 261 
Semantic differentials, 644 
Semon, R., 531 
Sense of wonder, 674 et seq. 
Sensory gratification, difference from 

aesthetic satisfaction, 385 
Seurat, 174, 329 
Sex-drive, 496 
Sexual tension, 496 
Shaftesbury, Earl of, 150 
Shakespeare, 148 
Shaw, G. B., 47, 120 
Shelley, P. B., 321 

Sherrington, Sir Charles, 28, 432, 498 
Sign-learning theory, 497 
Simplification, 333 
Skill 

autonomous and automatic functioning, 

550-1 
balancing, 548 

complex, assertive tendencies of, 552 

dual control in exercise of, 38 

hierarchic structure of complex, 288-9 

morphogenic, 415 

motor, 544 et seq. 

perceptual, 489 et seq. 
hearing, 513 et seq. 

prenatal, 415 et seq. 

vegetative, 415 
Skinner, B. F., 157, 496, 499, 500, 556, 

557, 559 
Skinner Box, 248 
Sleepwalkers, The, 11 
Smiling, facial changes in, 29 
Smithers, D. W. f 456 
Smoke micrographs, 389, 390 
Snobbery, the aesthetics of, 400 et seq. 
'Snowblindness* of thinkers, 216-20 



INDEX 



749 



Soccer, 552 

techniques of playing, 549 
Sound affinity, association by, 314-15 
Souriau, 145 
Space and Time, 174-5 
Speak, learning to, 592 et seq. 
Spearman, C, 177 
Speech 

action-words of children, 606-7 
childhood aspects of, 594-6 
concepts and labels in, 597-9 
dawn of symbol consciousness, 594-6 
direct, in illusion, 310 
ideation and verbalization in, 600-3 
memory and, 533-5 
motor activity precedes sensory control, 
594 

preparation before, 592-3 

verbal behaviour in, 593-4 
Spencer, Herbert, 55, 69, 432 
Spid&r, code of rules in building web, 38 
Spinoza, 650, 651 
Sponges, 451 

Spontaneous activities, 468 
S-R Theories, 561-2 
Stamping-in, 521, 522, 549-50 
Steam engine, 102, 109 
Stein, Gertrude, 433 

Stickleback, reproductive behaviour of, 479 
Stimuli, 499 

Strategy, related to skill, 38 
Structural differentiation, 416, 417 
Studies on the Telegraphic Language, 544 
Stutterers, bisociation of, 74 
Style, artistic, 334-5, 336-7 
Style codes, 640-1 
Sublimation, magic and, 258-63 
Subliminal self, 164 
Subsidiary awareness, 159 
Sullivan, Miss, 222 
Sully, J., 29 
Super-ego, 65 

Suzuki, D. T., note on, 177 
Swift, Dean, 73, 252, 257 
Swinburne, 322 
Sylvester II, 255 

Symbolism, concretization and, 182-6 
Symbolist movement, 337 
Sympathico-adrenal system, 57. 59> 62, 88, 
280, 305 

Sympathy as reason for weeping, 278-9 
Syntheses, premature 

Keplerian cosmology, 215 

things and numbers, 2x5 



Tattered, 133 
Taste, 385-7 
Taton, R., 234 

Technical communications, 265 
Telegraphy, 551 

learning processes in, 544-5 
Telepathy, 188 

Tension, unpleasurable, 496 et seq. 

Thacker, L. A., 506 

Theophrastus, 664 

Theorizing, derivation of term, 260 

Thinking 

abstraction of pre-verbal concepts, 
607-10 

application of the term 'code', 638 
associative, 635 
causality, 615-18 

concretization of relation between 

words and things, 613-14 
dimensional variables, 630-1 
directive, 635 
discrimination in, 610-iz 
explanation, nature of, 618 
in pictures, 168, 322-5 
logic, 625-9 
magical, 261 

master-switches and releasers, 635-7 

mathematical, 39, 40, 621-5 

multi-dimensional, 630-2 

not a linear process, 159 

physiological aspect of, 57-8 

pictorial, 167, 168 

recognition and transfer, 611-13 

rules and codes, 637-41 

single plane, 35, 36 

some aspects of, 630 et seq 

steps in purposive, 163 

underground, 178 et seq. 

verbal, 38-9, 43 

visual, 347-8 
Thinking— an experimental and Social Study, 

quoted, 231 
Thinking aside, 14s et seq., 182 
Thompson, d'Arcy, 466 
Thompson, J. J,, 671 
Thompson, W. R. 502 
Thorndike, E. L., 495, 5°4, 557, 568, 569* 
570. 586 

Thorpe, W. H., 450, 477. 478. 483, 49*. 

492, 493, 506, 5", 548, 5^2, 565, 5$7 
Thought 

abdication of conceptual, 170 

hooked atoms of, 164-6 



750 



INDEX 



Thought — cont. 

influence of unconscious processes on, 
159 et seq. 

laws of, 628 

matrices of, 38 et seq. 

matrix of verbal, 38-9, 43 

pathology of, 235-40 

rules in disciplined, X78 

verbal, specific patterns of, 636-7 
Thought processes, mathematical, 39, 40 
Tickling, bisociation of, 79 
Tillyard, E. M. W., 674 
Time, Space and, 174-5 
Tinbergen, N., 415. 433. 449, 45C 475. 
481, 482, 506, 557. 565. 566 

hierarchic control of instinct-activity, 
478-80 

Tolman, E. C, 497, 500, 561, 570, 571 

Tolstoy, L., 339 

Tools 

discovery of, 101-3 

making of, 103-5, 573 

use of, 573 
Total matrix, 641 
Touch-typing, 545 

Towns with M (parlour game), 162, 643-4 
Tragedy, 304 

cathartic function of, 307 
Tragic and trivial planes, 358 et seq. 
Traite de Mineralogie, 193 
Transfer, 611 
Transference, 296 

Transmutation of chemical elements, 2x5 

Transparency of language, 155 

Trans-substantiation, 294 

Trauma, 449 
factors leading to regenerative or patho- 
logical changes, 456 

Travels on the Amazon and Rio Negro, 141 

Treatise on Paintings, 375 

Trial and error learning, 576, 577 

Tribal mentality, 308 

Triptych, 27, 28, 46, 47, 48, 54, 88, 89, 91. 
455 

Tri-valency of creative activity, 45 
Trivial Plane, 363-364, 365 
True play, 509-10 
Truth 

a function of beauty, 331 

and beauty, 327-31 
Tucker, Abraham, 152 
Tumours, due to physiological isolation, 

45«. 
Tune, 530 



Turgenev, 318 
Twist, the, 311 

Tycho de Brahe, 127, 128, 131, 213, 240, 

249, 256, 662, 678 
Tyndall, John, 690 
Type-casting, 123 
Typing, 55* 

learning processes in, 544, 545-6 

stamping-in, 550 

Unconscious 
an automaton, 164 
coaxing the, 317-19 
concept of the, 147-54 
forgetting and the, 190 
thinking in pictures, 168, 322-5 
two-way traffic with conscious, 18 1-2 

Unconscious Before Freud, The, 148 

Unconscious cerebration, 152 

Unconscious guidance, theory of nature of, 
164 

Unconscious understanding, 6x9 
Understanding, gradations of, 6x9-20 
Unified Field Theory, 251 
Unity-in-diversity, 387 
Unity-in-variety, 388, 390 
Universe, 260-1, 662 

Aristotelian system, 237 

classic example of mental block, 236 

Copernician, 94, 125, 216-17, 234, 677 

Einstein's, 244-45, 260, 262 

expanding and steady-state controversy, 
241 

Kepler and the, 103, 124-30, X76, X99, 
213, 217, 237, 261, 290, 677, 679, 684 

Newtonian, 175, 245, 685 

Ptolemaic system, 677 
Universes of discourse, 38, 40 
Uranus, 6x4 
Usher, Bishop, 685 

Vaccination, x 12-14 
Valery, Paul, 317 
van Helmont, 663 
van Megeeren, 401 
Van't Hoff, 240 

Variations of Animals and Plants under 

Domestication, 137, 139 
Verbal ability, note on, 605 
Verbal behaviour, 593—4 

in speeches, 593 
Verbal creation, 301 et seq. 
Verbal models, 634 
Verbal symbolism, 594-6 



INDEX 



751 



Verbal thought 

among mathematicians, 172-3 

matrix on, 38-9* 43 

specific patterns of, 635-7 

value of regression from, 173 
Verne, Jules, 256 
Verse, 313 

nonsense, bisociation of exalted and 
trivial, 78-9 
Vesalius, 265 
Vestiges of Creation, 132 
Virgil, 146 
Vision 

limits of focal, 158 

non-existence of static, 158 

note on, 50 
Visual constancies, 43, 373, 515 
Visual creation, 366 et seq. 
Visual imagery, scientist's and, 16*9-73 
Visual inferences in Art, 373-d 
Visual input, in piano-playing, 547 
Visual learning, 526-7 
Visual perception, reversibility in, 192 
Visual scanning, 158 et seq. 

comparison with mental scanning, 161 
Visual thinkers, 348 
Visual thinking, 183 
Vogue, 36 
Volta, 667 

Voltaic battery, 667, 668 
von BertalanfFy. L., 432, 448 
von Hoist, E., 435. 438 
Voodoo-dancers, 311 
Vulcan, ii 



Wallace, A. R., 137. Ui. 142, 143. 207 

690 
Wallis, C, 23 
Walter, G., 49 

Warden's maze experiment, 598-9 
Wasps, 476, 486, 566 
Waterston, J. J., note on, 254 
Watson, J. B., 12, 13, 220, 496, 504, 507* 

557. 558, 559, 594. 6x0 
Watson-Crick model, 4x7 
Watt, James, 69 
Webster, D. L., 669 
Weeping, 299 

comparison with crying, 271-2 

psychology of, 271 et seq. 

reasons for, 273-82 
Weiss, Paul, 433. 435, 44©. 44L 44*. 443. 
444, 506, $19 



Wellington, Duke of, quoted, 44 

Wells, H. G., 60, 174, 256, 383 

Wernicke, C, 533 

Whale, Jonah and the, 360-1 

White Magician, 257 

White Queen, 77-78, 629 

Whitehead, A. N., 251, 265 

Whyte, L. L., 148, 151, 153. 177. 260 

Wiesner, Norbcrt, 177 

Wilde, Oscar, 77. 79. 85, 92 

Wilkes, John, 36 

Wilson chamber, 249 

Wine-press, 163 

Wit 

malicious, 92 

note on, 50 
Wit and its Relations to the Unconscious, 32 
Wittgenstein, L., 177 
Witticism, 64-7 

derivation of term, 28 
Wolff, Christian, 150 
Wollberg, L. R., 375 
Woodger, J. H., 432 

Woodworth, R. S„ 173, 448, 481. 505. 

544. 562, 600, 647 
Wonder, sense of, 674 et seq. 
Wonderful Century, The, 690 
Word-association tests, 39-40, 636, 637 

code for, 39 
Word-associationist school, X61 
Word-habit, 551 

in telegraphy, 544 
Words 

as tools and traps, 176 

snaring of scientific thought by, 175 
Wordsworth, W., 152 
Wright, Almroth, 707 
Writing, economy in, 339 
Wundt, W., 153 

Xerxes, 623 
X-rays, 195 
Xylographs, 121 

Yang and Yin, 199 
Yeasts, 699 

Yeats, W. B., 312, 341, 362, 674 
Yoga, 634. 635 
Young, Thomas, 672 

Zen Buddhism, 157; note on, 177 
Zen painting, 376. 377 
Zygote, 425. 428 



* 4* 

"Arthur^ Koestler's immense and splendid work may it- 
self be regarded as a creative act . . . Mr. Koestler is ex- 
cellent and very illuminating on the real history of 
ideas . . -Kathleen nott, commentary 



"A big day in the history of the human mind. Arthur 
Koestler has published an enormous book ... which, at a 
leap, has done much to make sense of that mystery of 
mysteries, genius." -peter lewis, London daily mail 

"...a valuable compendium of psychological and scien- 
tific information for the layman." -Elizabeth janeway, 

SATURDAY REVIEW 

"... learned, ingenious, amusing, and altogether remark- 
ably stimulating . . . written with admirable skill . . ." . 

—VICTOR LANGE, THE NEW REPUBLIC 

jn this future classic, which was recommended reading 
for all freshmen entering Radcliffe College in 1965, 
Ai^hdrlCo^jitler argues that the scientist's insight is simi- 
lar to the artist's act of creation, and that they share 
certain psychological conditions. Examining the common 
factors in scientific, artistic, and comic creations, he 
gives examples from psychology, Eastern mysticism, 
biology, and literature which yield "the moment of truth" 
in the creator's achievement. Discussing the nature of 
genius, he defines the process by which ability evolves 
into a completed work, and finds similarities to the-crea- 
tive process throughout the entire animal kingdom. A 
permanently rewarding book for all students of psychol- 
ogy, philosophy, and literature, as well as future and con- 
temporary scientists. 



PRINTED IN U.S.A.